Results for 'stochastic choice'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  66
    Stochastic Choice and Consistency in Decision Making Under Risk: An Experimental Study. Sopher & Narramore - 2000 - Theory and Decision 48 (4):323-349.
    This paper reports the results of an experiment designed to uncover the stochastic structure of individual preferences over lotteries. Unlike previous experiments, which have presented subjects with pair-wise choices between lotteries, our design allowed subjects to choose between two lotteries or (virtually) any convex combination of the two lotteries. We interpret the mixtures of lotteries chosen by subjects as a measure of the stochastic structure of choice. We test between two alternative interpretations of stochastic choice: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  14
    Stochastic choice over menus.Pedram Heydari - 2020 - Theory and Decision 88 (2):257-268.
    Models of choice over menus aim at capturing the effect of some behavioral or non-standard element of decision-making on the behavior of a single decision-maker. These models are usually compared with the standard model of choice over menus, in which the decision-maker chooses a menu whose best item is better than that of all other available ones. However, in many empirical settings such as experimental studies, choice data come from a population of decision-makers with possibly heterogeneous attitudes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  6
    Law of demand and stochastic choice.S. Cerreia-Vioglio, F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci & A. Rustichini - 2021 - Theory and Decision 92 (3-4):513-529.
    We consider random choice rules that, by satisfying a weak form of Luce’s choice axiom, embody a form probabilistic rationality. We show that for this important class of stochastic choices, the law of demand for normal goods—arguably the main result of traditional consumer theory—continues to hold on average when strictly dominated alternatives are dismissed.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  56
    Aggregation theorems and multidimensional stochastic choice models.A. A. J. Marley - 1991 - Theory and Decision 30 (3):245-272.
  5.  52
    The stochastic component in choice and regression to the mean.Aurora García-Gallego, Nikolaos Georgantzís, Daniel Navarro-Martínez & Gerardo Sabater-Grande - 2011 - Theory and Decision 71 (2):251-267.
    In this article, we illustrate experimentally an important consequence of the stochastic component in choice behaviour which has not been acknowledged so far. Namely, its potential to produce ‘regression to the mean’ (RTM) effects. We employ a novel approach to individual choice under risk, based on repeated multiple-lottery choices (i.e. choices among many lotteries), to show how the high degree of stochastic variability present in individual decisions can distort crucially certain results through RTM effects. We demonstrate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  24
    A stochastic model for individual choice behavior.R. J. Audley - 1960 - Psychological Review 67 (1):1-15.
  7.  6
    Empirical tests of stochastic binary choice models.Addison Pan - 2021 - Theory and Decision 93 (2):259-280.
    This paper provides an experimental test of stochastic choice models of decisions. Models that admit Fechnerian structure are tested through the repeated pairwise choice problems. Results refute the Fechner hypothesis that characterizing the probability of selecting a given prospect increases in how strongly it is preferred to alternative choices. However, the experimental data lend support to characterizing an individual’s binary choice probability as some scalable functions of the von Neumann–Morgenstern utilities in the risky context.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Stochastic revealed preference and rationalizability.Jan Heufer - 2011 - Theory and Decision 71 (4):575-592.
    This article explores rationalizability issues for finite sets of observations of stochastic choice in the framework introduced by Bandyopadhyay et al. (Journal of Economic Theory, 84(1), 95–110, 1999). It is argued that a useful approach is to consider indirect preferences on budgets instead of direct preferences on commodity bundles. A new rationalizability condition for stochastic choices, “rationalizable in terms of stochastic orderings on the normalized price space” (rsop), is defined. rsop is satisfied if and only if (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  75
    A dynamic and stochastic theory of choice, response time, and confidence.Timothy J. Pleskac & Jerome Busemeyer - 2007 - In McNamara D. S. & Trafton J. G. (eds.), Proceedings of the 29th Annual Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society. pp. 563--568.
  10.  8
    (Ir)rational choices of humans, rhesus macaques, and capuchin monkeys in dynamic stochastic environments.Julia Watzek & Sarah F. Brosnan - 2018 - Cognition 178 (C):109-117.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Exceeding Expectations: Stochastic Dominance as a General Decision Theory.Christian Tarsney - manuscript
    The principle that rational agents should maximize expected utility or choiceworthiness is intuitively plausible in many ordinary cases of decision-making under uncertainty. But it is less plausible in cases of extreme, low-probability risk (like Pascal's Mugging), and intolerably paradoxical in cases like the St. Petersburg and Pasadena games. In this paper I show that, under certain conditions, stochastic dominance reasoning can capture most of the plausible implications of expectational reasoning while avoiding most of its pitfalls. Specifically, given sufficient background (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  39
    A stochastic basis for microphysics.J. C. Aron - 1979 - Foundations of Physics 9 (3-4):163-191.
    The guiding idea of this work is that classical diffusion theory, being nonrelativistic, should be associated with nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. A study of classical diffusion leads to a generalization which should correspond to the relativistic domain. Actually, with a convenient choice of the basic constants, one sees the relativistic features (Lorentz contraction and covariant diffusion equation) emerge in the generalized process. This leads first to a derivation of the nonrelativistic and relativistic wave equations (and to a model of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  7
    The Ising Decision Maker: A binary stochastic network for choice response time.Stijn Verdonck & Francis Tuerlinckx - 2014 - Psychological Review 121 (3):422-462.
  14.  25
    A stochastic interpretation of propositional dynamic logic: expressivity.Ernst-Erich Doberkat - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):687-716.
    We propose a probabilistic interpretation of Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL). We show that logical and behavioral equivalence are equivalent over general measurable spaces. This is done first for the fragment of straight line programs and then extended to cater for the nondeterministic nature of choice and iteration, expanded to PDL as a whole. Bisimilarity is also discussed and shown to be equivalent to logical and behavioral equivalence, provided the base spaces are Polish spaces. We adapt techniques from coalgebraic (...) logic and point out some connections to Souslin's operation A from descriptive set theory. This leads to a discussion of complete stochastic Kripke models and model completion, which permits an adequate treatment of the test operator. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  25
    Where Stochastic OT fails: a discrete model of metrical variation.Paul Kiparsky - unknown
    In a remarkable confirmation of OT in an empirical domain for which it was not originally intended, phonological and morphological variation has been successfully modeled by partially ranked categorical constraints (Anttila 1997, 2002). Poetic meter is a good place to extend and test this approach to variation, because there is abundant and diverse quantitative data available for it, and because it is typically governed by a relatively small number of well-understood constraints. I report the results of four such studies here. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  55
    Lottery-Dependent Utility via Stochastic Benchmarking.Paola Modesti - 2003 - Theory and Decision 55 (1):45-57.
    The possibility to interpret expected and nonexpected utility theories in purely probabilistic terms has been recently investigated. Such interpretation proposes as guideline for the Decision Maker the comparison of random variables through their probability to outperform a stochastic benchmark. We apply this type of analysis to the model of Becker and Sarin, showing that their utility functional may be seen as the probability that an opportune random variable, depending on the one to be evaluated, does not outperform a non-random (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  49
    Games of Competition in a Stochastic Environment.Judith Avrahami, Werner Güth & Yaakov Kareev - 2005 - Theory and Decision 59 (4):255-294.
    The paper presents a set of games of competition between two or three players in which reward is jointly determined by a stochastic biased mechanism and players’ choices. More specifically, a resource can be found with unequal probabilities in one of two locations. The first agent is rewarded only if it finds the resource and avoids being found by the next agent in line; the latter is rewarded only if it finds the former. Five benchmarks, based on different psychological (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  98
    Is Context-Based Choice due to Context-Dependent Preferences?Kobi Kriesler & Shmuel Nitzan - 2008 - Theory and Decision 64 (1):65-80.
    The rationalization of context-based choice is usually based on the assumption that preferences are context-dependent. In this paper, we show that context-based choice can be due to the characteristics of the choice procedure applied by the individual and not to the dependence of preferences (stochastic or deterministic) on the context. Our arguments are illustrated focusing on the much-studied dominated-alternative effects.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  5
    Bounding the Inefficiency of the Multiclass, Multicriteria C-Logit Stochastic User Equilibrium in a Transportation Network.Lekai Yuan, Xi Zhang & Chaofeng Shi - 2021 - Complexity 2021:1-20.
    We derive the exact inefficiency upper bounds of the multiclass C-Logit stochastic user equilibrium in a transportation network. All travelers are classified on the basis of different values of time into M classes. The multiclass CL-SUE model gives a more realistic path choice probability in comparison with the logit-based stochastic user equilibrium model by considering the overlapping effects between paths. To find efficiency loss upper bounds of the multiclass CL-SUE, two equivalent variational inequalities for the multiclass CL-SUE (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  27
    Cognitive Models of Choice: Comparing Decision Field Theory to the Proportional Difference Model.Benjamin Scheibehenne, Jörg Rieskamp & Claudia González-Vallejo - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (5):911-939.
    People often face preferential decisions under risk. To further our understanding of the cognitive processes underlying these preferential choices, two prominent cognitive models, decision field theory (DFT; Busemeyer & Townsend, 1993) and the proportional difference model (PD; González‐Vallejo, 2002), were rigorously tested against each other. In two consecutive experiments, the participants repeatedly had to choose between monetary gambles. The first experiment provided the reference to estimate the models’ free parameters. From these estimations, new gamble pairs were generated for the second (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  84
    On propensity-frequentist models for stochastic phenomena; with applications to bell's theorem.Tomasz Placek - unknown
    The paper develops models of statistical experiments that combine propensities with frequencies, the underlying theory being the branching space-times (BST) of Belnap (1992). The models are then applied to analyze Bell's theorem. We prove the so-called Bell-CH inequality via the assumptions of a BST version of Outcome Independence and of (non-probabilistic) No Conspiracy. Notably, neither the condition of probabilistic No Conspiracy nor the condition of Parameter Independence is needed in the proof. As the Bell-CH inequality is most likely experimentally falsified, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  95
    Can good news lead to a more pessimistic choice of action?Giacomo Bonanno - 1988 - Theory and Decision 25 (2):123-136.
    Adapting a definition introduced by Milgrom (1981) we say that a signal about the environment is good news relative to some initial beliefs if the posterior beliefs dominate the initial beliefs in the sense of first-order stochastic dominance (the assumption being that higher values of the parameter representing the environment mean better environments). We give an example where good news leads to the adoption of a more pessimistic course of action (we say that action a, reveals greater pessimism than (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  32
    De Broglie's wave particle duality in the stochastic interpretation of quantum mechanics: A testable physical assumption. [REVIEW]Ph Gueret & J. -P. Vigier - 1982 - Foundations of Physics 12 (11):1057-1083.
    If one starts from de Broglie's basic relativistic assumptions, i.e., that all particles have an intrinsic real internal vibration in their rest frame, i.e., hv 0 =m 0 c 2 ; that when they are at any one point in space-time the phase of this vibration cannot depend on the choice of the reference frame, then, one can show (following Mackinnon (1) ) that there exists a nondispersive wave packet of de Broglie's waves which can be assimilated to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  7
    The voting paradox … with a single voter? Implications for transitivity in choice under risk.David Butler & Pavlo Blavatskyy - 2020 - Economics and Philosophy 36 (1):61-79.
    The voting paradox occurs when a democratic society seeking to aggregate individual preferences into asocialpreference reaches an intransitive ordering. However it is not widely known that the paradox may also manifest for anindividualaggregating over attributes of risky objects to form a preference over those objects. When this occurs, the relation ‘stochastically greater than’ is not always transitive and so transitivity need not hold between those objects. We discuss the impact of other decision paradoxes to address a series of philosophical and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  18
    Individual vs. group decision-making: an experiment on dynamic choice under risk and ambiguity.Enrica Carbone, Konstantinos Georgalos & Gerardo Infante - 2019 - Theory and Decision 87 (1):87-122.
    This paper focuses on the comparison of individual and group decision-making, in a stochastic inter-temporal problem in two decision environments, namely risk and ambiguity. Using a consumption/saving laboratory experiment, we investigate behaviour in four treatments: individual choice under risk; group choice under risk; individual choice under ambiguity and group choice under ambiguity. Comparing decisions within and between decision environments, we find an anti-symmetric pattern. While individuals are choosing on average closer to the theoretical optimal predictions, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  10
    Coordination Effects and Optimal Policy Choices of Macroprudential Policy and Monetary Policy.Haifeng Pan & Dingsheng Zhang - 2020 - Complexity 2020:1-11.
    Considering three monetary policy rules, together with two endogenous macroprudential policies that are credit constraints for households and counter-cyclical capital for bankers, this paper establishes a dynamic stochastic general equilibrium model. Based on the welfare analysis of different combinations of macroprudential rules and monetary policy rules, this paper identifies the optimal policy combinations and analyzes the coordination effects between macroprudential policies and monetary policies. The results show that no matter what kind of monetary policy rules is implemented, the introduction (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Steven Kelman.Choice Authority - 1985 - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics 29 (2):84.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. A complete list of Sen's writings is available a t http://www. economics. harvard.Collective Choice & Social Welfare - 2009 - In Christopher W. Morris (ed.), Amartya Sen. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  13
    Crossing borders: food and agriculture in the Americas.Food Choice - 1999 - Agriculture and Human Values 16:97-102.
  30. Douglas D. heckathorn.Sociological Rational Choice - 2001 - In Barry Smart & George Ritzer (eds.), Handbook of Social Theory. Sage Publications.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. James F. wittenberger.Male Choice - 1979 - In Michael S. Gazzaniga (ed.), Handbook of Behavioral Neurobiology. , Volume 2. pp. 3--273.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  4
    Pembrey and anionwu (1996) have defined the aim of medical.Prenatal Choices - 2009 - In Vardit Ravitsky, Autumn Fiester & Arthur L. Caplan (eds.), The Penn Center Guide to Bioethics. Springer Publishing Company. pp. 415.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Short literature notices.Crucial Treatment Choices - 2001 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4:101-113.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Jeremy Butterfield.Outcome Dependence & Stochastic Einstein Nonlocaljty - 1994 - In Dag Prawitz & Dag Westerståhl (eds.), Logic and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 385.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. The 1952 Allais theory of choice involving risk.of Choice Involving Risk - 1979 - In Maurice Allais & Ole Hagen (eds.), Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. D. Reidel. pp. 25.
  36. The letter D after a page number denotes a discussion comment.Choice see Decision - 1980 - In B. D. Josephson & V. S. Ramachandran (eds.), Consciousness and the Physical World: Edited Proceedings of an Interdisciplinary Symposium on Consciousness Held at the University of Cambridge in January 1978. Pergamon Press. pp. 201.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Lisa Green/Aspectual be–type Constructions and Coercion in African American English Yoad Winter/Distributivity and Dependency Instructions for Authors.Pauline Jacobson, Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, Inflectional Head, Thomas Ede Zimmermann, Free Choice Disjunction, Epistemic Possibility, Sigrid Beck & Uli Sauerland - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (373).
  38.  55
    The Experimetrics of Public Goods: Inferring Motivations from Contributions. [REVIEW]Nicholas Bardsley & Peter G. Moffatt - 2007 - Theory and Decision 62 (2):161-193.
    In public goods experiments, stochastic choice, censoring and motivational heterogeneity give scope for disagreement over the extent of unselfishness, and whether it is reciprocal or altruistic. We show that these problems can be addressed econometrically, by estimating a finite mixture model to isolate types, incorporating double censoring and a tremble term. Most subjects act selfishly, but a substantial proportion are reciprocal with altruism playing only a marginal role. Isolating reciprocators enables a test of Sugden’s model of voluntary contributions. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  39.  51
    Risk behavior for gain, loss, and mixed prospects.Peter Brooks, Simon Peters & Horst Zank - 2014 - Theory and Decision 77 (2):153-182.
    This study extends experimental tests of (cumulative) prospect theory (PT) over prospects with more than three outcomes and tests second-order stochastic dominance principles (Levy and Levy, Management Science 48:1334–1349, 2002; Baucells and Heukamp, Management Science 52:1409–1423, 2006). It considers choice behavior of people facing prospects of three different types: gain prospects (losing is not possible), loss prospects (gaining is not possible), and mixed prospects (both gaining and losing are possible). The data supports the distinction of risk behavior into (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Stability of risk preferences and the reflection effect of prospect theory.Manel Baucells & Antonio Villasís - 2010 - Theory and Decision 68 (1-2):193-211.
    Are risk preferences stable over time? To address this question we elicit risk preferences from the same pool of subjects at two different moments in time. To interpret the results, we use a Fechner stochastic choice model in which the revealed preference of individuals is governed by some underlying preference, together with a random error. We take cumulative prospect theory as the underlying preference model (Kahneman and Tversky, Econometrica 47:263–292, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. On choosing between deterministic and indeterministic models: underdetermination and indirect evidence.Charlotte Werndl - 2013 - Synthese 190 (12):2243-2265.
    There are results which show that measure-theoretic deterministic models and stochastic models are observationally equivalent. Thus there is a choice between a deterministic and an indeterministic model and the question arises: Which model is preferable relative to evidence? If the evidence equally supports both models, there is underdetermination. This paper first distinguishes between different kinds of choice and clarifies the possible resulting types of underdetermination. Then a new answer is presented: the focus is on the choice (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  42.  16
    A Misfit model: irrational deterrence and bounded rationality.Karl Sörenson - 2023 - Theory and Decision 94 (4):575-591.
    Contemporary theories of deterrence place a strong emphasis on coherency between model and theory. Schelling’s contention of irrational threats for successful deterrence abandons the rationality assumption to explain how a player can deter, thereby departing from the standard game theoretic solution concepts. It is a misfit model in relation to a deterrence theory and, therefore, excluded. The article defends and remodels Schelling’s intuition by employing the level-k model. It is shown that an unsophisticated player that randomizes over its strategies brings (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Causal potency of consciousness in the physical world.Danko D. Georgiev - 2024 - International Journal of Modern Physics B 38 (19):2450256.
    The evolution of the human mind through natural selection mandates that our conscious experiences are causally potent in order to leave a tangible impact upon the surrounding physical world. Any attempt to construct a functional theory of the conscious mind within the framework of classical physics, however, inevitably leads to causally impotent conscious experiences in direct contradiction to evolution theory. Here, we derive several rigorous theorems that identify the origin of the latter impasse in the mathematical properties of ordinary differential (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Moral Uncertainty for Deontologists.Christian Tarsney - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (3):505-520.
    Defenders of deontological constraints in normative ethics face a challenge: how should an agent decide what to do when she is uncertain whether some course of action would violate a constraint? The most common response to this challenge has been to defend a threshold principle on which it is subjectively permissible to act iff the agent's credence that her action would be constraint-violating is below some threshold t. But the threshold approach seems arbitrary and unmotivated: what would possibly determine where (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  45.  53
    Stronger utility.Pavlo R. Blavatskyy - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (2):265-286.
    Empirical research often requires a method how to convert a deterministic economic theory into an econometric model. A popular method is to add a random error term on the utility scale. This method, however, ignores stochastic dominance. A modification of this method is proposed to account for stochastic dominance. The modified model compares favorably to other existing models in terms of goodness of fit to experimental data. The modified model can rationalize the preference reversal phenomenon. An intuitive axiomatic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  51
    Even Risk-Averters may Love Risk.Alfred Müller & Marco Scarsini - 2002 - Theory and Decision 52 (1):81-99.
    A decision maker bets on the outcomes of a sequence of coin-tossings. At the beginning of the game the decision maker can choose one of two coins to play the game. This initial choice is irreversible. The coins can be biased and the player is uncertain about the nature of one (or possibly both) coin(s). If the player is an expected-utility maximizer, her choice of the coin will depend on different elements: the nature of the game (namely, whether (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  14
    Can we remain rational in the large world? On some unexpected consequences of ecological rationality.Marcin Gorazda - 2021 - Philosophical Problems in Science 71:75-105.
    The paper outlines various concepts of rationality, their characteristics and consequences. In the first, most general part, the metaphysical, instrumental and discursive rationality is distinguished. The following part focuses on instrumental rationality and the rational choice theory and ordinal and cardinal utility, expected utility and game theory, respectively. All those concepts are summarised as being the most mathematically elegant and mostly decidable and helpful in the decision-making process. Giving primacy to individual preferences and withholding the judgment on their “objective” (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  17
    Meaningful learning in weighted voting games: an experiment.Eric Guerci, Nobuyuki Hanaki & Naoki Watanabe - 2017 - Theory and Decision 83 (1):131-153.
    By employing binary committee choice problems, this paper investigates how varying or eliminating feedback about payoffs affects: subjects’ learning about the underlying relationship between their nominal voting weights and their expected payoffs in weighted voting games; the transfer of acquired learning from one committee choice problem to a similar but different problem. In the experiment, subjects choose to join one of two committees and obtain a payoff stochastically determined by a voting theory. We found that: subjects learned to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Nondegenerate Intervals of No-Trade Prices for Risk Averse Traders.Gerd Weinrich - 1999 - Theory and Decision 46 (1):79-99.
    According to the local risk-neutrality theorem an agent who has the opportunity to invest in an uncertain asset does not buy it or sell it short iff its expected value is equal to its price, independently of the agent's attitude towards risk. Contrary to that it is shown that, in the context of expected utility theory with differentiable vNM utility function, but without the assumption of stochastic constant returns to scale, nondegenerate intervals of no-trade prices may exist. With a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  34
    A note on “The no alternatives argument” by Richard Dawid, Stephan Hartmann and Jan Sprenger.Frederik Herzberg - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 4 (3):375-384.
    The defence of The No Alternatives Argument in a recent paper by R. Dawid, S. Hartmann and J. Sprenger rests on the assumption that the number of acceptable alternatives to a scientific hypothesis is independent of the complexity of the scientific problem. This note proves a generalisation of the main theorem by Dawid, Hartmann and Sprenger, where this independence assumption is no longer necessary. Some of the other assumptions are also discussed, and the limitations of the no-alternatives argument are explored.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000