Results for ' moral subjectivism'

988 found
Order:
See also
  1. Moral Subjectivism vs. Moral Objectivism.Seungbae Park - 2022 - Filosofija. Sociologija 3 (33):269–276.
    Moral subjectivism is not self-defeating, contrary to what moral objectivists claim. Ockham’s Razor favors moral subjectivism over moral objectivism. It is circular for moral objectivists to say that since we construct sound and cogent arguments out of moral statements, moral statements are true. Moral subjectivism acknowledges the role that arguments play in our moral lives, contrary to what moral objectivists contend. The way in which moral objectivists (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Moral Subjectivism.H. W. B. Acton - 1948 - Analysis 9 (1):1 - 8.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  9
    Moral Subjectivism.H. B. Acton - 1948 - Analysis 9 (1):1-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  25
    Moral Subjectivism: Dr. Ewing's Method.H. B. Acton - 1949 - Analysis 9 (4):57.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  11
    Moral subjectivism and the semantics of disagreements.Vitor Sommavilla - 2023 - Filosofia Unisinos 24 (3):1-11.
    In this paper, I discuss which semantic theory moral subjectivists should adopt. Moral subjectivism is understood broadly to include all theories according to which moral sentences are truth-apt, at least sometimes true, and made true by the mental attitudes of certain relevant agent or set of agents. Due to the breadth of this definition, an initial concern is whether a unified semantic approach is able to accommodate all varieties of subjectivism. I argue that it is. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  48
    Moral Subjectivism: Dr. Ewing's Method.H. B. Acton - 1948 - Analysis 9 (4):57 - 58.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Does moral subjectivism rest on a mistake?Philippa Foot - 2000 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 46:107-.
    I have asked that this article should be reprinted in the volume dedicated to Elizabeth Anscombe because it in particular reflects throughout my great indebtedness to her. I remember, as long ago as the late 1940s confidently referring to ‘the difference between descriptive and evaluative reasoning’ in one of the many discussions that we began to have from that time on. She, genuinely puzzled, simply asked, ‘What do you mean?’.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  8.  49
    Moral Subjectivism: A Further Reply to Prof. H. B. Acton.A. C. Ewing - 1949 - Analysis 10 (1):15 - 16.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  72
    Moral Subjectivism: Reply to Prof. Acton.A. C. Ewing - 1948 - Analysis 9 (2):17-23.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  9
    Was Smith A Moral Subjectivist?Kevin Quinn - 2019 - Economic Thought 8 (1):30.
    This paper challenges the commonly held view that Smith's moral theory is a subjectivist theory. Smith's test for goodness and rightness – for propriety – is not the approbation of an impartial spectator, but the warranted approbation of such a spectator. Something is right or good not because an impartial spectator would approve of it, but because such a spectator would be warranted in so approving....
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Liberalism and Moral Subjectivism.Edward Andrew - 2001 - In Ronald Beiner & W. J. Norman (eds.), Canadian Political Philosophy: Contemporary Reflections. Oxford University Press. pp. 363.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  46
    Hutcheson's Perceptual and Moral Subjectivism.Elizabeth S. Radcliffe - 1986 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 3 (4):407 - 421.
  13. Moral Overridingness and Moral Subjectivism.Seana Valentine Shiffrin - 1999 - Ethics 109 (4):772-794.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14. The Island Has Its Reasons: Moral Subjectivism in Fiction.Kasandra Barker - 2016 - Dialogue 55 (2):121-124.
    Tamar Gendler takes on “explaining our comparative difficulty in imagining fictional worlds that we take to be morally deviant” (56), otherwise known as the puzzle of imaginative resistance. Generally speaking, readers have no trouble believing untrue factual claims such as in Alice in Wonderland or The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn, but we resist claims which advocate praise or approval of immoral acts such as murder. Gendler submits that the implied author aims to persuade the reader to change his or her (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Expressivism, Subjectivism and Moral Disagreement.Sebastian Köhler - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):71-78.
    One worry about metaethical expressivism is that it reduces to some form of subjectivism. This worry is enforced by subjectivists who argue that subjectivism can explain certain phenomena thought to support expressivism equally well. Recently, authors have started to suggest that subjectivism can take away what has often been seen as expressivism's biggest explanatory advantage, namely expressivism's ability to explain the possibility of moral disagreement. In this paper, I will give a response to an argument recently (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16.  18
    Moral Inquiry Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism.Belén Pueyo-Ibáñez - 2021 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 35 (2):165-175.
    There is a shared feeling among those familiar with pragmatism that, if applied in practice, the teachings of Peirce, James, Dewey, and their heirs could prove extraordinarily helpful in our current uncertain times—times of persistent moral disagreements and almost irreparable social conflicts. But to what extent is this feeling justified? What is the nature of these infelicitous circumstances? And, what makes pragmatism such a suitable approach? In this article, I claim that the main reason behind the ineffectiveness with which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Subjectivist cosmopolitanism and the morality of intervention.Edward Song - 2010 - Journal of Social Philosophy 41 (2):137-151.
    While cosmopolitans are right to think that state sovereignty is derived from individuals, many cosmopolitan accounts can be too demanding in their expectations for illiberal regimes because they do not account for the attitudes of the persons with who will subject to the intervention. These ‘objectivist’ accounts suggest that sovereignty is wholly a matter of a state’s conformity to the objective demands of justice. In contrast, for ‘subjectivist’ accounts, the attitudes of citizens do matter. Subjectivist cosmopolitans do not deny the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  53
    Utility, Subjectivism and Moral Ontology.Philip J. Ross - 1994 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 11 (2):189-199.
    The paper seeks to show that underlying Bentham's concept of utility is a commitment to a criterion or principle of moral status distinguishing morally relevant beings from the morally irrelevant. Further, that the notion of moral status is ultimately inconsistent with Bentham's utility; that it implies something like a Kantian ethic barring the use of morally relevant beings as mere means to some other's satisfaction, an ethic which suitably interpreted may be more useful in defence of some concerns (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  27
    Value Subjectivism, Individualism, and Moral Standing.Christopher W. Morris - 1986 - Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 8:16-21.
    L. W. Sumner argues that humanism—the position that all and only humans possess moral standing—is false. I agree. Critically examining an argument purporting to establish the exclusive part of humanism—that only humans possess moral standing—Sumner argues that we should not confuse ultimate and objective value, value and welfare, and “formal” and “substantive” theses about value. Again I have no disagreement.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  59
    Marx, Subjectivism, and Modern Moral Philosophy.Jeanne Schuler & Patrick Murray - 2006 - Modern Schoolman 83 (3):173-196.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Subjectivism as moral weakness projected.Judith Lichtenberg - 1983 - Philosophical Quarterly 33 (133):378-385.
  22. Well-Being and Moral Constraints: A Modified Subjectivist Account.Megan Fritts - 2022 - Philosophia 50 (4):1809-1824.
    In this paper, I argue that a modified version of well-being subjectivism can avoid the standard, yet unintuitive, conclusion that morally horrible acts may contribute to an agent’s well-being. To make my case, I argue that “Modified Subjectivists” need not accept such conclusions about well-being so long as they accept the following three theoretical addenda: 1) there are a plurality of values pertaining to well-being, 2) there are some objective goods, even if they do not directly contribute to well-being, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Subjectivism, Relativism and Contextualism (2nd edition).Jussi Suikkanen - 2023 - In Christian B. Miller (ed.), The Bloomsbury Handbook of Ethics, 2nd Edition. Bloomsbury. pp. 130-149.
    There is a family of metaethical views according to which (i) there are no objectively correct moral standards and (ii) whether a given moral claim is true depends in some way on moral standards accepted by either an individual (forms of subjectivism) or a community (forms of relativism). This chapter outlines the three most important versions of this type of theories: old-fashioned subjectivism and relativism, contextualism and new wave subjectivism and relativism. It also explores (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  20
    Ethical Subjectivism: A Lost Cause.Carlo Alvaro - 2023 - Filosofija. Sociologija 34 (3).
    Individual relativism, also known as ethical subjectivism, is an attractive theory about morality. It argues that morality is a matter relative to the individual in a way akin to personal taste. For example, subjectivists regard the ethical judgment ‘Stealing is wrong’ as comparable with the judgment of taste ‘I dislike Brussels sprouts’. Yet, subjectivism is not nihilism. While nihilism denies the existence of moral value, duties, principles and truths, subjectivism claims that they exist, but they are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  54
    Regulative Control and the Subjectivist’s View of Moral Responsibility.P. Eddy Wilson - 2006 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 13 (1):28-33.
    In this essay I focus upon John Martin Fischer’s notion of taking on responsibility. In his view moral actors must acquire a proper self-understanding to take on moral responsibility. I question whether Fischer steps out of his role as a subjectivist, when he maintains that having only guidance control is a necessary condition for moral responsibility. I suggest that subjectivists are committed to the notion that taking on responsibility includes the acquisition of a proper phenomenology of freedom. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  62
    Proposal for a moral esperanto – an outline of universal subjectivism.Floris van den Berg - 2010 - Think 9 (24):97-107.
    How can people live together peacefully, especially in a multicultural, multi-religious society? We should find a minimum level of consensus which is needed to live peacefully together in an open society and a moral language to communicate with each other. Dutch philosopher Paul Cliteur published his book Moral Esperanto in 2007 in which he argues that it is important that people can communicate with each other in a moral and political language which is in principle understandable to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  43
    Meta-ethics and the mortality: Mortality salience leads people to adopt a less subjectivist morality.Onurcan Yilmaz & Hasan G. Bahçekapili - 2018 - Cognition 179 (C):171-177.
    Although lay notions in normative ethics have previously been investigated within the framework of the dual-process interpretation of the terror management theory (TMT), meta-ethical beliefs (subjective vs. objective morality) have not been previously investigated within the same framework. In the present research, we primed mortality salience, shown to impair reasoning performance in previous studies, to see whether it inhibits subjectivist moral judgments in three separate experiments. In Experiment 3, we also investigated whether impaired reasoning performance indeed mediates the effect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  15
    Externalization of moral demands does not motivate exclusion of non-cooperators: A defense of a subjectivist moral psychology.Armin W. Schulz - 2018 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. The subjectivist consequences of expressivism.Jussi Suikkanen - 2009 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (3):364-387.
    Jackson and Pettit argue that expressivism in metaethics collapses into subjectivism. A sincere utterer of a moral claim must believe that she has certain attitudes to be expressed. The truth-conditions of that belief then allegedly provide truth-conditions also for the moral utterance. Thus, the expressivist cannot deny that moral claims have subjectivist truth-conditions. Critics have argued that this argument fails as stated. I try to show that expressivism does have subjectivist repercussions in a way that avoids (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30. Jesse Prinz, The Emotional Construction of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007): Prinz's Subjectivist Moral Realism1.David Copp - 2011 - Noûs 45 (3):577-594.
  31. Von der Möglichkeit des moralischen Subjektivismus. Eine Untersuchung zum Einstellungscharakter von Moral und Religion.Michael Oliva Córdoba - 2021 - Methodus 10 (1):3-31.
    Moral subjectivism is commonly associated with out-of-favour theories like, e.g., Alfred Ayer’s emotivism or John Mackie’s error theory. This paper approaches the field against the background of the attitudinal character of morality and religion. The possibility of a brand of moral subjectivism is established which is common to Ayer’s and Mackie’s theories in name only yet still has significant merits. The perspective from action theory and the philosophy of mind suggests that the problem of moral (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  42
    When Subjectivism Matters.Richard Double - 2003 - Metaphilosophy 34 (4):510-523.
    In this article I consider when the question of whether entities exist subjectively (only in the minds of subjects) or objectively (in themselves, independently of the minds of subjects) is important, both theoretically and practically. I argue that when it comes to the metaphysics underlying three types of moral questions, broadly conceived, the subjectivity question does not matter practically, although it is widely thought to matter. Subjectivism does not matter in these moral questions in the same way(s) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  65
    Ethical Subjectivism and Expressivism.Neil Sinclair - 2020 - Cambridge University Press.
    Ethical subjectivists hold that moral judgements are descriptions of our attitudes. Expressivists hold that they are expressions of our attitudes. These views cook with the same ingredients – the natural world, and our reactions to it – and have similar attractions. This Element assesses each of them by considering whether they can accommodate three central features of moral practice: the practicality of moral judgements, the phenomenon of moral disagreement, and the mind-independence of some moral truths. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  60
    Can Subjectivism Account for Degrees of Wellbeing?Willem van der Deijl & Huub Brouwer - 2021 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 24 (3):767-788.
    Wellbeing describes how good life is for the person living it. Wellbeing comes in degrees. Subjective theories of wellbeing maintain that for objects or states of affairs to benefit us, we need to have a positive attitude towards these objects or states of affairs: the Resonance Constraint. In this article, we investigate to what extent subjectivism can plausibly account for degrees of wellbeing. There is a vast literature on whether preference-satisfaction theory – one particular subjective theory – can account (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. A Subjectivist Solution to the Problem of Harm in Genetic Enhancement.Sruthi Rothenfluch - 2015 - Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics 3 (4).
    Some have recently argued that parents are morally obligated, under certain circumstances, to use pre-natal genetic intervention as a means of enhancement. Despite aiming to benefit the child, such intervention may produce serious and irreparable harm. In these cases, parents seem to have an obligation not to intervene, as such efforts make the child worse off. Julian Savulesu has argued that while harm raises doubts about the acceptability of genetic enhancement, genetic selection remains an obligation. This claim, however, rests on (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  32
    Subjectivism and Blame.David Sobel - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (sup1):149-170.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37. Does expressivism have subjectivist consequences?Mark Schroeder - 2014 - Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1):278-290.
    Metaethical expressivists claim that we can explain what moral words like ‘wrong’ mean without having to know what they are about – but rather by saying what it is to think that something is wrong – namely, to disapprove of it. Given the close connection between expressivists’ theory of the meaning of moral words and our attitudes of approval and disapproval, expressivists have had a hard time shaking the intuitive charge that theirs is an objectionably subjectivist or mind-dependent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  38.  19
    Metaethical Subjectivism.Richard Double - 2006 - Routledge.
    Metaethical subjectivism, the idea that the truth or falsity of moral statements is contingent upon the attitudes or conventions of observers, is often regarded as a lurid philosophical doctrine which generates much psychological resistance to its acceptance. In this accessible book, Richard Double, presents a vigorous defense of metaethical subjectivism, arguing that the acceptance of this doctrine need have no deleterious effects upon theorizing either in normative ethics or in moral practice. Proceeding from a 'worldview' methodology (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Moral objectivism across the lifespan.James R. Beebe & David Sackris - 2016 - Philosophical Psychology 29 (6):912-929.
    We report the results of two studies that examine folk metaethical judgments about the objectivity of morality. We found that participants attributed almost as much objectivity to ethical statements as they did to statements of physical fact and significantly more objectivity to ethical statements than to statements about preferences or tastes. In both studies, younger participants attributed less objectivity to ethical statements than older participants. Females were observed to attribute slightly less objectivity to ethical statements than males, and we found (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  40.  54
    Subjectivism and the Framework of Constitutive Grounds.Andrés G. Garcia & Jakob Green Werkmäster - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (1):155-167.
    Philosophers have applied the framework of constitutive grounds to make sense of the disagreement between subjectivism and objectivism. The framework understands the two theories as being involved in a disagreement about the extent to which value is determined by attitudes. Although the framework affords us with some useful observations about how this should be interpreted, the question how value can be determined by attitudes in the first place is left largely unanswered. Here we explore the benefits of a positive (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. How to be impartial as a subjectivist.Emad H. Atiq - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (3):757-779.
    The metaethical subjectivist claims that there is nothing more to a moral disagreement than a conflict in the desires of the parties involved. Recently, David Enoch has argued that metaethical subjectivism has unacceptable ethical implications. If the subjectivist is right about moral disagreement, then it follows, according to Enoch, that we cannot stand our ground in moral disagreements without violating the demands of impartiality. For being impartial, we’re told, involves being willing to compromise in conflicts that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  46
    Subjectivism and Toleration.Bernard Williams - 1991 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 30:197-208.
    Bertrand Russell said more than once that he was uncomfortable about a conflict, as he saw it, between two things: the strength of the conviction with which he held his ethical beliefs, and the philosophical opinions that he had about the status of those ethical beliefs—opinions which were non-cognitivist, and in some sense subjectivist. Russell felt that, in some way, if he did not think that his ethical beliefs were objective, he had no right to hold them so passionately. This (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Subjectivism versus Relativism in Ethics.D. H. Monro - 1950 - Analysis 11 (1):19 - 24.
    In this article I argue that ethical subjectivism does not lead to relativism, If that is defined as the theory that men do genuinely differ in their ultimate moral judgments, And that there are no grounds for preferring one such moral judgment to another. On the contrary, This view is inconsistent with subjectivism, Since it rests on the objective truth of some such premise as that one ought not to condemn another simply because his tastes are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  77
    Revolutionary Normative Subjectivism.Lewis Williams - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
    The what next question for moral error theorists asks: if moral discourse is systematically error-ridden, then how, if at all, should moral error theorists continue to employ moral discourse? Recent years have seen growing numbers of moral error theorists come to endorse a wider normative error theory according to which all normative judgements are untrue. But despite this shift, the what next question for normative error theorists has received far less attention. This paper presents a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  23
    Subjectivism and Relational Good.Fritz-Anton Fritzson - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (2):359-370.
    In this paper, a distinctly subjectivist analysis of the nature of relational goodness or goodness for is proposed. Like the generic subjectivist analysis of value, the proposal is to analyse value in terms of attitudes. Specifically, the proposed analysis of goodness for appeals to a special kind of attitude: namely, so-called for-someone’s-sake attitudes. Unlike other analyses in the literature that have appealed to this kind of attitude, the analysis proposed here is not a fitting-attitude analysis. Rather than appealing to for-someone’s-sake (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  85
    Intuitionism and subjectivism.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - Metaphilosophy 22 (1-2):115-121.
    I define ethical intuitionism as the view that it is appropriate to appeal to inferentially unsupported moral beliefs in the course of moral reasoning. I mention four common objections to this view, including the view that all such appeals to intuitionism collapse into “subjectivism”, i.e., that they make truth in ethical theory depend on what people believe. I defend intuitionism from versions of this criticism expressed by R.M. Hare and Peter Singer.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  70
    Objectivism, subjectivism, and relativism in ethics.Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred Dycus Miller & Jeffrey Paul (eds.) - 2008 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Some essays in this book consider whether objective moral truths can be grounded in an understanding of the nature of human beings as rational and social ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  27
    A Subjectivist Reply to Swinburne.Geoffrey Harrison - 1978 - Philosophy 53 (205):389 - 394.
    A philosophical tradition is in part identified by its more durable controversies. The British tradition in moral philosophy running, roughly, from Hobbes to the present day, involves several fine examples of the type—the plausibility or otherwise of the compatibilist view of free will, the case for and against utilitarianism, and perhaps above all the implications of the fact/value distinction. It is always pleasing to find some new variation on such themes; you have a comforting sense of the inherent permanence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  30
    The meaningful life: subjectivism, objectivism, and divine support.Bradford Hooker - 2008 - In Nafsika Athanassoulis & Samantha Vice (eds.), The Moral Life: Essays in Honour of John Cottingham. Palgrave. pp. 184-200.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50.  10
    Spinoza and Ethical Subjectivism.Ruth Mattern - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (sup1):59-82.
    A puzzling feature of Spinoza's discussion of the good is that it takes place on two different levels whose compatibility seems uncertain. He advances a view of the nature of ascriptions of “good” to certain individual things, but he also devotes a large part of the Ethics to recommending a particular conception of the good person. The first theory appears to undermine the force of the second. For Spinoza's view of ascriptions of “good” to any objects apparently leads in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 988