Switch to: References

Citations of:

Meaning

Oxford,: Clarendon Press (1972)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Gaps in Harley's argument on evolutionarily stable learning rules and in the logic of “tit for tat”.Reinhard Selten & Peter Hammerstein - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):115.
  • Joint attention, collective knowledge, and the "we" perspective.Axel Seemann - 2007 - Social Epistemology 21 (3):217 – 230.
    In this paper, I am concerned with the practical aspect of joint attention. In particular, I ask what enables us to engage in joint activities, and go on to suggest that on a representational account of joint attention, this question cannot be satisfactorily answered. I explore John Campbell's "relational" approach and suggest that if one couples it with Peter Hobson's notion of "feeling perception", one may be in a position to account for the action-enabling aspect of joint engagements. This approach (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Indexicals and the theory of reference.Stephen Schiffer - 1981 - Synthese 49 (1):43--100.
  • Social habits and enlightened cooperation: Do humans measure up to Lewis conventions? [REVIEW]Eike Savigny - 1985 - Erkenntnis 22 (1-3):79-96.
  • Rationality as an explanation of language?Stuart J. Russell - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):730.
  • There is more than one way to access an image.Lynn C. Robertson - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):568.
  • Meaning and Mindreading.J. Robert Thompson - 2014 - Mind and Language 29 (2):167-200.
    In this article, I defend Neo-Gricean accounts of language and communication from an objection about linguistic development. According to this objection, children are incapable of understanding the minds of others in the way that Neo-Gricean accounts require until long after they learn the meanings of words, are able to produce meaningful utterances, and understand the meaningful utterances of others. In answering this challenge, I outline exactly what sorts of psychological states are required by Neo-Gricean accounts and conclude that there is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Meaning, belief, and language acquisition.Mark Risjord - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (4):465-475.
    A very plausible and common view of meaning supposes that linguistic meaning is to be understood in terms of speakers' intentions. This program proposes to analyse the meaning of a sentence in terms of what speakers mean by or in uttering it; and this speaker meaning in turn is to be analysed in terms of the speaker's intentions. This essay argues that intention-based semantics cannot provide an adequate analysis of linguistic meaning: not because of contrived counterexamples, nor because it conflicts (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • B. F. Skinner's operationism.Jon D. Ringen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):567.
  • Convergence, Community, and Force in Aesthetic Discourse.Nick Riggle - 2021 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 8 (47).
    Philosophers often characterize discourse in general as aiming at some sort of convergence (in beliefs, plans, dispositions, feelings, etc.), and many views about aesthetic discourse in particular affirm this thought. I argue that a convergence norm does not govern aesthetic discourse. The conversational dynamics of aesthetic discourse suggest that typical aesthetic claims have directive force. I distinguish between dynamic and illocutionary force and develop related theories of each for aesthetic discourse. I argue that the illocutionary force of aesthetic utterances is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Common Knowledge and Davis's Argument from Symmetry in the Prisoner's Dilemma.Richard Reiner - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (2):281-.
  • Literalness and other pragmatic principles.François Recanati - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):729-730.
  • The relevance of Relevance for fiction.Anne Reboul - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):729.
  • Problems for testimonial acquaintance.Michael J. Raven - 2008 - Noûs 42 (4):727-745.
    We think about and refer to things that we’ve never perceived or experienced. This paper bears on how this could be. Someone is testimonially acquainted with something just in case the explanation of one’s ability to think de re thoughts about it essentially appeals to communication with others who already have that ability. The main motivation for the claim that testimonial acquaintance is possible is that it best explains how we can think de re about and refer to things we’ve (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Game theory without rationality.Anatol Rapoport - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):114.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental, yes. Private, no.Howard Rachlin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):566.
  • Learning rules and learning rules.Howard Rachlin - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):113.
  • Party Politics and Democratic Disagreement.Maura Priest - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (1):1-13.
    Political parties seem inclined to dogmatism. Understanding party politics via a plural-subject account of collective belief explains this phenomenon. It explains inter-party outrage at slight deviations from the party line and dogged refusals to compromise. It also aligns with an alternative theory of political representation. I argue that party dogmatism is unlikely to change and can be a democratic good. I conclude that not parties but patriots counteract the democratic ills of dogmatic party politics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Characterizing spontaneous inferences.Guy Politzer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):177-178.
  • Law and Conversational Implicatures.Francesca Poggi - 2011 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 24 (1):21-40.
    This essay investigates the applicability of Grice’s theory of conversational implicatures to legal interpretation, in order to highlight some of its characteristics. After introducing the notions of language and discourse, and briefly explaining the most salient aspects of Grice’s theory, I will analyse the interpretation of two types of legal acts; authoritative legal acts and acts of private autonomy. Regarding the first class, exemplified by statutes, I will argue against the applicability of Gricean theory due to the conflictual behaviour of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Hunting memes.H. C. Plotkin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):768-769.
  • Logic, reference, and mentalism.Ullin T. Place - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):565.
  • Modified Occam’s Razor.Ben Phillips - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (2):371-382.
    According to the principle Grice calls 'Modified Occam's Razor' (MOR), 'Senses are not to be multiplied beyond necessity'. More carefully, MOR says that if there are distinct ways in which an expression is regularly used, then, all other things being equal, we should favour the view that the expression is unambiguous and that certain uses of it can be explained in pragmatic terms. In this paper I argue that MOR cannot have the central role that is typically assigned to it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Inference and information.Philip Pettit - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):727.
  • An inferentialist approach to semantics: Time for a new kind of structuralism?Jaroslav Peregrin - 2008 - Philosophy Compass 3 (6):1208-1223.
    The perennial question – What is meaning? – receives many answers. In this paper I present and discuss inferentialism – a recent approach to semantics based on the thesis that to have ( such and such ) a meaning is to be governed by ( such and such ) a cluster of inferential rules . I point out that this thesis presupposes that looking for meaning requires seeing language as a social institution (rather than, say, a psychological reality). I also (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Interpersonal self-consciousness.Christopher Peacocke - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (1):1-24.
    If one were to write a book titled TheVarieties of Self-Consciousness, one would start off with some distinctions. It will help to locate my topic in relation to those distinctions.The first distinction concerns that kind of self-consciousness which involves only the minimal ability on the part of a subject to self-represent, to be in mental states with first person content, be it conceptual or nonconceptual. This minimal ability involves very little as compared with the more sophisticated states of which humans (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The epistemic core of weak joint action.Cedric Paternotte - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology (1):1-24.
    Over the last three decades, joint action has received various definitions, which for all their differences share many features. However, they cannot fit some perplexing cases of weak joint action, such as demonstrations, where agents rely on distinct epistemic sources, and as a result, have no first-hand knowledge about each other. I argue that one major reason why the definition of such collective actions is akin to the classical ones is that it crucially relies on the concept of common knowledge. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Being realistic about common knowledge: a Lewisian approach.Cedric Paternotte - 2011 - Synthese 183 (2):249-276.
    Defined and formalized several decades ago, widely used in philosophy and game theory, the concept of common knowledge is still considered as problematic, although not always for the right reasons. I suggest that the epistemic status of a group of human agents in a state of common knowledge has not been thoroughly analyzed. In particular, every existing account of common knowledge, whether formal or not, is either too strong to fit cognitively limited individuals, or too weak to adequately describe their (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Communication and strategic inference.Prashant Parikh - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (5):473 - 514.
  • On Defining Communicative Intentions.François Recanati - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (3):213-41.
  • Paul Grice and the philosophy of language.Stephen Neale - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (5):509 - 559.
    The work of the late Paul Grice (1913–1988) exerts a powerful influence on the way philosophers, linguists, and cognitive scientists think about meaning and communication. With respect to a particular sentence φ and an “utterer” U, Grice stressed the philosophical importance of separating (i) what φ means, (ii) what U said on a given occasion by uttering φ, and (iii) what U meant by uttering φ on that occasion. Second, he provided systematic attempts to say precisely what meaning is by (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • On skinner's radical operationism.J. Moore - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):564.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Apes have mimetic culture.Robert W. Mitchell & H. Lyn Miles - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):768-768.
  • Co-ordination, salience and rationality.Seumas Miller - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (3):359-370.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Difference of Some Consequence Between Conventions and Rules.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 2008 - Topoi 27 (1-2):87-99.
    Lewis’s view of the way conventions are passed on may have some especially interesting consequences for the study of language. I’ll start by briefly discussing agreements and disagreements that I have with Lewis’s general views on conventions and then turn to how linguistic conventions spread. I’ll compare views of main stream generative linguistics, in particular, Chomsky’s views on how syntactic forms are passed on, with the sort of view of language acquisition and language change advocated by usage-based or construction grammars, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Radical behaviorism and mental events: Four methodological queries.Paul E. Meehl - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):563.
  • How to do things with things other than just words.Alec McHoul - 2002 - Semiotica 2002 (142).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is matching behavior an evolutionary inevitability?James E. Mazur - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):112.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The End of the Theory of Meaning.Mark Johnston - 1988 - Mind and Language 3 (1):28-42.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On convention.Andrei Marmor - 1996 - Synthese 107 (3):349 - 371.
    Following the pioneering work of David Lewis, many philosophers believe that the rationale of following a convention consists in the fact that conventions are solutions to recurrent coordination problems. Margaret Gilbert has criticised this view, offering an alternative account of the nature of conventions and their normative aspect. In this paper I argue that Gilbert's criticism of Lewis and her alternative suggestions rest on serious misunderstandings. As between these two opposed views, Lewis's is closer to the truth, but I argue (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Correct data base: Wrong model?Alexander Marshack - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):767-768.
  • Evolutionary game theory: Suddenly it's 1960!John C. Malone - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):112.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lessons from evolution for artificial intelligence?Rudi Lutz - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):766-766.
  • The flight from human behavior.C. Fergus Lowe - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):562.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is it possible to be optimal?A. W. Logue - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):111.
  • Uncommon Knowledge.Harvey Lederman - 2018 - Mind 127 (508):1069-1105.
    Some people commonly know a proposition just in case they all know it, they all know that they all know it, they all know that they all know that they all know it, and so on. They commonly believe a proposition just in case they all believe it, they all believe that they all believe it, they all believe that they all believe that they all believe it, and so on. A long tradition in economic theory, theoretical computer science, linguistics (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Optimization and flexibility.S. E. G. Lea & S. M. Dow - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):110.
  • Language equals mimesis plus speech.Aarre Laakso - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):765-766.
  • An explanatory theory of communicative intentions.S. -Y. Kuroda - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (6):655 - 681.
  • A formal theory of speech acts.S. -Y. Kuroda - 1986 - Linguistics and Philosophy 9 (4):495 - 524.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation