Results for ' Hilbert Irreducibility Theorem'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Algebraic extensions in nonstandard models and Hilbert's irreducibility theorem.Masahiro Yasumoto - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):470-480.
    LetKbe an algebraic number field andIKthe ring of algebraic integers inK. *Kand *IKdenote enlargements ofKandIKrespectively. LetxЄ *K–K. In this paper, we are concerned with algebraic extensions ofKwithin *K. For eachxЄ *K–Kand each natural numberd, YKis defined to be the number of algebraic extensions ofKof degreedwithin *K.xЄ *K–Kis called a Hilbertian element ifYK= 0 for alldЄ N,d> 1; in other words,Khas no algebraic extension within *K. In their paper [2], P. C. Gilmore and A. Robinson proved that the existence of a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  27
    Nonstandard Aspects of Hilbert's Irreducibility Theorem.Alexander Prestel & Peter Roquette - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):1056.
  3.  38
    Peter Roquette. Nonstandard aspects of Hilbert's irreducibility theorem. Model theory and algebra, A memorial tribute to Abraham Robinson, edited by D. H. Saracino and V. B. Weispfenning, Lecture notes in mathematics, vol. 498, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, and New York, 1975, pp. 231–275. [REVIEW]Alexander Prestel - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):1056.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    A Topological Approach to Undefinability in Algebraic Extensions Of.Kirsten Eisenträger, Russell Miller, Caleb Springer & Linda Westrick - 2023 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 29 (4):626-655.
    For any subset $Z \subseteq {\mathbb {Q}}$, consider the set $S_Z$ of subfields $L\subseteq {\overline {\mathbb {Q}}}$ which contain a co-infinite subset $C \subseteq L$ that is universally definable in L such that $C \cap {\mathbb {Q}}=Z$. Placing a natural topology on the set ${\operatorname {Sub}({\overline {\mathbb {Q}}})}$ of subfields of ${\overline {\mathbb {Q}}}$, we show that if Z is not thin in ${\mathbb {Q}}$, then $S_Z$ is meager in ${\operatorname {Sub}({\overline {\mathbb {Q}}})}$. Here, thin and meager both mean “small”, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  22
    The Foundations of Geometry.David Hilbert - 1899 - Open Court Company (This Edition Published 1921).
    §30. Significance of Desargues's theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64 CHAPTER VI. PASCAL'S THEOREM. §31. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  6.  43
    Quine’s Substitutional Definition of Logical Truth and the Philosophical Significance of the Löwenheim-Hilbert-Bernays Theorem.Henri Wagner - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 40 (2):182-199.
    The Löwenheim-Hilbert-Bernays theorem states that, for an arithmetical first-order language L, if S is a satisfiable schema, then substitution of open sentences of L for the predicate letters of S...
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  38
    A weak variant of Hindman’s Theorem stronger than Hilbert’s Theorem.Lorenzo Carlucci - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (3-4):381-389.
    Hirst investigated a natural restriction of Hindman’s Finite Sums Theorem—called Hilbert’s Theorem—and proved it equivalent over \ to the Infinite Pigeonhole Principle for all colors. This gave the first example of a natural restriction of Hindman’s Theorem provably much weaker than Hindman’s Theorem itself. We here introduce another natural restriction of Hindman’s Theorem—which we name the Adjacent Hindman’s Theorem with apartness—and prove it to be provable from Ramsey’s Theorem for pairs and strictly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  33
    Satisfying Predicates: Kleene's Proof of the Hilbert–Bernays Theorem.Gary Ebbs - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (4):346-366.
    The Hilbert–Bernays Theorem establishes that for any satisfiable first-order quantificational schema S, one can write out linguistic expressions that are guaranteed to yield a true sentence of elementary arithmetic when they are substituted for the predicate letters in S. The theorem implies that if L is a consistent, fully interpreted language rich enough to express elementary arithmetic, then a schema S is valid if and only if every sentence of L that can be obtained by substituting predicates (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  5
    Der Beweis des Hilbert-Schmidt-Theorems.R. Siegmund-Schultze - 1986 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 36 (3):251-270.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  73
    First‐order logical validity and the hilbert‐bernays theorem.Gary Ebbs & Warren Goldfarb - 2018 - Philosophical Issues 28 (1):159-175.
    What we call the Hilbert‐Bernays (HB) Theorem establishes that for any satisfiable first‐order quantificational schema S, there are expressions of elementary arithmetic that yield a true sentence of arithmetic when they are substituted for the predicate letters in S. Our goals here are, first, to explain and defend W. V. Quine's claim that the HB theorem licenses us to define the first‐order logical validity of a schema in terms of predicate substitution; second, to clarify the theorem (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  34
    Ordinal numbers and the Hilbert basis theorem.Stephen G. Simpson - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):961-974.
  12.  76
    Survey of general quantum physics.C. Piron - 1972 - Foundations of Physics 2 (4):287-314.
    The abstract description of a physical system is developed, along lines originally suggested by Birkhoff and von Neumann, in terms of the complete lattice of propositions associated with that system, and the distinction between classical and quantum systems is made precise. With the help of the notion of state, a propositional system is defined: it is remarked that every irreducible propositional system (of more than three dimensions) is isomorphic to the lattice of all closed subspaces of a Hilbert space (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  13.  48
    Hilbert's 'Verunglückter Beweis', the first epsilon theorem, and consistency proofs.Richard Zach - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (2):79-94.
    In the 1920s, Ackermann and von Neumann, in pursuit of Hilbert's programme, were working on consistency proofs for arithmetical systems. One proposed method of giving such proofs is Hilbert's epsilon-substitution method. There was, however, a second approach which was not reflected in the publications of the Hilbert school in the 1920s, and which is a direct precursor of Hilbert's first epsilon theorem and a certain "general consistency result" due to Bernays. An analysis of the form (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  14.  22
    Hilbert's Programme and Gödel's Theorems.Matthias Schirn Karl‐Georg Niebergall - 2002 - Dialectica 56 (4):347-370.
    In this paper, we attempt to show that a weak version of Hilbert's metamathematics is compatible with Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems by employing only what are clearly natural prov‐ ability predicates. Defining first “T proves the consistency of a theory S indirectly in one step”, we subsequently prove “PA proves its own consistency indirectly in one step” and sketch the proof for “If S is a recursively enumerable extension of , S proves its own consistency indirectly in one step”. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Fermat’s last theorem proved in Hilbert arithmetic. I. From the proof by induction to the viewpoint of Hilbert arithmetic.Vasil Penchev - 2021 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 13 (7):1-57.
    In a previous paper, an elementary and thoroughly arithmetical proof of Fermat’s last theorem by induction has been demonstrated if the case for “n = 3” is granted as proved only arithmetically (which is a fact a long time ago), furthermore in a way accessible to Fermat himself though without being absolutely and precisely correct. The present paper elucidates the contemporary mathematical background, from which an inductive proof of FLT can be inferred since its proof for the case for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Fermat’s last theorem proved in Hilbert arithmetic. III. The quantum-information unification of Fermat’s last theorem and Gleason’s theorem.Vasil Penchev - 2022 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 14 (12):1-30.
    The previous two parts of the paper demonstrate that the interpretation of Fermat’s last theorem (FLT) in Hilbert arithmetic meant both in a narrow sense and in a wide sense can suggest a proof by induction in Part I and by means of the Kochen - Specker theorem in Part II. The same interpretation can serve also for a proof FLT based on Gleason’s theorem and partly similar to that in Part II. The concept of (probabilistic) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Fermat’s last theorem proved in Hilbert arithmetic. II. Its proof in Hilbert arithmetic by the Kochen-Specker theorem with or without induction.Vasil Penchev - 2022 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 14 (10):1-52.
    The paper is a continuation of another paper published as Part I. Now, the case of “n=3” is inferred as a corollary from the Kochen and Specker theorem (1967): the eventual solutions of Fermat’s equation for “n=3” would correspond to an admissible disjunctive division of qubit into two absolutely independent parts therefore versus the contextuality of any qubit, implied by the Kochen – Specker theorem. Incommensurability (implied by the absence of hidden variables) is considered as dual to quantum (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  10
    Hilbert's program: incompleteness theorems vs. partial realizations.Roman Murawski - 1994 - In Jan Wolenski (ed.), Philosophical Logic in Poland. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 103--127.
  19. On an alleged refutation of Hilbert's program using gödel's first incompleteness theorem.Michael Detlefsen - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 19 (4):343 - 377.
    It is argued that an instrumentalist notion of proof such as that represented in Hilbert's viewpoint is not obligated to satisfy the conservation condition that is generally regarded as a constraint on Hilbert's Program. A more reasonable soundness condition is then considered and shown not to be counter-exemplified by Godel's First Theorem. Finally, attention is given to the question of what a theory is; whether it should be seen as a "list" or corpus of beliefs, or as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20. Gödel mathematics versus Hilbert mathematics. I. The Gödel incompleteness (1931) statement: axiom or theorem?Vasil Penchev - 2022 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 14 (9):1-56.
    The present first part about the eventual completeness of mathematics (called “Hilbert mathematics”) is concentrated on the Gödel incompleteness (1931) statement: if it is an axiom rather than a theorem inferable from the axioms of (Peano) arithmetic, (ZFC) set theory, and propositional logic, this would pioneer the pathway to Hilbert mathematics. One of the main arguments that it is an axiom consists in the direct contradiction of the axiom of induction in arithmetic and the axiom of infinity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Hilbert’s Program.Richard Zach - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    In the early 1920s, the German mathematician David Hilbert (1862–1943) put forward a new proposal for the foundation of classical mathematics which has come to be known as Hilbert's Program. It calls for a formalization of all of mathematics in axiomatic form, together with a proof that this axiomatization of mathematics is consistent. The consistency proof itself was to be carried out using only what Hilbert called “finitary” methods. The special epistemological character of finitary reasoning then yields (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  22.  54
    The strong soundness theorem for real closed fields and Hilbert’s Nullstellensatz in second order arithmetic.Nobuyuki Sakamoto & Kazuyuki Tanaka - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (3):337-349.
    By RCA 0 , we denote a subsystem of second order arithmetic based on Δ0 1 comprehension and Δ0 1 induction. We show within this system that the real number system R satisfies all the theorems (possibly with non-standard length) of the theory of real closed fields under an appropriate truth definition. This enables us to develop linear algebra and polynomial ring theory over real and complex numbers, so that we particularly obtain Hilbert’s Nullstellensatz in RCA 0.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Hilbert's programme and gödel's theorems.Karl-Georg Niebergall & Matthias Schirn - 2002 - Dialectica 56 (4):347–370.
  24.  64
    Redundancies in the Hilbert-Bernays derivability conditions for gödel's second incompleteness theorem.R. G. Jeroslow - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (3):359-367.
  25. Contemporary perspectives on Hilbert's second problem and the gödel incompleteness theorems.Harvey Friedman - manuscript
    It is not yet clear just what the most illuminating ways of rigorously stating the Incompleteness Theorems are. This is particularly true of the Second. Also I believe that there are more illuminating proofs of the Second that have yet to be uncovered.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  28
    Hilbert Algebras with a Modal Operator $${\Diamond}$$ ◊.Sergio A. Celani & Daniela Montangie - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (3):639-662.
    A Hilbert algebra with supremum is a Hilbert algebra where the associated order is a join-semilattice. This class of algebras is a variety and was studied in Celani and Montangie . In this paper we shall introduce and study the variety of $${H_{\Diamond}^{\vee}}$$ H ◊ ∨ -algebras, which are Hilbert algebras with supremum endowed with a modal operator $${\Diamond}$$ ◊ . We give a topological representation for these algebras using the topological spectral-like representation for Hilbert algebras (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  10
    Redundancies in the Hilbert-Bernays Derivability Conditions for Gödel's Second Incompleteness Theorem.R. G. Jeroslow - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):875-876.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  21
    The Rank Function and Hilbert'S Second ϵ‐Theorem.Pier Luigi Ferrari - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (4):367-373.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  25
    The Rank Function and Hilbert'S Second ε-Theorem.Pier Luigi Ferrari - 1989 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35 (4):367-373.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Hilbert's program then and now.Richard Zach - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), Philosophy of Logic. Malden, Mass.: North Holland. pp. 411–447.
    Hilbert’s program was an ambitious and wide-ranging project in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. In order to “dispose of the foundational questions in mathematics once and for all,” Hilbert proposed a two-pronged approach in 1921: first, classical mathematics should be formalized in axiomatic systems; second, using only restricted, “finitary” means, one should give proofs of the consistency of these axiomatic systems. Although Gödel’s incompleteness theorems show that the program as originally conceived cannot be carried out, it had (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  31. Hilbert Mathematics versus Gödel Mathematics. III. Hilbert Mathematics by Itself, and Gödel Mathematics versus the Physical World within It: both as Its Particular Cases.Vasil Penchev - 2023 - Philosophy of Science eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 16 (47):1-46.
    The paper discusses Hilbert mathematics, a kind of Pythagorean mathematics, to which the physical world is a particular case. The parameter of the “distance between finiteness and infinity” is crucial. Any nonzero finite value of it features the particular case in the frameworks of Hilbert mathematics where the physical world appears “ex nihilo” by virtue of an only mathematical necessity or quantum information conservation physically. One does not need the mythical Big Bang which serves to concentrate all the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. How Hilbert’s attempt to unify gravitation and electromagnetism failed completely, and a plausible resolution.Victor Christianto, Florentin Smarandache & Robert N. Boyd - manuscript
    In the present paper, these authors argue on actual reasons why Hilbert’s axiomatic program to unify gravitation theory and electromagnetism failed completely. An outline of plausible resolution of this problem is given here, based on: a) Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, b) Newton’s aether stream model. And in another paper we will present our calculation of receding Moon from Earth based on such a matter creation hypothesis. More experiments and observations are called to verify this new hypothesis, albeit it is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  26
    On the validity of hilbert's nullstellensatz, artin's theorem, and related results in grothendieck toposes.W. A. MacCaull - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (4):1177-1187.
  34. Hilbert Mathematics Versus Gödel Mathematics. IV. The New Approach of Hilbert Mathematics Easily Resolving the Most Difficult Problems of Gödel Mathematics.Vasil Penchev - 2023 - Philosophy of Science eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 16 (75):1-52.
    The paper continues the consideration of Hilbert mathematics to mathematics itself as an additional “dimension” allowing for the most difficult and fundamental problems to be attacked in a new general and universal way shareable between all of them. That dimension consists in the parameter of the “distance between finiteness and infinity”, particularly able to interpret standard mathematics as a particular case, the basis of which are arithmetic, set theory and propositional logic: that is as a special “flat” case of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  45
    Hilbert's programme.Georg Kreisel - 1958 - Dialectica 12 (3‐4):346-372.
    Hilbert's plan for understanding the concept of infinity required the elimination of non‐finitist machinery from proofs of finitist assertions. The failure of the original plan leads to a hierarchy of progressively less elementary, but still constructive methods instead of finitist ones . A mathematical proof of this failure requires a definition of « finitist ».—The paper sketches the three principal methods for the syntactic analysis of non‐constructive mathematics, the resulting consistency proofs and constructive interpretations, modelled on Herbrand's theorem, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  36.  8
    On an extension of Hilbert's second ε-theorem.T. B. Flannagan - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (3):393-397.
  37.  44
    Richard Zach, Hilbert's 'Verunglückter Beweis', the First Epsilon Theorem, and Consistency Proofs. [REVIEW]Dirk Schlimm - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):247-248.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  94
    Hilbert's program sixty years later.Wilfried Sieg - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):338-348.
    On June 4, 1925, Hilbert delivered an address to the Westphalian Mathematical Society in Miinster; that was, as a quick calculation will convince you, almost exactly sixty years ago. The address was published in 1926 under the title Über dasUnendlicheand is perhaps Hilbert's most comprehensive presentation of his ideas concerning the finitist justification of classical mathematics and the role his proof theory was to play in it. But what has become of the ambitious program for securing all of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  39.  47
    Hilbert spaces with generic groups of automorphisms.Alexander Berenstein - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):289-299.
    Let G be a countable group. We prove that there is a model companion for the theory of Hilbert spaces with a group G of automorphisms. We use a theorem of Hulanicki to show that G is amenable if and only if the structure induced by countable copies of the regular representation of G is existentially closed.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  10
    Da Hilbert a von Neumann. La svolta pragmatica nell'assiomatica.Giambattista Formica - 2013 - Roma RM, Italia: Carocci.
    I teoremi di Gödel suscitano un interesse sempre crescente nella riflessione filosofica contemporanea. Rimane però in discussione fra gli studiosi come si sia arrivati alla loro scoperta e quale sia il loro significato per il dibattito sui fondamenti delle scienze. Nel volume si ripercorrono le vicende che portarono alla formulazione dei teoremi di incompletezza, a partire dall’incontro tra von Neumann e Gödel al Congresso di Königsberg nel 1930, e si indaga, riferendosi in particolare al lavoro di von Neumann, sull’impatto che (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Hilbert's program and the omega-rule.Aleksandar Ignjatović - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):322 - 343.
    In the first part of this paper we discuss some aspects of Detlefsen's attempt to save Hilbert's Program from the consequences of Godel's Second Incompleteness Theorem. His arguments are based on his interpretation of the long standing and well-known controversy on what, exactly, finitistic means are. In his paper [1] Detlefsen takes the position that there is a form of the ω-rule which is a finitistically valid means of proof, sufficient to prove the consistency of elementary number theory (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  42.  48
    Hilbert’s varepsilon -operator in intuitionistic type theories.John L. Bell - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):323--337.
    We investigate Hilbert’s varepsilon -calculus in the context of intuitionistic type theories, that is, within certain systems of intuitionistic higher-order logic. We determine the additional deductive strength conferred on an intuitionistic type theory by the adjunction of closed varepsilon -terms. We extend the usual topos semantics for type theories to the varepsilon -operator and prove a completeness theorem. The paper also contains a discussion of the concept of “partially defined‘ varepsilon -term. MSC: 03B15, 03B20, 03G30.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Does the deduction theorem fail for modal logic?Raul Hakli & Sara Negri - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):849-867.
    Various sources in the literature claim that the deduction theorem does not hold for normal modal or epistemic logic, whereas others present versions of the deduction theorem for several normal modal systems. It is shown here that the apparent problem arises from an objectionable notion of derivability from assumptions in an axiomatic system. When a traditional Hilbert-type system of axiomatic logic is generalized into a system for derivations from assumptions, the necessitation rule has to be modified in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  44. A variant to Hilbert's theory of the foundations of arithmetic.G. Kreisel - 1953 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4 (14):107-129.
    IN Hilbert's theory of the foundations of any given branch of mathematics the main problem is to establish the consistency (of a suitable formalisation) of this branch. Since the (intuitionist) criticisms of classical logic, which Hilbert's theory was intended to meet, never even alluded to inconsistencies (in classical arithmetic), and since the investigations of Hilbert's school have always established much more than mere consistency, it is natural to formulate another general problem in the foundations of mathematics: to (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  20
    Jeroslow R. G.. Redundancies in the Hilbert–Bernays derivability conditions for Gödel's second incompleteness theorem.C. F. Kent - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):875-876.
  46.  58
    Hilbert's program modi ed.Solomon Feferman - unknown
    The background to the development of proof theory since 1960 is contained in the article (MATHEMATICS, FOUNDATIONS OF), Vol. 5, pp. 208- 209. Brie y, Hilbert's program (H.P.), inaugurated in the 1920s, aimed to secure the foundations of mathematics by giving nitary consistency proofs of formal systems such as for number theory, analysis and set theory, in which informal mathematics can be represented directly. These systems are based on classical logic and implicitly or explicitly depend on the assumption of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. The Kochen - Specker theorem in quantum mechanics: a philosophical comment (part 1).Vasil Penchev - 2013 - Philosophical Alternatives 22 (1):67-77.
    Non-commuting quantities and hidden parameters – Wave-corpuscular dualism and hidden parameters – Local or nonlocal hidden parameters – Phase space in quantum mechanics – Weyl, Wigner, and Moyal – Von Neumann’s theorem about the absence of hidden parameters in quantum mechanics and Hermann – Bell’s objection – Quantum-mechanical and mathematical incommeasurability – Kochen – Specker’s idea about their equivalence – The notion of partial algebra – Embeddability of a qubit into a bit – Quantum computer is not Turing machine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  38
    Hilbert versus Hindman.Jeffry L. Hirst - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (1-2):123-125.
    We show that a statement HIL, which is motivated by a lemma of Hilbert and close in formulation to Hindman’s theorem, is actually much weaker than Hindman’s theorem. In particular, HIL is finitistically reducible in the sense of Hilbert’s program, while Hindman’s theorem is not.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  17
    A note on a proof of Hilbert's second ε-theorem.Pier Luigi Ferrari - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):214-215.
  50.  20
    A Note on a Proof of Hilbert's Second $varepsilon$-Theorem.Pier Luigi Ferrari - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):214-215.
1 — 50 / 1000