Switch to: References

Citations of:

Hilbert's programme

Dialectica 12 (3‐4):346-372 (1958)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hilbert’s Program.Richard Zach - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    In the early 1920s, the German mathematician David Hilbert (1862–1943) put forward a new proposal for the foundation of classical mathematics which has come to be known as Hilbert's Program. It calls for a formalization of all of mathematics in axiomatic form, together with a proof that this axiomatization of mathematics is consistent. The consistency proof itself was to be carried out using only what Hilbert called “finitary” methods. The special epistemological character of finitary reasoning then yields the required justification (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Hilbert's program then and now.Richard Zach - 2006 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 411–447.
    Hilbert’s program was an ambitious and wide-ranging project in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. In order to “dispose of the foundational questions in mathematics once and for all,” Hilbert proposed a two-pronged approach in 1921: first, classical mathematics should be formalized in axiomatic systems; second, using only restricted, “finitary” means, one should give proofs of the consistency of these axiomatic systems. Although Gödel’s incompleteness theorems show that the program as originally conceived cannot be carried out, it had many partial (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Enciclopédia de Termos Lógico-Filosóficos.João Miguel Biscaia Branquinho, Desidério Murcho & Nelson Gonçalves Gomes (eds.) - 2006 - São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Martins Fontes.
    Esta enciclopédia abrange, de uma forma introdutória mas desejavelmente rigorosa, uma diversidade de conceitos, temas, problemas, argumentos e teorias localizados numa área relativamente recente de estudos, os quais tem sido habitual qualificar como «estudos lógico-filosóficos». De uma forma apropriadamente genérica, e apesar de o território teórico abrangido ser extenso e de contornos por vezes difusos, podemos dizer que na área se investiga um conjunto de questões fundamentais acerca da natureza da linguagem, da mente, da cognição e do raciocínio humanos, bem (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hilbert’s Finitism: Historical, Philosophical, and Metamathematical Perspectives.Richard Zach - 2001 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    In the 1920s, David Hilbert proposed a research program with the aim of providing mathematics with a secure foundation. This was to be accomplished by first formalizing logic and mathematics in their entirety, and then showing---using only so-called finitistic principles---that these formalizations are free of contradictions. ;In the area of logic, the Hilbert school accomplished major advances both in introducing new systems of logic, and in developing central metalogical notions, such as completeness and decidability. The analysis of unpublished material presented (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • ‘Metamathematics’ in Transition.Matthias Wille - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (4):333 - 358.
    In this paper, we trace the conceptual history of the term ?metamathematics? in the nineteenth century. It is well known that Hilbert introduced the term for his proof-theoretic enterprise in about 1922. But he was verifiably inspired by an earlier usage of the phrase in the 1870s. After outlining Hilbert's understanding of the term, we will explore the lines of inducement and elucidate the different meanings of ?metamathematics? in the final decades of the nineteenth century. Finally, we will investigate the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Metamathematics and the philosophy of mind.Judson Webb - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (June):156-78.
    The metamathematical theorems of Gödel and Church are frequently applied to the philosophy of mind, typically as rational evidence against mechanism. Using methods of Post and Smullyan, these results are presented as purely mathematical theorems and various such applications are discussed critically. In particular, J. Lucas's use of Gödel's theorem to distinguish between conscious and unconscious beings is refuted, while more generally, attempts to extract philosophy from metamathematics are shown to involve only dramatizations of the constructivity problem in foundations. More (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • König's Infinity Lemma and Beth's Tree Theorem.George Weaver - 2017 - History and Philosophy of Logic 38 (1):48-56.
    König, D. [1926. ‘Sur les correspondances multivoques des ensembles’, Fundamenta Mathematica, 8, 114–34] includes a result subsequently called König's Infinity Lemma. Konig, D. [1927. ‘Über eine Schlussweise aus dem Endlichen ins Unendliche’, Acta Litterarum ac Scientiarum, Szeged, 3, 121–30] includes a graph theoretic formulation: an infinite, locally finite and connected graph includes an infinite path. Contemporary applications of the infinity lemma in logic frequently refer to a consequence of the infinity lemma: an infinite, locally finite tree with a root has (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hilbert between the formal and the informal side of mathematics.Giorgio Venturi - 2015 - Manuscrito 38 (2):5-38.
    : In this article we analyze the key concept of Hilbert's axiomatic method, namely that of axiom. We will find two different concepts: the first one from the period of Hilbert's foundation of geometry and the second one at the time of the development of his proof theory. Both conceptions are linked to two different notions of intuition and show how Hilbert's ideas are far from a purely formalist conception of mathematics. The principal thesis of this article is that one (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Origin of Symbolic Mathematics and Its Significance for Wittgenstein’s Thought.Sören Stenlund - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (1):7-92.
    The main topic of this essay is symbolic mathematics or the method of symbolic construction, which I trace to the end of the sixteenth century when Franciscus Vieta invented the algebraic symbolism and started to use the word ‘symbolic’ in the relevant, non-ontological sense. This approach has played an important role for many of the great inventions in modern mathematics such as the introduction of the decimal place-value system of numeration, Descartes’ analytic geometry, and Leibniz’s infinitesimal calculus. It was also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Relative consistency and accessible domains.Wilfried Sieg - 1990 - Synthese 84 (2):259 - 297.
    Wilfred Sieg. Relative Consistency and Accesible Domains.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Hilbert's 'Verunglückter Beweis', the first epsilon theorem, and consistency proofs.Richard Zach - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (2):79-94.
    In the 1920s, Ackermann and von Neumann, in pursuit of Hilbert's programme, were working on consistency proofs for arithmetical systems. One proposed method of giving such proofs is Hilbert's epsilon-substitution method. There was, however, a second approach which was not reflected in the publications of the Hilbert school in the 1920s, and which is a direct precursor of Hilbert's first epsilon theorem and a certain "general consistency result" due to Bernays. An analysis of the form of this so-called "failed proof" (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hilbert's Program Revisited.Panu Raatikainen - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):157-177.
    After sketching the main lines of Hilbert's program, certain well-known andinfluential interpretations of the program are critically evaluated, and analternative interpretation is presented. Finally, some recent developments inlogic related to Hilbert's program are reviewed.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inferentializing Semantics.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (3):255 - 274.
    The entire development of modern logic is characterized by various forms of confrontation of what has come to be called proof theory with what has earned the label of model theory. For a long time the widely accepted view was that while model theory captures directly what logical formalisms are about, proof theory is merely our technical means of getting some incomplete grip on this; but in recent decades the situation has altered. Not only did proof theory expand into new (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Recursive Functions and Metamathematics: Problems of Completeness and Decidability, Gödel's Theorems.Rod J. L. Adams & Roman Murawski - 1999 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    Traces the development of recursive functions from their origins in the late nineteenth century to the mid-1930s, with particular emphasis on the work and influence of Kurt Gödel.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Essay Review.Enrico Moriconi - 2017 - History and Philosophy of Logic 38 (2):1-11.
    Gerhard Gentzen was born on 24 November 1909. In 1929 he moved to Göttingen where he wrote his doctoral thesis, Untersuchungen über das logische Schliessen, under the supervision of P. Bernays. The...
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparer la logique et le droit? Quelques remarques théoriques sur l’usage du numérique en droit. [REVIEW]Jean Lassègue - 2022 - Revue de Synthèse 143 (3-4):495-511.
    Résumé La numérisation actuelle du droit permet de revenir sur les liens historiques entre le droit et la logique moderne. En se fondant sur la différence établie par J. Van Heijenoort entre logique «comme calcul» et logique «comme langage», l’article établit des analogies entre différentes interprétations de la logique et différents types de systèmes ou d’instances juridiques : «Common law», systèmes «civils», «cour de cassation», cette dernière notion caractérisant le formalisme hilbertien. Ce formalisme a tenté de réduire la logique «comme (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logique mathématique et philosophie des mathématiques.Yvon Gauthier - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):243-275.
    Pour le philosophe intéressé aux structures et aux fondements du savoir théorétique, à la constitution d'une « méta-théorétique «, θεωρíα., qui, mieux que les « Wissenschaftslehre » fichtéenne ou husserlienne et par-delà les débris de la métaphysique, veut dans une intention nouvelle faire la synthèse du « théorétique », la logique mathématique se révèle un objet privilégié.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does reductive proof theory have a viable rationale?Solomon Feferman - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):63-96.
    The goals of reduction andreductionism in the natural sciences are mainly explanatoryin character, while those inmathematics are primarily foundational.In contrast to global reductionistprograms which aim to reduce all ofmathematics to one supposedly ``universal'' system or foundational scheme, reductive proof theory pursues local reductions of one formal system to another which is more justified in some sense. In this direction, two specific rationales have been proposed as aims for reductive proof theory, the constructive consistency-proof rationale and the foundational reduction rationale. However, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Hilbert's program relativized: Proof-theoretical and foundational reductions.Solomon Feferman - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):364-384.
  • On Theorems of Gödel and Kreisel: Completeness and Markov's Principle.D. C. McCarty - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (1):99-107.
    In 1957, Gödel proved that completeness for intuitionistic predicate logic HPL implies forms of Markov's Principle, MP. The result first appeared, with Kreisel's refinements and elaborations, in Kreisel. Featuring large in the Gödel-Kreisel proofs are applications of the axiom of dependent choice, DC. Also in play is a form of Herbrand's Theorem, one allowing a reduction of HPL derivations for negated prenex formulae to derivations of negations of conjunctions of suitable instances. First, we here show how to deduce Gödel's results (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Scope of Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem.Bernd Buldt - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (3-4):499-552.
    Guided by questions of scope, this paper provides an overview of what is known about both the scope and, consequently, the limits of Gödel’s famous first incompleteness theorem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Proof theory in philosophy of mathematics.Andrew Arana - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (4):336-347.
    A variety of projects in proof theory of relevance to the philosophy of mathematics are surveyed, including Gödel's incompleteness theorems, conservation results, independence results, ordinal analysis, predicativity, reverse mathematics, speed-up results, and provability logics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reading Gentzen's Three Consistency Proofs Uniformly.Ryota Akiyoshi & Yuta Takahashi - 2013 - Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 41 (1):1-22.
  • On a Relationship between Gödel's Second Incompleteness Theorem and Hilbert's Program.Ryota Akiyoshi - 2009 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 17:13-29.
  • Hilbert's Metamathematical Problems and Their Solutions.Besim Karakadilar - 2008 - Dissertation, Boston University
    This dissertation examines several of the problems that Hilbert discovered in the foundations of mathematics, from a metalogical perspective. The problems manifest themselves in four different aspects of Hilbert’s views: (i) Hilbert’s axiomatic approach to the foundations of mathematics; (ii) His response to criticisms of set theory; (iii) His response to intuitionist criticisms of classical mathematics; (iv) Hilbert’s contribution to the specification of the role of logical inference in mathematical reasoning. This dissertation argues that Hilbert’s axiomatic approach was guided primarily (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel on intuition and on Hilbert's finitism.W. W. Tait - 2010 - In Kurt Gödel, Solomon Feferman, Charles Parsons & Stephen G. Simpson (eds.), Kurt Gödel: Essays for His Centennial. Association for Symbolic Logic.
    There are some puzzles about G¨ odel’s published and unpublished remarks concerning finitism that have led some commentators to believe that his conception of it was unstable, that he oscillated back and forth between different accounts of it. I want to discuss these puzzles and argue that, on the contrary, G¨ odel’s writings represent a smooth evolution, with just one rather small double-reversal, of his view of finitism. He used the term “finit” (in German) or “finitary” or “finitistic” primarily to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations