Results for 'Miller, Timothy D.'

(not author) ( search as author name )
987 found
Order:
  1.  60
    Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes.Richard E. Nisbett & Timothy D. Wilson - 1977 - Psychological Review; Psychological Review 84 (3):231.
  2.  32
    Tomoka Takeuchi, Robert D. Ogilvie, Anthony V. Ferrelli, Timothy I. Murphy, and Kathy Belicki.Kelly A. Forrest, Craig Kunimoto, Jeff Miller, Harold Pashler, J. G. Taylor & Valerie Hardcastle - 2001 - Consciousness and Cognition 10:158.
  3. Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconscious.Timothy D. Wilson - 2002 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  4.  51
    Contrasting approaches to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):125-139.
    The general process view of learning, which guided research into learning for the first half of this century, has come under attack in recent years from several quarters. One form of criticism has come from proponents of the so-called biological boundaries approach to learning. These theorists have presented a variety of data showing that supposedly general laws of learning may in fact be limited in their applicability to different species and learning tasks, and they argue that the limitations are drawn (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  5. An Examination of the Psychopathic Personality Inventory’s Nomological Network: A Meta-Analytic Review.Joshua D. Miller & Donald R. Lynam - 2012 - Personality Disorders: Theory, Research, and Treatment 3 (3):305–326.
    Since its publication, the Psychopathic Personality Inventory and its revision (Lilien- feld & Andrews, 1996; Lilienfeld & Widows, 2005) have become increasingly popular such that it is now among the most frequently used self-report inventories for the assessment of psychopathy. The current meta-analysis examined the relations between the two PPI factors (factor 1: Fearless Dominance; factor 2: Self-Centered Impulsivity), as well as their relations with other validated measures of psychopathy, internalizing and externalizing forms of psychopathology, general personality traits, and antisocial (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6. Scientific Realism and the Pessimistic Meta-Modus Tollens.Timothy D. Lyons - 2010 - In S. Clarke & T. D. Lyons (eds.), Recent Themes in the Philosophy of Science: Scientific Realism and Commonsense. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 63-90.
    Broadly speaking, the contemporary scientific realist is concerned to justify belief in what we might call theoretical truth, which includes truth based on ampliative inference and truth about unobservables. Many, if not most, contemporary realists say scientific realism should be treated as ‘an overarching scientific hypothesis’ (Putnam 1978, p. 18). In its most basic form, the realist hypothesis states that theories enjoying general predictive success are true. This hypothesis becomes a hypothesis to be tested. To justify our belief in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  7. Scientific Realism.Timothy D. Lyons - 2014 - In Paul Humphreys (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press. pp. 564-584.
    This article endeavors to identify the strongest versions of the two primary arguments against epistemic scientific realism: the historical argument—generally dubbed “the pessimistic meta-induction”—and the argument from underdetermination. It is shown that, contrary to the literature, both can be understood as historically informed but logically validmodus tollensarguments. After specifying the question relevant to underdetermination and showing why empirical equivalence is unnecessary, two types of competitors to contemporary scientific theories are identified, both of which are informed by science itself. With the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  8. Scientific realism and the stratagema de divide et impera.Timothy D. Lyons - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (3):537-560.
    In response to historical challenges, advocates of a sophisticated variant of scientific realism emphasize that theoretical systems can be divided into numerous constituents. Setting aside any epistemic commitment to the systems themselves, they maintain that we can justifiably believe those specific constituents that are deployed in key successful predictions. Stathis Psillos articulates an explicit criterion for discerning exactly which theoretical constituents qualify. I critique Psillos's criterion in detail. I then test the more general deployment realist intuition against a set of (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  9. Explaining the Success of a Scientific Theory.Timothy D. Lyons - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):891-901.
    Scientific realists have claimed that the posit that our theories are (approximately) true provides the best or the only explanation for their success . In response, I revive two non-realists explanations. I show that realists, in discarding them, have either misconstrued the phenomena to be explained or mischaracterized the relationship between these explanations and their own. I contend nonetheless that these non-realist competitors, as well as their realist counterparts, should be rejected; for none of them succeed in explaining a significant (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  10.  56
    Response to Open Peer Commentaries on “'Doctor, Would You Prescribe a Pill to Help Me…?'A National Survey of Physicians on Using Medicine for Human Enhancement”.Timothy D. Hotze, Kavita Shah, Emily E. Anderson & Matthew K. Wynia - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (1):W1 - W3.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  15
    Development and the origin of behavioral strategies.Timothy D. Johnston - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):108.
  12. Readings in philosophy of religion: ancient to contemporary.Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski & Timothy Miller (eds.) - 2009 - Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell.
    This anthology offers a comprehensive historical introduction to the central questions of philosophy of religion. Approximately two-thirds of the selections are from ancient, medieval, and modern sources, helping students to understand and engage the rich traditions of reflection on these timeless questions. The remaining contemporary readings introduce students to the more recent developments in the field. Each of the thematically arranged sections begins with an editor's introduction to clarify the central issues and positions presented in the readings that follow."--Book jacket.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  11
    The ends of Philosophy of Religion: Terminus and Telos.Timothy D. Knepper - 2013 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Knepper criticizes existing efforts in the philosophy of religion for being out of step with, and therefore useless to, the academic study of religion, then forwards a new program for philosophy of religion that is in step with, and therefore useful to, the academic study of religion.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14. Toward a Purely Axiological Scientific Realism.Timothy D. Lyons - 2005 - Erkenntnis 63 (2):167-204.
    The axiological tenet of scientific realism, “science seeks true theories,” is generally taken to rest on a corollary epistemological tenet, “we can justifiably believe that our successful theories achieve (or approximate) that aim.” While important debates have centered on, and have led to the refinement of, the epistemological tenet, the axiological tenet has suffered from neglect. I offer what I consider to be needed refinements to the axiological postulate. After showing an intimate relation between the refined postulate and ten theoretical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  15. Reading Plato’s Theaetetus.Timothy D. J. Chappell - 2004 - Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett Pub. Co.. Edited by Plato.
    Timothy Chappell’s new translation of the Theaetetus is presented here in short sections of text, each preceded by a summary of the argument and followed by his philosophical commentary on it. Introductory remarks discuss Plato and his works, his use of dialogue, the structure of the Theaetetus, and alternative interpretations of the work as a whole. A glossary and bibliography are provided.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16. Epistemic selectivity, historical threats, and the non-epistemic tenets of scientific realism.Timothy D. Lyons - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3203-3219.
    The scientific realism debate has now reached an entirely new level of sophistication. Faced with increasingly focused challenges, epistemic scientific realists have appropriately revised their basic meta-hypothesis that successful scientific theories are approximately true: they have emphasized criteria that render realism far more selective and, so, plausible. As a framework for discussion, I use what I take to be the most influential current variant of selective epistemic realism, deployment realism. Toward the identification of new case studies that challenge this form (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  7
    Philosophies of religion: a global and critical introduction.Timothy D. Knepper - 2022 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    In this global introduction to philosophy of religion you begin not with a single tradition, but with religious philosophies from East Asia, South Asia, West Africa, and Native North America, alongside the classical Abrahamic and modern European traditions. Matching this diversity of traditions, chapters are organized around questions that acknowledge there is no single understanding of any god or ultimate reality. Instead you approach six different traditions of philosophizing about religion by asking questions about the journeys of both the self (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  32
    Epigenesis and phylogenesis: Re-ordering the priorities.Timothy D. Johnston & Gilbert Gottlieb - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):243-244.
  19. Tom Farer and Timothy D. Sisk.Timothy D. Sisk - 2012 - In Timothy J. Sinclair (ed.), Global Governance. Polity Press. pp. 18--4.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. A Historically Informed Modus Ponens Against Scientific Realism: Articulation, Critique, and Restoration.Timothy D. Lyons - 2013 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 27 (4):369-392.
    There are two primary arguments against scientific realism, one pertaining to underdetermination, the other to the history of science. While these arguments are usually treated as altogether distinct, P. Kyle Stanford's ‘problem of unconceived alternatives’ constitutes one kind of synthesis: I propose that Stanford's argument is best understood as a broad modus ponens underdetermination argument, into which he has inserted a unique variant of the historical pessimistic induction. After articulating three criticisms against Stanford's argument and the evidence that he offers, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  21. Embodying difference: The making of burakumin in modern Japan.Timothy D. Amos - 2013 - Philosophy East and West 63 (2).
  22.  25
    Aristotle and Augustine on freedom: two theories of freedom, voluntary action, and akrasia.Timothy D. J. Chappell - 1995 - New York: St. Martin's Press.
  23. Structural realism versus deployment realism: A comparative evaluation.Timothy D. Lyons - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 59:95-105.
    In this paper I challenge and adjudicate between the two positions that have come to prominence in the scientific realism debate: deployment realism and structural realism. I discuss a set of cases from the history of celestial mechanics, including some of the most important successes in the history of science. To the surprise of the deployment realist, these are novel predictive successes toward which theoretical constituents that are now seen to be patently false were genuinely deployed. Exploring the implications for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  20
    An ecological approach to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):162-173.
  25. The Problem of Deep Competitors and the Pursuit of Epistemically Utopian Truths.Timothy D. Lyons - 2011 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 42 (2):317-338.
    According to standard scientific realism, science seeks truth and we can justifiably believe that our successful theories achieve, or at least approximate, that goal. In this paper, I discuss the implications of the following competitor thesis: Any theory we may favor has competitors such that we cannot justifiably deny that they are approximately true. After defending that thesis, I articulate three specific threats it poses for standard scientific realism; one is epistemic, the other two are axiological (that is, pertaining to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. History and the Contemporary Scientific Realism Debate.Timothy D. Lyons & Peter Vickers - 2021 - In Timothy D. Lyons & Peter Vickers (eds.), Contemporary Scientific Realism: The Challenge From the History of Science. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  27.  32
    Sounds exaggerate visual shape.Timothy D. Sweeny, Emmanuel Guzman-Martinez, Laura Ortega, Marcia Grabowecky & Satoru Suzuki - 2012 - Cognition 124 (2):194-200.
  28. Four Challenges to Epistemic Scientific Realism—and the Socratic Alternative.Timothy D. Lyons - 2018 - Spontaneous Generations 9 (1):146-150.
    Four Challenges to Epistemic Scientific Realism—and the Socratic Alternative.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  44
    A new look at anchoring effects: basic anchoring and its antecedents.Timothy D. Wilson, Christopher E. Houston, Kathryn M. Etling & Nancy Brekke - 1996 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 125 (4):387.
  30.  13
    Genes, interactions, and the development of behavior.Timothy D. Johnston & Laura Edwards - 2002 - Psychological Review 109 (1):26-34.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  31. Contemporary Scientific Realism: The Challenge From the History of Science.Timothy D. Lyons & Peter Vickers (eds.) - 2021 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Scientific realists claim we can justifiably believe that science is getting at the truth. But they have long faced historical challenges: various episodes across history appear to demonstrate that even strongly supported scientific theories can be overturned and left behind. In response, realists have developed new positions and arguments. As a result of specific challenges from the history of science, and realist responses, we find ourselves with an ever increasing data-set bearing on the (possible) relationship between science and truth. The (...)
  32. Evangelical Millennialism in the Trans-Atlantic World, 1500–2000.Timothy Miller - 2012 - Utopian Studies 23 (2):534-537.
    In 2011 an American Christian radio broadcaster named Harold Camping attracted massive media attention, and some actual following, for his prediction that on May 21 of that year Christ would return to earth and rapture away the faithful, carrying them heavenward, while the rest went through terrible earthly tribulations that would culminate five months later with the end of the world. It was not Camping's first exercise in date-setting; he had earlier published predictions of the end in 1988 and 1994. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    Architecture and Anarchism: Building without Authority.Timothy Miller - 2022 - Utopian Studies 33 (2):350-352.
    Visionary architecture is a longstanding part of utopianism, a tangible expression of the utopian imagination. Anarchism is also an essential element in the pantheon of utopian thought and action, since by its nature utopianism, in imagining a better way to be and do, inherently criticizes and undermines the dominant social order. In his latest book Paul Dobraszczyk explores examples of what he calls building without authority, building in a new and often startling fashion, typically contravening established architectural conventions, even if (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    A Foundational Bibliography for American Intentional Communities.Timothy Miller - 2020 - Utopian Studies 31 (2):443-452.
    Lyman Tower Sargent has been the preeminent scholar of utopianism in our time and has undertaken a diverse network of approaches to the study of what he has called “social dreaming.” He has written monographs, articles, and essays and has been a relentless compiler of information on utopianism heretofore largely overlooked by his peers. One of the main directions of his work has been bibliographical, as he has compiled guides to the vast corpus of utopianism that he has uncovered.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  28
    Dreaming the Biosphere: The Theater of All Possibilities (review).Timothy Miller - 2011 - Utopian Studies 22 (2):393-396.
  36.  25
    Aristotle on the Human Good.Timothy D. Roche & Richard Kraut - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):629.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37. Non‐competitor Conditions in the Scientific Realism Debate.Timothy D. Lyons - 2009 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 23 (1):65-84.
    A general insight of 20th-century philosophy of science is that the acceptance of a scientific theory is grounded, not merely on a theory's relation to data, but on its status as having no, or being superior to its, competitors. I explore the ways in which scientific realists might be thought to utilise this insight, have in fact utilised it, and can legitimately utilise it. In more detail, I point out that, barring a natural but mistaken characterisation of scientific realism, traditional (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  41
    Long-lasting effects of subliminal affective priming from facial expressions.Timothy D. Sweeny, Marcia Grabowecky, Satoru Suzuki & Ken A. Paller - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (4):929-938.
    Unconscious processing of stimuli with emotional content can bias affective judgments. Is this subliminal affective priming merely a transient phenomenon manifested in fleeting perceptual changes, or are long-lasting effects also induced? To address this question, we investigated memory for surprise faces 24 h after they had been shown with 30-ms fearful, happy, or neutral faces. Surprise faces subliminally primed by happy faces were initially rated as more positive, and were later remembered better, than those primed by fearful or neutral faces. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  74
    Did Aristotle have the concept of identity?Fred D. Miller - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (4):483-490.
  40. Systematicity theory meets Socratic scientific realism: the systematic quest for truth.Timothy D. Lyons - 2019 - Synthese 196 (3):833-861.
    Systematicity theory—developed and articulated by Paul Hoyningen-Huene—and scientific realism constitute separate encompassing and empirical accounts of the nature of science. Standard scientific realism asserts the axiological thesis that science seeks truth and the epistemological thesis that we can justifiably believe our successful theories at least approximate that aim. By contrast, questions pertaining to truth are left “outside” systematicity theory’s “intended scope” ; the scientific realism debate is “simply not” its “focus”. However, given the continued centrality of that debate in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. Aristotle's Politics Reconsidered.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Assesses the presuppositions underlying Aristotle's political theory. The principle of teleology holds that human beings strive to fulfil certain natural ends such as rationality and social cooperation; the principle of perfectionism holds that the good for human beings consists in the attainment of these ends; the principle of community holds that individuals can attain the good only if they are subject to the authority of the community, including the state ; and the principle of rulership holds that the community can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  13
    At the Centre of Kierkegaard: An objective absurdity.E. D. L. Miller - 1997 - Religious Studies 33 (4):433-441.
    No one doubts that Kierkegaard's Concluding Unscientific Postscript is one of the most important, one of the most artistically contrived, and certainly one of the wittiest works in the history of philosophy. Further, the Postscript has often been accorded a kind of centrality in the Kierkegaardian corpus. Kierkegaard himself seems to have assigned it some such role. He informs the reader in the ‘First and Last Declaration’ that he originally intended the Postscript to be his last word before retiring from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Constitutions and Political Rights.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle's constitutional theory applies his theory of justice and rights to the unifying institutions of the polis. He defines a citizen as one who has a liberty right to partake in deliberative or judicial office. He distinguishes between constitutions in terms of whether they are correct or deviant and on the basis of whether political rights are assigned to one, few, or many persons––resulting in a six‐fold classification of constitutions: kingship versus tyranny, aristocracy versus oligarchy, and polity versus democracy. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Deviant Constitutions.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In addition to his study of correct constitutions, Aristotle investigated the entire spectrum of regimes existing in his day. Aristotle believes that it is a proper task for politics and legislation to deal with deviant or imperfect constitutions such as oligarchy and democracy. In seeking to preserve and reform imperfect constitutions and prevent revolution, Aristotle employs a maxim of superiority: that the part of the polis that supports the constitution ought to be superior to the part that does not. Although (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Justice.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Justice is central to Aristotle's political theory because he holds that all constitutions are a form of justice. In so far as it is just in the universal sense, the constitution aims at the happiness of the political community; in so far as it is just in the particular sense of distributive justice, the constitution assigns rights to offices, property, or honours to the citizens in accordance with their worth. Aristotle also claims that political justice is partly natural and partly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Nature and Politics.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle's politics may be characterized as ‘naturalistic’, in the sense that it assigns a fundamental role to the concept of nature in the explanation and evaluation of the political community. Aristotle's naturalism is summed up in three claims: the polis exists by nature, human beings are by nature political animals, and the polis is by nature prior to the individual. Aristotle has been accused of inconsistency because he also asserts that the human lawgiver brings the polis into existence. This chapter, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Property Rights.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Supports Ernest Barker's interpretation that Aristotle offers a ‘vindication of the right of private property.’ Although Aristotle emphasizes the common interests of the citizens, he also provides a place for private property in all of his constitutions, including the best constitution. The chapter argues that Aristotle gives a basic account of property ownership that is similar to modern concepts of property rights. He offers justifications of private property, states conditions under which property may be justly acquired, defends private property against (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Rights.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Although past commentators saw Aristotle as recognizing the rights of individuals, recent interpreters have objected that no single Greek word corresponds to the modern word ‘rights’. In reply, it is shown with evidence from Aristotle and other writers that the ancient Greek discourse of law and politics included distinct locutions corresponding to the different senses of ‘rights’ distinguished by the jurist W. N. Hohfeld: to dikaion corresponds to Hohfeld's claim right, exousia to a liberty or privilege, kurios to authority or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Argument of Aristotle's Politics.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Describes Aristotle's life and historical context. Discusses the place of politics––the science of the polis ––within Aristotle's taxonomy of science and of virtue. Provides an overview of Aristotle's argument, emphasizing the role of nature, justice, and rights. Describes the four main presuppositions of Aristotle's argument: natural teleology, perfectionism, community, and rulership. Also distinguishes and explains the different modes of interpretation employed in this book and in other works on the history of political thought.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Best Constitution.Fred D. Miller - 1995 - In Fred Dycus Miller (ed.), Nature, justice, and rights in Aristotle's Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle states that ‘there is only one constitution which is everywhere according to nature the best.’ This constitution is unqualifiedly just and ‘according to nature’ because it promotes the common advantage. The interpretation of ‘common advantage’ is problematic: does it consist in the advantage of the citizens considered as distinct individuals or the advantage of the polis considered as a whole? Only on the former, individualistic interpretation would the best constitution be deeply committed to individual rights, and it is argued (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 987