Results for 'correct logical system'

996 found
Order:
  1. What is the correct logic of necessity, actuality and apriority?Peter Fritz - 2014 - Review of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):385-414.
    This paper is concerned with a propositional modal logic with operators for necessity, actuality and apriority. The logic is characterized by a class of relational structures defined according to ideas of epistemic two-dimensional semantics, and can therefore be seen as formalizing the relations between necessity, actuality and apriority according to epistemic two-dimensional semantics. We can ask whether this logic is correct, in the sense that its theorems are all and only the informally valid formulas. This paper gives outlines of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  2. Correction regarding 'Normalisation and Subformula Property for a System of Classical Logic with Tarski's Rule'.Nils Kürbis - manuscript
    This note corrects an error in my paper 'Normalisation and Subformula Property for a System of Classical Logic with Tarski's Rule' (Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (2022): 105-129, DOI 10.1007/s00153-021-00775-6): Theorem 2 is mistaken, and so is a corollary drawn from it as well as a corollary that was concluded by the same mistake. Luckily this does not affect the main result of the paper.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. A correction to a new system of deontic logic.Georg Henrik Von Wright - 1965 - Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 2:103-107.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4.  52
    Logical Pluralism and Interpretations of Logical Systems.Diego Tajer & Camillo Fiore - 2022 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 31:1-26.
    Logical pluralism is a general idea that there is more than one correct logic. Carnielli and Rodrigues [2019a] defend an epistemic interpretation of the paraconsistent logic N4, according to which an argument is valid in this logic just in case it necessarily preserves evidence. The authors appeal to this epistemic interpretation to briefly motivate a kind of logical pluralism: “different accounts of logical consequence may preserve different properties of propositions”. The aim of this paper is to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  35
    Correction to: HYPE: A System of Hyperintensional Logic.Hannes Leitgeb - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (2):407-407.
    The original version of the article unfortunately contained a mistake. The author missed to mention the support by a EU-funded research network that he is involved in. See below. This work was supported by the Marie-Sklodowska-Curie Innovative Training Network DIAPHORA.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  37
    Is There Only One Correct System of Modal Logic?E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (1):23-56.
  7.  80
    Completud de dos cálculos logicos de Leibniz (Completeness of Two Logical Systems of Leibniz).Alejandro Martin Maldonado - 2001 - Theoria 16 (3):539-558.
    Este trabajo se encuadra dentro de una nueva visión de la lógica de Leibniz, la cual pretende mostrar que sus escritos fueron ricos no solamente en proyectos ambiciosos (Característica Universal, Combinatoria, Mathesis) sino también en desarrollos lógico-matematicos concretos. Se demuestra que su “Caracteristica Numerica” que asigna pares de números a las proposiciones categóricas es una semántiea para la cual la silogística aristotélica es correcta y completa, y que el sistema algebraico presentado en Fundamentos de un Cálculo Lógico es una lógica (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  5
    Is There Only One Correct System of Modal Logic?E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (1):23-56.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  18
    Symposium: Is There Only One Correct System of Modal Logic?E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (2):23 - 56.
  10. The required correction to Copi's statement of ug.Symbolic Logic - 1966 - Logique Et Analyse 33:267.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  12
    A. N. Prior. The theory of implication. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 9 , pp. 1–6. - A. N. Prior. The theory of implication: two corrections. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 11 , pp. 381–382. - Bolesław Sobociński. A note on Prior's systems in “The theory of deduction.”Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 5 no. 2 , pp. 139–140. [REVIEW]Alan Ross Anderson - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):665-666.
  12.  71
    Logical Revision by Counterexamples: A Case Study of the Paraconsistent Counterexample to Ex Contradictione Quodlibet.Seungrak Choi - 2019 - In Byunghan Kim, Jörg Brendle, Gyesik Lee, Fenrong Liu, R. Ramanujam, Shashi M. Srivastava, Akito Tsuboi & Liang Yu (eds.), Proceedings of the 14th and 15th Asian Logic Conferences. World Scientific Publishing Company. pp. 141-167.
    It is often said that a correct logical system should have no counterexample to its logical rules and the system must be revised if its rules have a counterexample. If a logical system (or theory) has a counterexample to its logical rules, do we have to revise the system? In this paper, focussing on the role of counterexamples to logical rules, we deal with the question. -/- We investigate two mutually (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  26
    E. J. Lemmon. Symposium: Is there only one correct system of modal logic? I.Aristotelian Society supplementary volume XXXIII, London1959, pp. 23–40. - G. P. Henderson. Is there only one correct system of modal logic? II. Aristotelian Society supplementary volume XXXIII, London1959, pp. 41–56. [REVIEW]Sörén Halldén - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):306-306.
  14.  15
    Roderick M. Chisholm. Contrary-to-duty imperatives and deontic logic. Analysis , vol. 24 no. 2 , pp. 33–36. - Mark Fisher. A contradiction in deontic logic?Analysis , vol. 25 no. 1 , pp. 12–13. - G. H. von Wright. A new system of deontic logic. Danish yearbook of philosophy, vol. 1 , pp. 173–182. - G. H. von Wright. A correction to a new system of deontic logic. Danish yearbook of philosophy, vol. 2 , pp. 103–107. [REVIEW]Frederic B. Fitch - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):243-244.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  15
    E. J. Lemmon. Symposium: Is there only one correct system of modal logic? I.Aristotelian Society supplementary volume XXXIII, London1959, pp. 23–40. - G. P. Henderson. Is there only one correct system of modal logic? II. Aristotelian Society supplementary volume XXXIII, London1959, pp. 41–56. [REVIEW]E. J. Lemmon & G. P. Henderson - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):306-306.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  8
    Logic Programming: Proceedings of the Joint International Conference and Symposium on Logic Programming.Krzysztof R. Apt & Association for Logic Programming - 1992 - MIT Press (MA).
    The Joint International Conference on Logic Programming, sponsored by the Association for Logic Programming, is a major forum for presentations of research, applications, and implementations in this important area of computer science. Logic programming is one of the most promising steps toward declarative programming and forms the theoretical basis of the programming language Prolog and its various extensions. Logic programming is also fundamental to work in artificial intelligence, where it has been used for nonmonotonic and commonsense reasoning, expert systems implementation, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  10
    Logic.Stan Baronett - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    Featuring an exceptionally clear writing style and a wealth of real-world examples and exercises, Logic, Second Edition, shows how logic relates to everyday life, demonstrating its applications in such areas as the workplace, media and entertainment, politics, science and technology, student life, and elsewhere.Thoroughly revised and expanded in this second edition, the text now features 2600 exercises, more than 1000 of them new; three new chapters on legal arguments, moral arguments, and analyzing a long essay; enhanced pedagogy; and much more.FEATURES* (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  18. Rivalry, normativity, and the collapse of logical pluralism.Erik Stei - 2020 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 63 (3-4):411-432.
    Logical pluralism is the view that there is more than one correct logic. This very general characterization gives rise to a whole family of positions. I argue that not all of them are stable. The main argument in the paper is inspired by considerations known as the “collapse problem”, and it aims at the most popular form of logical pluralism advocated by JC Beall and Greg Restall. I argue that there is a more general argument available that (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  65
    Beyond Logical Pluralism and Logical Monism.Pavel Arazim - 2020 - Logica Universalis 14 (2):151-174.
    Logical pluralism as a thesis that more than one logic is correct seems very plausible for two basic reasons. First, there are so many logical systems on the market today. And it is unclear how we should decide which of them gets the logical rules right. On the other hand, logical monism as the opposite thesis still seems plausible, as well, because of normativity of logic. An approach which would manage to bring a synthesis of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  24
    Zohar Manna. Mathematical theory of partial correctness. Journal of computer and system sciences, vol. 5 , pp. 239–253.Andrzej Blikle - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):348.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Logical Particularism.Nicole Wyatt & Gillman Payette - 2018 - In Jeremy Wyatt, Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen & Nathan Kellen (eds.), Pluralisms in Truth and Logic. Cham, Switzerland and Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 277-299.
    Logics—that is to say logical systems—are generally conceived of as describing the logical forms of arguments as well as endorsing cer- tain principles or rules of inference specified in terms of these forms. From this perspective, a correct logic is a system which captures only (and perhaps all) of the correct principles, and good—i.e. logical— reasoning is reasoning which at the level of logical form conforms to the principles of a correct logic. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  24
    Meredith David. A correction to von Wright's decision procedure for the deontic system P. Mind, n.s. vol. 65 , pp. 548–550. [REVIEW]E. J. Lemmon - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (1):92-92.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  21
    The Theory of Implication.The Theory of Implication: Two Corrections.A Note on Prior's Systems in "The Theory of Deduction.".A. N. Prior - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):665-666.
  24. Intuitionism and the Modal Logic of Vagueness.Susanne Bobzien & Ian Rumfitt - 2020 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 49 (2):221-248.
    Intuitionistic logic provides an elegant solution to the Sorites Paradox. Its acceptance has been hampered by two factors. First, the lack of an accepted semantics for languages containing vague terms has led even philosophers sympathetic to intuitionism to complain that no explanation has been given of why intuitionistic logic is the correct logic for such languages. Second, switching from classical to intuitionistic logic, while it may help with the Sorites, does not appear to offer any advantages when dealing with (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. Logic and Truth.Ken Akiba - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Research 25:101-123.
    It is usually held that what distinguishes a good inference from a bad one is that a good inference is truth-preserving. Against this view, this paper argues that a logical inference is good or bad depending not on whether it is truth-preserving or not, but whether it belongs to a logical system the addition of which makes a deductively conservative extension of the derivation relations among the atomic statements. To so argue, the paper first contends that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  29
    Logic and Truth.Ken Akiba - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Research 25:101-123.
    It is usually held that what distinguishes a good inference from a bad one is that a good inference is truth-preserving. Against this view, this paper argues that a logical inference is good or bad depending not on whether it is truth-preserving or not, but whether it belongs to a logical system the addition of which makes a deductively conservative extension of the derivation relations among the atomic statements. To so argue, the paper first contends that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  4
    Logic Programming and Non-monotonic Reasoning: Proceedings of the First International Workshop.Wiktor Marek, Anil Nerode, V. S. Subrahmanian & Association for Logic Programming - 1991 - MIT Press (MA).
    The First International Workshop brings together researchers from the theoretical ends of the logic programming and artificial intelligence communities to discuss their mutual interests. Logic programming deals with the use of models of mathematical logic as a way of programming computers, where theoretical AI deals with abstract issues in modeling and representing human knowledge and beliefs. One common ground is nonmonotonic reasoning, a family of logics that includes room for the kinds of variations that can be found in human reasoning. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  94
    The philosophical logic of Stéphane Lupasco (1900–1988).Joseph E. Brenner - 2010 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 19 (3):243-285.
    The advent of quantum mechanics in the early 20 th Century had profound consequences for science and mathematics, for philosophy (Schrödinger), and for logic (von Neumann). In 1968, Putnam wrote that quantum mechanics required a revolution in our understanding of logic per se. However, applications of quantum logics have been little explored outside the quantum domain. Dummett saw some implications of quantum logic for truth, but few philosophers applied similar intuitions to epistemology or ontology. Logic remained a truth-functional ’science’ of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. Logical Pluralism is Compatible with Monism about Metaphysical Modality.Nicola Ciprotti & Luca Moretti - 2009 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 87 (2):275-284.
    Beall and Restall 2000; 2001; 2006 advocate a comprehensive pluralist approach to logic, which they call Logical Pluralism, according to which there is not one true logic but many equally acceptable logical systems. They maintain that Logical Pluralism is compatible with monism about metaphysical modality, according to which there is just one correct logic of metaphysical modality. Wyatt 2004 contends that Logical Pluralism is incompatible with monism about metaphysical modality. We first suggest that if Wyatt (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  26
    Learning correction grammars.Lorenzo Carlucci, John Case & Sanjay Jain - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):489-516.
    We investigate a new paradigm in the context of learning in the limit, namely, learning correction grammars for classes of computably enumerable (c.e.) languages. Knowing a language may feature a representation of it in terms of two grammars. The second grammar is used to make corrections to the first grammar. Such a pair of grammars can be seen as a single description of (or grammar for) the language. We call such grammars correction grammars. Correction grammars capture the observable fact that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  27
    On Logic, Syntax, and Slience.Majid Davoody Beni - 2015 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 42 (1):195-209.
    The relationship between Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language and Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus has been interpreted in several ways during past decades. One of the interpretations has gained keen advocates among Carnap scholars. It was originally provoked by what Caranp said in LSL, and it consists of two parts. First, it indicates that in TLP the possibility of speaking about the logical form of a language within the same language had been foresworn by Wittgenstein, but Carnap proved him wrong (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  24
    The logical basis of metaphysics.Richard L. Purtill - 1995 - History of European Ideas 21 (2):297-298.
    Michael Dummett's new book is the greatly expanded and recently revised version of his distinguished William James Lectures, delivered in 1976. Dummett regards the construction of a satisfactory theory of meaning as the most pressing task of contemporary analytical philosophy. He believes that the successful completion of this difficult assignment will lead to a resolution of problems before which philosophy has been stalled, in some instances for centuries. These problems turn on the correctness or incorrectness of a realistic view of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. The logic of partitions: Introduction to the dual of the logic of subsets: The logic of partitions.David Ellerman - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):287-350.
    Modern categorical logic as well as the Kripke and topological models of intuitionistic logic suggest that the interpretation of ordinary “propositional” logic should in general be the logic of subsets of a given universe set. Partitions on a set are dual to subsets of a set in the sense of the category-theoretic duality of epimorphisms and monomorphisms—which is reflected in the duality between quotient objects and subobjects throughout algebra. If “propositional” logic is thus seen as the logic of subsets of (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  8
    Review: A. N. Prior, The Theory of Implication; A. N. Prior, The Theory of Implication: Two Corrections; Boleslaw Sobocinski, A Note on Prior's Systems in "The Theory of Deduction.". [REVIEW]Alan Ross Anderson - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (4):665-666.
  35. On an Intuitionistic Logic for Pragmatics.Gianluigi Bellin, Massimiliano Carrara & Daniele Chiffi - 2018 - Journal of Logic and Computation 50 (28):935–966..
    We reconsider the pragmatic interpretation of intuitionistic logic [21] regarded as a logic of assertions and their justi cations and its relations with classical logic. We recall an extension of this approach to a logic dealing with assertions and obligations, related by a notion of causal implication [14, 45]. We focus on the extension to co-intuitionistic logic, seen as a logic of hypotheses [8, 9, 13] and on polarized bi-intuitionistic logic as a logic of assertions and conjectures: looking at the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  10
    Relevant Logics.Edwin D. Mares & Robert K. Meyer - 2017 - In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 280–308.
    Once upon a time, modal logic was castigated because it ‘had no semantics.’ Kripke, Hintikka, Kanger, and others changed all that. In a similar way, when Relevant Logic was introduced by Anderson and Belnap, it too was castigated for ‘having no semantics.’ The present overview marks a culmination of that effort. The semantic approach described here brings together a number of hitherto disparate efforts to set out formal systems for logics of relevant implication and entailment. It also makes clear (despite (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  37.  66
    Logic.Immanuel Kant - 1974 - New York: Dover Publications.
    The second, corrected edition of the first and only complete English translation of Kant’s highly influential introduction to philosophy, presenting both the terminological and structural basis for his philosophical system, and offering an invaluable key to his main works, particularly the three Critiques. Extensive editiorial apparatus.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  38. Logic: Normative or descriptive? The ethics of belief or a branch of psychology?Michael D. Resnik - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):221-238.
    By a logical theory I mean a formal system together with its semantics, meta-theory, and rules for translating ordinary language into its notation. Logical theories can be used descriptively (for example, to represent particular arguments or to depict the logical form of certain sentences). Here the logician uses the usual methods of empirical science to assess the correctness of his descriptions. However, the most important applications of logical theories are normative, and here, I argue, the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  39. The Concept of Logical Consequence: An Introduction to Philosophical Logic.Matthew W. McKeon - 2010 - Peter Lang.
    Introduction -- The concept of logical consequence -- Tarski's characterization of the common concept of logical consequence -- The logical consequence relation has a modal element -- The logical consequence relation is formal -- The logical consequence relation is A priori -- Logical and non-logical terminology -- The meanings of logical terms explained in terms of their semantic properties -- The meanings of logical terms explained in terms of their inferential properties (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. The Logic of Hyperlogic. Part A: Foundations.Alexander W. Kocurek - 2024 - Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):244-271.
    Hyperlogic is a hyperintensional system designed to regiment metalogical claims (e.g., “Intuitionistic logic is correct” or “The law of excluded middle holds”) into the object language, including within embedded environments such as attitude reports and counterfactuals. This paper is the first of a two-part series exploring the logic of hyperlogic. This part presents a minimal logic of hyperlogic and proves its completeness. It consists of two interdefined axiomatic systems: one for classical consequence (truth preservation under a classical interpretation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  32
    Tense logic for discrete future time.Patrick Schindler - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):105-118.
    Prior has conjectured that the tense-logical system Gli obtained by adding to a complete basis for the classical propositional calculus the primitive symbolG, the definitionsDf. F:Fα=NGNαDf. L:Lα=KαGα,and the postulatesis complete for the logic of linear, infinite, transitive, discrete future time. In this paper it is demonstrated that that conjecture is correct and it is shown that Gli has the finite model property: see [4]. The techniques used are in part suggested by those used in Bull [2] and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  80
    Interpreted Dynamical Systems and Qualitative Laws: from Neural Networks to Evolutionary Systems.Hannes Leitgeb - 2005 - Synthese 146 (1-2):189-202.
    . Interpreted dynamical systems are dynamical systems with an additional interpretation mapping by which propositional formulas are assigned to system states. The dynamics of such systems may be described in terms of qualitative laws for which a satisfaction clause is defined. We show that the systems Cand CL of nonmonotonic logic are adequate with respect to the corresponding description of the classes of interpreted ordered and interpreted hierarchical systems, respectively. Inhibition networks, artificial neural networks, logic programs, and evolutionary systems (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43. Semantic information and the correctness theory of truth.Luciano Floridi - 2011 - Erkenntnis 74 (2):147–175.
    Semantic information is usually supposed to satisfy the veridicality thesis: p qualifies as semantic information only if p is true. However, what it means for semantic information to be true is often left implicit, with correspondentist interpretations representing the most popular, default option. The article develops an alternative approach, namely a correctness theory of truth (CTT) for semantic information. This is meant as a contribution not only to the philosophy of information but also to the philosophical debate on the nature (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  44.  26
    Grammatical structures and logical deductions.Wojciech Buszkowski - 1995 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 3:47-86.
    The three essays presented here concern natural connections between grammatical derivations and structures provided by certain standard grammar formalisms, on the one hand, and deductions in logical systems, on the other hand. In the first essay we analyse the adequacy of Polish notation for higher-order languages. The Ajdukiewicz algorithm (Ajdukiewicz 1935) is discussed in terms of generalized MP-deductions. We exhibit a failure in Ajdukiewicz’s original version of the algorithm and give a correct one; we prove that generalized MP-deductions (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Enriching Deontic Logic.Ilaria Canavotto & Alessandro Giordani - 2018 - Journal of Logic and Computation 1:1-23.
    It is well known that systems of action deontic logic emerging from a standard analysis of permission in terms of possibility of doing an action without incurring in a violation of the law are subject to paradoxes. In general, paradoxes are acknowledged as such if we have intuitions telling us that things should be different. The aim of this paper is to introduce a paradox-free deontic action system by (i) identifying the basic intuitions leading to the emergence of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  7
    Logic: An Empirical Study of A Priori Truths.John Kearns - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 8:92-97.
    I distinguish a priori knowledge from a priori truths or statements. A priori knowledge either is evident or is derived from evident premisses by means of correct reasoning. An a priori statement is one that reflects features of the conceptual framework within which it is placed. The statement either describes semantic relations between concepts of the framework or it characterizes the application of the framework to experience and the world. An a priori statement is not necessarily part of anyone’s (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  80
    Classical Logic.Stewart Shapiro & Teresa Kouri Kissel - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    Typically, a logic consists of a formal or informal language together with a deductive system and/or a model-theoretic semantics. The language is, or corresponds to, a part of a natural language like English or Greek. The deductive system is to capture, codify, or simply record which inferences are correct for the given language, and the semantics is to capture, codify, or record the meanings, or truth-conditions, or possible truth conditions, for at least part of the language.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  48.  54
    The logic of content effects in propositional reasoning: The case of conditional reasoning with a point of view.Sieghard Beller & Hans Spada - 2003 - Thinking and Reasoning 9 (4):335 – 378.
    In order to resolve the controversial discussion regarding content effects in deductive reasoning, we propose distinguishing between two inferential sources—an argument's form , and additional relations people associate with the argument's content —and analysing their interplay. Both sources are equally necessary in order to understand the role content plays in deductive reasoning. People make valid deductions from the content relations ( content competence ), but in thematic reasoning tasks, these deductions lead to the intriguing phenomenon known as content effects . (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  49.  47
    Basic Intuitionistic Conditional Logic.Yale Weiss - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (3):447-469.
    Conditional logics have traditionally been intended to formalize various intuitively correct modes of reasoning involving conditional expressions in natural language. Although conditional logics have by now been thoroughly studied in a classical context, they have yet to be systematically examined in an intuitionistic context, despite compelling philosophical and technical reasons to do so. This paper addresses this gap by thoroughly examining the basic intuitionistic conditional logic ICK, the intuitionistic counterpart of Chellas’ important classical system CK. I give ICK (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50. Frontiers of Conditional Logic.Yale Weiss - 2019 - Dissertation, The Graduate Center, City University of New York
    Conditional logics were originally developed for the purpose of modeling intuitively correct modes of reasoning involving conditional—especially counterfactual—expressions in natural language. While the debate over the logic of conditionals is as old as propositional logic, it was the development of worlds semantics for modal logic in the past century that catalyzed the rapid maturation of the field. Moreover, like modal logic, conditional logic has subsequently found a wide array of uses, from the traditional (e.g. counterfactuals) to the exotic (e.g. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 996