Results for ' Carnap's confirmation theory'

994 found
Order:
  1.  36
    Carnap's Theories of Confirmation.Pierre Wagner - 2011 - In Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao Gonzalo, Thomas Uebel, Stephan Hartmann & Marcel Weber (eds.), Explanation, Prediction, and Confirmation. Springer. pp. 477--486.
    The first theory of confirmation that Carnap developed in detail is to be found in "Testability and Meaning". In this paper, he addressed the issue of a definition of empiricism, several years after abandoning the quest for a unique and universal logical framework supposed to be the basis of a clear distinction between the meaningful sentences of science and the pseudo-sentences of metaphysics. The principle of tolerance (according to which everyone is free to build up his own form (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  53
    Abstracts from Logical Form: An Experimental Study of the Nexus between Language and Logic II.Joseph S. Fulda - 2006 - Journal of Pragmatics 38 (6):925-943.
    This experimental study provides further support for a theory of meaning first put forward by Bar-Hillel and Carnap in 1953 and foreshadowed by Asimov in 1951. The theory is the Popperian notion that the meaningfulness of a proposition is its a priori falsity. We tested this theory in the first part of this paper by translating to logical form a long, tightly written, published text and computed the meaningfulness of each proposition using the a priori falsity measure. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. A Note on Carnap's "Truth and Confirmation.".Leonard Linsky & Rudolf Carnap - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):139-139.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On inductive logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1945 - Philosophy of Science 12 (2):72-97.
    Among the various meanings in which the word ‘probability’ is used in everyday language, in the discussion of scientists, and in the theories of probability, there are especially two which must be clearly distinguished. We shall use for them the terms ‘probability1’ and ‘probability2'. Probability1 is a logical concept, a certain logical relation between two sentences ; it is the same as the concept of degree of confirmation. I shall write briefly “c” for “degree of confirmation,” and “c” (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  5. Analogy and confirmation theory.Mary Hesse - 1964 - Philosophy of Science 31 (4):319-327.
    The argument from analogy is examined from the point of view of Carnap's confirmation theory. It is argued that if inductive arguments are to be applicable to the real world, they must contain elementary analogical inferences. Carnap's system as originally developed (theλ -system) is not strong enough to take account of analogical arguments, but it is shown that the new system, which he has announced but not published in detail (theη -system), is capable of satisfying the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  6.  29
    Analogy and confirmation theory.Mary Hesse - 1963 - Dialectica 17 (2-3):284-292.
    The argument from analogy is examined from the standpoint of Carnap's confirmation theory. Carnap's own discussion of analogy in relation to his c*— function is restricted to cases where the analogues are known to be similar, but not known to be different in any respect. It has been argued by the author in a previous work,, and by P. Achinstein, that typical analogy arguments involve known differences between the analogues as well as similarities. Achinstein shows that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  7. On the Use of Hilbert's ε-Operator in Scientific Theories.Rudolf Carnap - 1961 - In Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua & [From Old Catalog] (eds.), Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics. Jerusalem,: Magnes Press. pp. 156--164.
  8.  54
    Carnap's Empiricism, Lost and Found.Robert G. Hudson - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 43:81-88.
    Recent scholarship (by mainly Michael Friedman, but also by Thomas Uebel) on the philosophy of Rudolf Carnap covering the period from the publication of Carnap’s’ 1928 book Der Logische Aufbau der Welt through to the mid to late 1930’s has tended to view Carnap as espousing a form of conventionalism (epitomized by his adoption of the principle of tolerance) and not a form of empirical foundationalism. On this view, it follows that Carnap’s 1934 The Logical Syntax of Language is the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  42
    Karl R. Popper. The demarcation between science and metaphysics. A reprint of XXXVI 533. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 183–226. - John G. Kemeny. Carnap's theory of probability and induction. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 711–738. - Arthur W. Burks. On the significance of Carnap's system of inductive logic for the philosophy of induction. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living philosophers, vol. 11, Open Court, La Salle, Ill., and Cambridge University Press, London, 1963, pp. 739–759. - Hilary Putnam. “Degree of confirmation” and inductive logic. The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp, The library of living. [REVIEW]Richard C. Jeffrey - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):631-633.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  73
    Variety and analogy in confirmation theory.Peter Achinstein - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (3):207-221.
    Confirmation theorists seek to define a function that will take into account the various factors relevant in determining the degree to which an hypothesis is confirmed by its evidence. Among confirmation theorists, only Rudolf Carnap has constructed a system which purports to consider factors in addition to the number of instances, viz. the variety manifested by the instances and the amount of analogy between the instances. It is the purpose of this paper to examine the problem which these (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11.  29
    From Russell’s Logical Atomism to Carnap’s Aufbau: Reinterpreting the Classic and Modern Theories on the Subject.Henrique Ribeiro - 2001 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 8:305-318.
    The theme of this paper was inspired by studies related to the subject of my doctoral dissertation,1 and, more specifically, by the work of A. Richardson and M. Friedman on the same subject presented in their two recently published books.2 The material in these books which addresses the connection between Russell and Carnap’s Der logische Aufbau der Welt reveals the same basic perspective in both authors and, in fact, represents the first in depth enquiry of this connection, despite certain fairly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  28
    Carnap’s First Philosophy.Hiram Caton - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):623 - 659.
    The empiricist bent of philosophy of science and epistemology over the past four decades has recently been challenged, partly by arguments that exploit the uncertainty about what precisely the given is. It is claimed that this uncertainty stems from the fact that all observation is theory-laden; different "enities" [[sic]] are said to be observed as the theory constituting them is varied. Observations therefore do not test theories. So-called tests are really circular arguments, if they confirm the theory, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Carnap’s dream: Gödel, Wittgenstein, and Logical, Syntax.S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2007 - Synthese 159 (1):23-45.
    In Carnap’s autobiography, he tells the story how one night in January 1931, “the whole theory of language structure” in all its ramifications “came to [him] like a vision”. The shorthand manuscript he produced immediately thereafter, he says, “was the first version” of Logical Syntax of Language. This document, which has never been examined since Carnap’s death, turns out not to resemble Logical Syntax at all, at least on the surface. Wherein, then, did the momentous insight of 21 January (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  14.  9
    Analytical Truths in R. Carnap’s Theory and in Natural Language.Petr S. Kusliy & Andrey A. Veretennikov - 2024 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 61 (1):184-201.
    The article presents a critical semantic analysis of the so-called analytical truths as they were discussed by R. Carnap and building on some new empirical data that are not fully satisfactorily explained by Carnap’s theory. A theoretical reconstruction of Carnap’s theory of analytical truths is proposed. It is demonstrated how his understanding of analytical truths, as statements that are true in all possible worlds and amenable to a quite obvious definition on a par with the concepts of sense (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Carnap, completeness, and categoricity:The gabelbarkeitssatz OF 1928. [REVIEW]S. Awodey & A. W. Carus - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (2):145-172.
    In 1929 Carnap gave a paper in Prague on Investigations in General Axiomatics; a briefsummary was published soon after. Its subject lookssomething like early model theory, and the mainresult, called the Gabelbarkeitssatz, appears toclaim that a consistent set of axioms is complete justif it is categorical. This of course casts doubt onthe entire project. Though there is no furthermention of this theorem in Carnap''s publishedwritings, his Nachlass includes a largetypescript on the subject, Investigations inGeneral Axiomatics. We examine this work (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  16. Some problems for bayesian confirmation theory.Charles S. Chihara - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (4):551-560.
  17.  75
    Cancer Patients' Perception of Being or Not Being Confirmed.Dagfinn Nåden & Berit Sæteren - 2006 - Nursing Ethics 13 (3):222-235.
    The aim of this study was to obtain in-depth knowledge about caring confirmation of patients with cancer, from the patients’ point of view. The research topic was: what is the significance for patients of their being confirmed by nursing personnel? Fifteen men and women between 43 and 80 years of age participated in this study. The method of data collection used was qualitative research interviewing. A hermeneutic approach was used to interpret the data, in which Kvale’s self-perception, the ‘common (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. Logical Positivism and Carnap's Confirmability on the Meaningfulness of Religious Language.Alberto Oya - 2018 - Espíritu 67 (155):243-249.
    Due to their acceptance of the verifiability principle, the only way left for logical positivists to argue for the meaningfulness of religious language was to accept some sort of emotivistic conception of it or to reduce it to the description of religious attitude. The verifiability principle, however, suffers from some severe limitations that make it inadequate as a criterion for cognitive meaning. To resolve these problems, logical positivists gave up the requirement of conclusive verifiability and defended a sort of ‘liberalization’ (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. SWINBURNE, R. "An Introduction to Confirmation Theory". [REVIEW]S. Blackburn - 1975 - Mind 84:146.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  15
    Induction, probabilités et confirmation chez Carnap.Samir Boukhris - 2006 - Revue de Synthèse 127 (1):115-139.
    L'idée d'associer probabilité et induction n'est pas propre au xxe siècle, mais elle a reçu un développement systématique lorsque les philosophes néo-positivistes s'en sont emparés. Dès les années 1940, le philosophe Rudolf Carnap s'est proposé de relever le «défi humien» en fondant une théorie de la confirmation par la construction d'une logique probabiliste dite «inductive». Ce projet avait été esquissé à Cambridge dans les années 1920 par l'économiste John M. Keynes. Examiner le programme de Carnap dans sa totalité, le (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The problem with p-rules Thomas Oberdan clemson university.Carnap'S. Conventionalism - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1):119-137.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  56
    Confirming universal generalizations.S. L. Zabell - 1996 - Erkenntnis 45 (2-3):267-283.
    The purpose of this paper is to make a simple observation regarding the Johnson -Carnap continuum of inductive methods. From the outset, a common criticism of this continuum was its failure to permit the confirmation of universal generalizations: that is, if an event has unfailingly occurred in the past, the failure of the continuum to give some weight to the possibility that the event will continue to occur without fail in the future. The Johnson -Carnap continuum is the mathematical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Normativity and Instrumentalism in David Lewis’ Convention.S. M. Amadae - 2011 - History of European Ideas 37 (3):325-335.
    David Lewis presented Convention as an alternative to the conventionalism characteristic of early-twentieth-century analytic philosophy. Rudolf Carnap is well known for suggesting the arbitrariness of any particular linguistic convention for engaging in scientific inquiry. Analytic truths are self-consistent, and are not checked against empirical facts to ascertain their veracity. In keeping with the logical positivists before him, Lewis concludes that linguistic communication is conventional. However, despite his firm allegiance to conventions underlying not just languages but also social customs, he pioneered (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24. Experiment, observation and the confirmation of laws.S. Okasha - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):222-232.
    It is customary to distinguish experimental from purely observational sciences. The former include physics and molecular biology, the latter astronomy and palaeontology. Experiments involve actively intervening in the course of nature, as opposed to observing events that would have happened anyway. When a molecular biologist inserts viral DNA into a bacterium in his laboratory, this is an experiment; but when an astronomer points his telescope at the heavens, this is an observation. Without the biologist’s handiwork the bacterium would never have (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25.  6
    Heterodox Probability Theory.Peter Forrest - 2006 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 582–594.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Bayesian Orthodoxy Idealization Two Approaches to a Theory of Probability Adjustment for Nonclassical Logics Carnap's Confirmation Theory Proportional Syllogisms Kyburg's Fuzzy Probabilities Levi's Indeterminate Systems Qualitative Theories of Probability The Dynamics of Subjective Probability Probability Theory and Quantum Theory.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  40
    On simplicity in empirical hypotheses.S. F. Barker - 1961 - Philosophy of Science 28 (2):162-171.
    The title of this symposium, “Formal Simplicity as a Weight in the Acceptability of Scientific Theories,” to some people might seem to suggest that we are to be making positive proposals about how the concept of simplicity could be defined for formalized languages, defined so as to figure in a formalized theory of confirmation. I must confess at the start that I do not have any such ambitious object in view. I now feel, indeed, that premature formalizations have (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27.  94
    A parametric analysis of prospect theory’s functionals for the general population.Adam S. Booij, Bernard M. S. van Praag & Gijs van de Kuilen - 2010 - Theory and Decision 68 (1-2):115-148.
    This article presents the results of an experiment that completely measures the utility function and probability weighting function for different positive and negative monetary outcomes, using a representative sample of N = 1,935 from the general public. The results confirm earlier findings in the lab, suggesting that utility is less pronounced than what is found in classical measurements where expected utility is assumed. Utility for losses is found to be convex, consistent with diminishing sensitivity, and the obtained loss-aversion coefficient of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  28.  28
    The Aristotelianism of Locke's Politics.J. S. Maloy - 2009 - Journal of the History of Ideas 70 (2):235-257.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Aristotelianism of Locke's PoliticsJ. S. MaloyThose, then, who think that the positions of statesman, king, household manager, and master of slaves are the same are not correct. For they hold that each of these differs not innly in whether the subjects ruled are few or many... the assumption being that there is no difference between a large household and a small city-state.... But these claims are not true.Aristotle, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  2
    On Seeing Long Shadows: Is Academic Medicine at its Core a Practice of Racial Oppression?Thomas S. Huddle - forthcoming - HEC Forum:1-19.
    Suggestions that academic medicine is systemically racist are increasingly common in the medical literature. Such suggestions often rely upon expansive notions of systemic racism that are deeply controversial. The author argues for an empirical concept of systemic racism and offers a counter argument to a recent suggestion that academic medicine is systemically racist in its treatment of medical trainees: Anderson et al.’s (Academic Medicine, 98(8S), S28–S36, 2023) “The Long Shadow: a Historical Perspective on Racism in Medical Education.” Contra the authors (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Herbert G. Bohnert.Carnap'S. Logicism - 1975 - In Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist: Materials and Perspectives. D. Reidel Pub. Co.. pp. 73--183.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Richard C. Jeffrey.Carnap'S.. Inductive Logic - 1975 - In Jaakko Hintikka (ed.), Rudolf Carnap, Logical Empiricist: Materials and Perspectives. D. Reidel Pub. Co.. pp. 73--325.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  22
    Logicism, Pragmatism, and Metascience: Towards a Pancritical Pragmatic Theory of Meta-Level Discourse.G. S. Axtell - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:39 - 49.
    The faults of logical empiricist accounts of metascientific discourse are examined through a study of the modifications Carnap makes to his version of the program over four decades. As empiricists acquiesced on the distinction between theory and observation, Carnap attempted to retain and insulate an equally suspect sharp distinction between the theoretic and the pragmatic. Carnap's later philosophy was understood as a modification of the program in the direction of pragmatism. But neither the key notion of "external questions" (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  23
    Carnap's internal and external questions: Part I: Quine's criticisms.I. Carnap'S. Distinctions - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--97.
  34. Predicting the unpredictable.S. L. Zabell - 1992 - Synthese 90 (2):205-232.
    A major difficulty for currently existing theories of inductive inference involves the question of what to do when novel, unknown, or previously unsuspected phenomena occur. In this paper one particular instance of this difficulty is considered, the so-called sampling of species problem.The classical probabilistic theories of inductive inference due to Laplace, Johnson, de Finetti, and Carnap adopt a model of simple enumerative induction in which there are a prespecified number of types or species which may be observed. But, realistically, this (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  35. Operationalism and ordinary language: A critique of Wittgenstein.Charles S. Chihara & Jerry A. Fodor - 1965 - American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (4):281-95.
    This paper explores some lines of argument in wittgenstein's post-Tractatus writings in order to indicate the relations between wittgenstein's philosophical psychology, On the one hand, And his philosophy of language, His epistemology, And his doctrines about the nature of philosophical analysis on the other. The authors maintain that the later writings of wittgenstein express a coherent doctrine in which an operationalistic analysis of confirmation and language supports a philosophical psychology of a type the authors call "logical behaviorism." they also (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  36. Acceptibility, Evidence, and Severity.Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay & Gordon G. Brittan - 2006 - Synthese 148 (2):259-293.
    The notion of a severe test has played an important methodological role in the history of science. But it has not until recently been analyzed in any detail. We develop a generally Bayesian analysis of the notion, compare it with Deborah Mayo’s error-statistical approach by way of sample diagnostic tests in the medical sciences, and consider various objections to both. At the core of our analysis is a distinction between evidence and confirmation or belief. These notions must be kept (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  7
    Vaught’s conjecture for almost chainable theories.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):991-1005.
    A structure ${\mathbb Y}$ of a relational language L is called almost chainable iff there are a finite set $F \subset Y$ and a linear order $\,<$ on the set $Y\setminus F$ such that for each partial automorphism $\varphi $ of the linear order $\langle Y\setminus F, <\rangle $ the mapping $\mathop {\mathrm {id}}\nolimits _F \cup \varphi $ is a partial automorphism of ${\mathbb Y}$. By theorems of Fraïssé and Pouzet, an infinite structure ${\mathbb Y}$ is almost chainable iff the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  14
    Theory of Colours. [REVIEW]S. P. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (2):352-353.
    The papers comprising Zur Farbenlehre, best known portion of Goethe's writings on color and optics, appeared between 1808 and 1810. Portions of Zur Farbenlehre, translated by the painter Charles Lock Eastlake and frequently reprinted under the title Theory of Colours, achieved immediate notoriety because of Goethe's insistent questioning of Newton's methodology. Acknowledging no mentors except Theophrastus and the physicist Robert Boyle, Goethe compared the Newtonian theory of colors--indelicately, some think--to a once proud castle still revered long after it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Contrast, inference and scientific realism.Mark Day & George S. Botterill - 2008 - Synthese 160 (2):249-267.
    The thesis of underdetermination presents a major obstacle to the epistemological claims of scientific realism. That thesis is regularly assumed in the philosophy of science, but is puzzlingly at odds with the actual history of science, in which empirically adequate theories are thin on the ground. We propose to advance a case for scientific realism which concentrates on the process of scientific reasoning rather than its theoretical products. Developing an account of causal–explanatory inference will make it easier to resist the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  40. Statistical Inference and the Plethora of Probability Paradigms: A Principled Pluralism.Mark L. Taper, Gordon Brittan Jr & Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay - manuscript
    The major competing statistical paradigms share a common remarkable but unremarked thread: in many of their inferential applications, different probability interpretations are combined. How this plays out in different theories of inference depends on the type of question asked. We distinguish four question types: confirmation, evidence, decision, and prediction. We show that Bayesian confirmation theory mixes what are intuitively “subjective” and “objective” interpretations of probability, whereas the likelihood-based account of evidence melds three conceptions of what constitutes an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  3
    A framework for the analysis of self-confirming policies.P. Battigalli, S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci & T. Sargent - 2022 - Theory and Decision 92 (3-4):455-512.
    This paper provides a general framework for analyzing self-confirming policies. We study self-confirming equilibria in recurrent decision problems with incomplete information about the true stochastic model. We characterize stationary monetary policies in a linear-quadratic setting.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Davidson, Analyticity, and Theory Confirmation.Nathaniel Jason Goldberg - 2003 - Dissertation, Georgetown University
    In this dissertation, I explore the work of Donald Davidson, reveal an inconsistency in it, and resolve that inconsistency in a way that complements a debate in philosophy of science. In Part One, I explicate Davidson's extensional account of meaning; though not defending Davidson from all objections, I nonetheless present his seemingly disparate views as a coherent whole. In Part Two, I explicate Davidson's views on the dualism between conceptual schemes and empirical content, isolating four seemingly different arguments that Davidson (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  28
    Local Explanations via Necessity and Sufficiency: Unifying Theory and Practice.David S. Watson, Limor Gultchin, Ankur Taly & Luciano Floridi - 2022 - Minds and Machines 32 (1):185-218.
    Necessity and sufficiency are the building blocks of all successful explanations. Yet despite their importance, these notions have been conceptually underdeveloped and inconsistently applied in explainable artificial intelligence, a fast-growing research area that is so far lacking in firm theoretical foundations. In this article, an expanded version of a paper originally presented at the 37th Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence, we attempt to fill this gap. Building on work in logic, probability, and causality, we establish the central role of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  21
    Challenge and Response. [REVIEW]S. C. A. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (2):373-374.
    This is a challenging and original work on the concept of justification and its application to ethical statements. The book divides into two parts. The first part is devoted to a systematic treatment of the nature of justification. It begins with a critical rejection of the deductive model. Wellman presents plausible arguments for the existence of non-deductive evidences in ethics and shows how ethical theories can be tested by "thought-experiment" as analogous to the confirmation of scientific theories by laboratory (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  75
    Does Quantum Cognition Imply Quantum Minds?S. Gao - 2021 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 28 (3-4):100-111.
    Quantum cognition is a new theoretical framework for constructing cognitive models based on the mathematical principles of quantum theory. Due to its increasing empirical success, one wonders what it tells us about the underlying process of cognition. Does it imply that we have quantum minds and there is some sort of quantum structure in the brain? In this paper, I address this important issue by using a new result in the research of quantum foundations. Based on the PBR theorem (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  35
    An appraisal of Glymour's confirmation theory.Paul Horwich - 1978 - Journal of Philosophy 75 (2):98-113.
  47.  17
    Incommensurability: The scaling of mind-body theories as a counter example.Sam S. Rakover - 1989 - Behaviorism 17 (2):103-118.
    An opponent thesis to that of incommensurability—the commensurability approach—is proposed. The new thesis is based on the delineation of an empirical comparative metatheory for comparing theories of different paradigms. The method of multidimensional scaling together with the proximity-predictability hypothesis instantiate and substantiate this metatheory. The scaling of mind body theories, and the confirmation of certain predictions derived from MDS and the PP hypothesis concerning the relations that exist among these theories, are brought as actual examples supporting the present paper's (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  14
    A Novel Discrete-Time Leslie–Gower Model with the Impact of Allee Effect in Predator Population.S. Vinoth, R. Sivasamy, K. Sathiyanathan, B. Unyong, R. Vadivel & Nallappan Gunasekaran - 2022 - Complexity 2022:1-21.
    The discrete-time system has more complex and chaotic dynamical behaviors as compared to the continuous-time system. This paper extends a discrete Leslie–Gower predator-prey system with the Allee effect in the predator’s population, whose dynamics are analyzed and explored. We have determined the equilibrium points and studied their local stability properties. We find that the system undergoes flip bifurcation and Neimark–Sacker bifurcation around the interior equilibrium point by choosing the Allee parameter as a bifurcation parameter. We discuss the stability and direction (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. answering Some Objections To Scientific Realism.S. Hood - 2002 - Florida Philosophical Review 2 (2):73-83.
    Scientific realism is, roughly, the thesis according to which science is an epistemically progressive enterprise and current well-confirmed theories are at least approximately true. Putnam has argued that scientific realism is the only philosophy of science that does not make the success of science a miracle. This “explanationist” defense of scientific realism has come under attack by philosophers such as Arthur Fine, Chuang Liu, and Putnam himself. In this paper, I defend the explanationist defense against some of these objections.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Logic of Confirmation and Theory Assessment.Franz Huber - 2005 - In L. Behounek & M. Bilkova (eds.), The Logica Yearbook. Filosofia.
    This paper discusses an almost sixty year old problem in the philosophy of science -- that of a logic of confirmation. We present a new analysis of Carl G. Hempel's conditions of adequacy (Hempel 1945), differing from the one Carnap gave in §87 of his Logical Foundations of Probability (1962). Hempel, it is argued, felt the need for two concepts of confirmation: one aiming at true theories and another aiming at informative theories. However, he also realized that these (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 994