Results for 'Weak Pareto principle'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  57
    Pareto principles, positive responsiveness, and majority decisions.Susumu Cato - 2011 - Theory and Decision 71 (4):503-518.
    This article investigates the relationship among the weak Pareto principle, the strong Pareto principle, and positive responsiveness in the context of voting. First, it is shown that under a mild domain condition, if an anonymous and neutral collective choice rule (CCR) is complete and transitive, then the weak Pareto principle and the strong Pareto principle are equivalent. Next, it is shown that under another mild domain condition, if a neutral CCR (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  10
    Weak independence and the Pareto principle.Susumu Cato - 2016 - Social Choice and Welfare 47:295–314.
    In this paper, the independence of irrelevant alternatives and the Pareto principle are simultaneously weakened in the Arrovian framework of social choice. Moreover, we also relax transitivity of social preferences. We show that impossibility remains under weaker versions of Arrow’s original conditions. Our results complement the recent work by Coban and Sanver (Soc Choice Welf 43(4):953–961, 2014).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  57
    Equal value of life and the pareto principle.Andreas Hasman & Lars Peter Østerdal - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (1):19-33.
    A principle claiming equal entitlement to continued life has been strongly defended in the literature as a fundamental social value. We refer to this principle as ‘equal value of life'. In this paper we argue that there is a general incompatibility between the equal value of life principle and the weak Pareto principle and provide proof of this under mild structural assumptions. Moreover we demonstrate that a weaker, age-dependent version of the equal value of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Strong dictatorship via ratio-scale measurable utilities: a simpler proof.Jacob M. Nebel - forthcoming - Economic Theory Bulletin.
    Tsui and Weymark (Economic Theory, 1997) have shown that the only continuous social welfare orderings on the whole Euclidean space which satisfy the weak Pareto principle and are invariant to individual-specific similarity transformations of utilities are strongly dictatorial. Their proof relies on functional equation arguments which are quite complex. This note provides a simpler proof of their theorem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  42
    An Evolutionary Efficiency Alternative to the Notion of Pareto Efficiency.Irene van Staveren - 2012 - Economic Thought 1 (1).
    The paper argues that the notion of Pareto efficiency builds on two normative assumptions: the more general consequentialist norm of any efficiency criterion, and the strong no-harm principle of the prohibition of any redistribution during the economic process that hurts at least one person. These normative concerns lead to a constrained and static notion of efficiency in mainstream economics, ignoring dynamic efficiency gains from more equal allocations of resources. The paper argues that a weak no-harm principle (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  8
    Acyclicity, anonymity, and prefilters.Walter Bossert & Susumu Cato - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Economics 87:134–141.
    We analyze the decisiveness structures associated with acyclical collective choice rules. In particular, we examine the consequences of adding anonymity to weak Pareto, thereby complementing earlier results on acyclical social choice. Both finite and countably infinite populations are considered. As established in contributions by Donald Brown and by Jeffrey Banks, acyclical social choice is closely linked to prefilters in the presence of the weak Pareto principle. We introduce the notion of a conditional prefilter and use (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The impossibility of a Paretian republican? Some comments on Pettit and Sen.Christian List - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (1):65-87.
    Philip Pettit (2001) has suggested that there are parallels between his republican account of freedom and Amartya Sen's (1970) account of freedom as decisive preference. In this paper, I discuss these parallels from a social-choice-theoretic perspective. I sketch a formalization of republican freedom and argue that republican freedom is formally very similar to freedom as defined in Sen's “minimal liberalism” condition. In consequence, the republican account of freedom is vulnerable to a version of Sen's liberal paradox, an inconsistency between universal (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8. Foreign aid and the moral value of freedom.Martin Peterson - 2004 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (3):293-307.
    Peter Singer has famously argued that people living in affluent western countries are morally obligated to donate money to famine relief. The central premise in his argument is that, If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do so. The present paper offers an argument to the effect that affluent people ought to support foreign aid projects based on a much weaker ethical premise. The (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  14
    Love, On the Univocity of Rawls’s Difference Principle.Alain Boyer - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 17 (45):60-71.
    A double ambiguity has been charged against Rawls’s difference principle (DP). Is it Maximin, Leximin, or something else? Usually, following A. Sen, scholars identify DP with the so-called Leximin. One argues here that one has to distinguish 1° the Leximin, 2° the Maximin (as rule of justice formally analogous to the maximin rule of decision), represented by the figure in L of the perfectly substitutable goods, and 3° the genuine DP. When the augmentation of inequality benefits the worse off, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Pareto Principles in Infinite Ethics.Amanda Askell - 2018 - Dissertation, New York University
    It is possible that the world contains infinitely many agents that have positive and negative levels of well-being. Theories have been developed to ethically rank such worlds based on the well-being levels of the agents in those worlds or other qualitative properties of the worlds in question, such as the distribution of agents across spacetime. In this thesis I argue that such ethical rankings ought to be consistent with the Pareto principle, which says that if two worlds contain (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  11.  30
    On the impossibility of complete non-interference in Paretian social judgements.Marco Mariotti & Roberto Veneziani - 2013 - Journal of Economic Theory 148 (4):1689-1699.
    We study a principle of ‘Non-Interference’ in social welfare judgements. Non-Interference captures aspects of liberal approaches (particularly a Millian approach) to social decision making. In its full generality, Non-Interference produces an impossibility result: together with Weak Pareto Optimality, it implies that a social welfare ordering must be dictatorial. However, interesting restricted versions of Non-Interference are compatible with standard social welfare orderings.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  43
    Epistemological Consequences of Frege Puzzles.Timothy Williamson - 2021 - Philosophical Topics 49 (2):287-319.
    Frege puzzles exploit cognitive differences between co-referential terms. Traditionally, they were handled by some version of Frege’s distinction between sense and reference, which avoided disruptive consequences for epistemology. However, the Fregean programme did not live up to its original promise, and was undermined by the development of theories of direct reference; for semantic purposes, its prospects now look dim. In particular, well-known analogues of Frege puzzles concern pairs of uncontentious synonyms; attempts to deal with them by distinguishing idiolects or postulating (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13. Spurious Unanimity and the Pareto Principle.Philippe Mongin - 2016 - Economics and Philosophy 32 (3):511-532.
    The Pareto principle states that if the members of society express the same preference judgment between two options, this judgment is compelling for society. A building block of normative economics and social choice theory, and often borrowed by contemporary political philosophy, the principle has rarely been subjected to philosophical criticism. The paper objects to it on the ground that it indifferently applies to those cases in which the individuals agree on both their expressed preferences and their reasons (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  14. Infinite utilitarianism: More is always better.Luc Lauwers & Peter Vallentyne - 2004 - Economics and Philosophy 20 (2):307-330.
    We address the question of how finitely additive moral value theories (such as utilitarianism) should rank worlds when there are an infinite number of locations of value (people, times, etc.). In the finite case, finitely additive theories satisfy both Weak Pareto and a strong anonymity condition. In the infinite case, however, these two conditions are incompatible, and thus a question arises as to which of these two conditions should be rejected. In a recent contribution, Hamkins and Montero (2000) (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  15.  74
    Harsanyi's Social Aggregation Theorem and Dictatorship.Osamu Mori - 2003 - Theory and Decision 55 (3):257-272.
    In this paper I investigate the possibility of a dictatorship in the context of Harsanyi's Social Aggregation Theorem. Preliminarily, some propositions about Harsanyi's Theorem are presented using an alternative principle that I name Quasi-strong Pareto, which is the latter part of Strong Pareto. Then I define dictatorship as a requirement that social preference agrees with a dictator's preference or those of members of dictatorial group even if their preferences strictly contradict those of all other people in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  28
    Public Legal Reason.Lawrence B. Solum - unknown
    This essay develops an ideal of public legal reason--a normative theory of legal reasons that is appropriate for a society characterized by religious and moral pluralism. One of the implications of this theory is that normative theorizing about public and private law should eschew reliance on the deep premises of deontology or consequentialism and should instead rely on what the author calls public values--values that can be affirmed without relying on the deep and controversial premises of particular comprehensive moral doctrines. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  86
    A Pareto Principle for Possible People.Christoph Fehige - 1998 - In Christoph Fehige & Ulla Wessels (eds.), Preferences. New York: W. de Gruyter. pp. 508–543.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  18.  15
    When is weak Pareto equivalent to strong Pareto?Susumu Cato - 2023 - Economics Letters 222:110953.
    This paper shows that weak Pareto and strong Pareto are equivalent under continuity and strong quasi-concavity. We use a framework that incorporates welfare as well as non-welfare information.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  24
    The Pareto Principle.Jürgen Backhaus - 1980 - Analyse & Kritik 2 (2):146-171.
    The purpose of the paper is a discussion of the meaning and relevance of the Pareto principle in economics. To begin with, the principle is briefly retraced in Pareto’s own writings. Its contemporary meaning was, however, developed in the context of the “New Welfare Economics”. While Pareto technically employed the principle in order to describe an equilibrium situation, Kaldor and Hicks developed it somewhat differently as a yardstick for economic policy formulation. Sometimes, the (...) is also discussed as a decision rule, and in this context some critics - though not the present author - believe it to have a conservative bias. Finally, recent discussions center around the incompatibility of the Pareto principle and “liberal” values. This conflict might be of limited relevance, only, due to a misconstrued formalism. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  8
    Coherence Against the Pareto Principle.John Broome - 2017 - In Weighing Goods. Oxford, UK: Wiley. pp. 151–164.
    The coherence of general good turns out to conflict with the widely accepted Pareto principle. This chapter explains the conflict and resolves it in favour of coherence. It also presents an example of a head‐on collision between coherence and the Pareto principle. The example relies on an auxiliary assumption, but one that is very plausible. The principle of personal good is immune to the difficulty raised by the probability agreement theorem. The theorem presents welfare economics (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The ex ante pareto principle.Anna Mahtani - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy 114 (6):303-323.
    The concept of ‘pareto superiority’ plays a central role in ethics, economics, and law. Pareto superiority is sometimes taken as a relation between outcomes, and sometimes as a relation between actions—even where the outcomes of the actions are uncertain. Whether one action is classed as (ex ante) pareto superior to another depends on the prospects under the actions for each person concerned. I argue that a person’s prospects (in this context) can depend on how that person is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22.  22
    Diskussion/Discussion. The Pareto Principle: Another View.Warren J. Samuels - 1981 - Analyse & Kritik 3 (1):124-134.
    The Pareto principle is in fact the fundamental concept of welfare economics. However, it has serious analytical and heuristic limits, is selective and conservative in nature and use, and is heavily normative notwithstanding the pretensions by advocates of its positive character.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  3
    Social choice without the Pareto principle: a comprehensive analysis.Susumu Cato - 2012 - Social Choice and Welfare 39:869–889.
    This article provides a systematic analysis of social choice theory without the Pareto principle, by revisiting the method of Murakami Yasusuke. This article consists of two parts. The first part investigates the relationship between rationality of social preference and the axioms that make a collective choice rule either Paretian or anti-Paretian. In the second part, the results in the first part are applied to obtain impossibility results under various rationality requirements of social preference, such as S-consistency, quasi-transitivity, semi-transitivity, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  76
    Social choice, the strong Pareto principle, and conditional decisiveness.Susumu Cato - 2013 - Theory and Decision 75 (4):563-579.
    This paper examines social choice theory with the strong Pareto principle. The notion of conditional decisiveness is introduced to clarify the underlying power structure behind strongly Paretian aggregation rules satisfying binary independence. We discuss the various degrees of social rationality: transitivity, semi-transitivity, the interval-order property, quasi-transitivity, and acyclicity.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Share the Sugar.Christian Tarsney, Harvey Lederman & Dean Spears - manuscript
    We provide a general argument against value incomparability, based on a new style of impossibility result. In particular, we show that, against plausible background assumptions, value incomparability creates an incompatibility between two very plausible principles for ranking lotteries: a weak "negative dominance" principle (to the effect that Lottery 1 can be better than Lottery 2 only if some possible outcome of Lottery 1 is better than some possible outcome of Lottery 2) and a weak form of ex (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Frege’s puzzle and the ex ante Pareto principle.Anna Mahtani - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (6):2077-2100.
    The ex ante Pareto principle has an intuitive pull, and it has been a principle of central importance since Harsanyi’s defence of utilitarianism. The principle has been used to criticize and refine a range of positions in welfare economics, including egalitarianism and prioritarianism. But this principle faces a serious problem. I have argued elsewhere :303-323 2017) that the concept of ex ante Pareto superiority is not well defined, because its application in a choice situation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  21
    Diskussion/Discussion. The Pareto Principle and Policy Analysis.Jürgen Backhaus - 1981 - Analyse & Kritik 3 (2):237-246.
    Warren Samuels has suggested that the Pareto Principle, when being used in policy analysis, is (1) limited, (2) selective, and (3) displays a conservative bias. In contrast to this view, in this note it is argued that the Pareto Principle is much less limited than was initially perceived (e.g. by Pareto himself) or is generally believed to be the case, that it tends to emphasize inclusiveness instead of selectivity, and that it is more likely to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  35
    The Reflection Principle and the Ex-Ante Pareto Principle in Anna Mahtani’s Objects of Credence.Luc Bovens - forthcoming - Economics and Philosophy:1-7.
    First, Mahtani argues that both in the game The Mug and in the Sleeping Beauty we should not defer to a trusted person under a particular designation if they do not self-identify under this designation. This invites a more complex Reflection Principle. I respond that there are more parsimonious ways to avoid the challenges posed to the Reflection Principle. Second, Mahtani argues that preferences create a hyperintensional context, which poses a challenge to the Ex-Ante Pareto Principle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  76
    Liberty, Equality and the Pareto Principle: A Comment on Weale.Iain McLean - 1980 - Analysis 40 (4):212 - 213.
  30.  12
    The Weak Vopěnka Principle for Definable Classes of Structures.Joan Bagaria & Trevor M. Wilson - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (1):145-168.
    We give a level-by-level analysis of the Weak Vopěnka Principle for definable classes of relational structures ( $\mathrm {WVP}$ ), in accordance with the complexity of their definition, and we determine the large-cardinal strength of each level. Thus, in particular, we show that $\mathrm {WVP}$ for $\Sigma _2$ -definable classes is equivalent to the existence of a strong cardinal. The main theorem (Theorem 5.11) shows, more generally, that $\mathrm {WVP}$ for $\Sigma _n$ -definable classes is equivalent to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  32
    How perspective-based aggregation undermines the Pareto principle.Itai Sher - 2020 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 19 (2):182-205.
    The Pareto principle is a normative principle about preferences that advocates concordance with unanimous preference. However, people have perspectives not just preferences. Evaluating preferences...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Weighing and aggregating reasons under uncertainty: a trilemma.Ittay Nissan-Rozen - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (9):2853-2871.
    I discuss the trilemma that consists of the following three principles being inconsistent: 1. The Common Principle: if one distribution, A, necessarily brings a higher total sum of personal value that is distributed in a more egalitarian way than another distribution, B, A is more valuable than B. 2. (Weak) ex-ante Pareto: if one uncertain distribution, A, is more valuable than another uncertain distribution, B, for each patient, A is more valuable than B. 3. Pluralism about attitudes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  19
    The weak pigeonhole principle for function classes in S12.Norman Danner & Chris Pollett - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (6):575-584.
    It is well known that S12 cannot prove the injective weak pigeonhole principle for polynomial time functions unless RSA is insecure. In this note we investigate the provability of the surjective weak pigeonhole principle in S12 for provably weaker function classes.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Autonomy, welfare, and the Pareto principle.Daniel A. Farber - 2015 - In Aristides N. Hatzis & Nicholas Mercuro (eds.), Law and economics: philosophical issues and fundamental questions. New York, NY: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  17
    Weak reflection principle, saturation of the nonstationary ideal on ω 1 and diamonds.Víctor Torres-pérez - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (2):724-736.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  18
    Dual weak pigeonhole principle, Boolean complexity, and derandomization.Emil Jeřábek - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 129 (1-3):1-37.
    We study the extension 123) of the theory S21 by instances of the dual weak pigeonhole principle for p-time functions, dWPHPx2x. We propose a natural framework for formalization of randomized algorithms in bounded arithmetic, and use it to provide a strengthening of Wilkie's witnessing theorem for S21+dWPHP. We construct a propositional proof system WF , which captures the Π1b-consequences of S21+dWPHP. We also show that WF p-simulates the Unstructured Extended Nullstellensatz proof system of Buss et al. 256). We (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37. Anthropic fluctuations vs. weak anthropic principle.Milan M. Ćirković - 2002 - Foundations of Science 7 (4):453-463.
    A modern assessment of the classical Boltzmann-Schuetz argument for large-scale entropy fluctuations as the origin of our observable cosmological domain is given.The emphasis is put on the central implication of this picture which flatly contradicts the weak anthropic principle as an epistemological statement about the universe. Therefore, to associate this picture with the anthropic principle as it is usually done is unwarranted. In particular, Feynman's criticism of theanthropic principle based on the entropy-fluctuation picture is a product (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  71
    A note on Murakami’s theorems and incomplete social choice without the Pareto principle.Wesley H. Holliday & Mikayla Kelley - 2020 - Social Choice and Welfare 55:243-253.
    In Arrovian social choice theory assuming the independence of irrelevant alternatives, Murakami (1968) proved two theorems about complete and transitive collective choice rules that satisfy strict non-imposition (citizens’ sovereignty), one being a dichotomy theorem about Paretian or anti-Paretian rules and the other a dictator-or-inverse-dictator impossibility theorem without the Pareto principle. It has been claimed in the later literature that a theorem of Malawski and Zhou (1994) is a generalization of Murakami’s dichotomy theorem and that Wilson’s (1972) impossibility theorem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. The weak anthropic principle and the design argument.Joseph M. Zycinski - 1996 - Zygon 31 (1):115-130.
    The design argument for God’s existence was critically assessed when in the growth of modern science the cognitive value of teleological categories was called into question. In recent discussions dealing with anthropic principles there has appeared a new version of the design argument, in which cosmic design is described without the use of teleological terms. The weak anthropic principle (WAP), a most critical version of all these principles, describes the fine-tuning of physical parameters necessary to the genesis of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  56
    A very weak square principle.Matthew Foreman & Menachem Magidor - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (1):175-196.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  41.  42
    Utilitarianism and Pareto principle: A comment.Eerik Lagerspetz - 1984 - Theory and Decision 16 (1):107-109.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  64
    The rigid relation principle, a new weak choice principle.Joel David Hamkins & Justin Palumbo - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (6):394-398.
    The rigid relation principle, introduced in this article, asserts that every set admits a rigid binary relation. This follows from the axiom of choice, because well-orders are rigid, but we prove that it is neither equivalent to the axiom of choice nor provable in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice. Thus, it is a new weak choice principle. Nevertheless, the restriction of the principle to sets of reals is provable without the axiom of choice.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  18
    A finite family weak square principle.Ernest Schimmerling - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (3):1087-1110.
  44. Dual weak pigeonhole principle, pseudo-surjective functions, and provability of circuit lower bounds.Jan Krajíček - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (1):265-286.
    This article is a continuation of our search for tautologies that are hard even for strong propositional proof systems like EF, cf. [Kra-wphp,Kra-tau]. The particular tautologies we study, the τ-formulas, are obtained from any.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  9
    Induction, bounding, weak combinatorial principles, and the homogeneous model theorem.Denis Roman Hirschfeldt - 2017 - Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society. Edited by Karen Lange & Richard A. Shore.
    Goncharov and Peretyat'kin independently gave necessary and sufficient conditions for when a set of types of a complete theory is the type spectrum of some homogeneous model of. Their result can be stated as a principle of second order arithmetic, which is called the Homogeneous Model Theorem (HMT), and analyzed from the points of view of computability theory and reverse mathematics. Previous computability theoretic results by Lange suggested a close connection between HMT and the Atomic Model Theorem (AMT), which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  71
    Minimal belief change and the pareto principle.Oliver Schulte - 1999 - Synthese 118 (3):329-361.
    This paper analyzes the notion of a minimal belief change that incorporates new information. I apply the fundamental decision-theoretic principle of Pareto-optimality to derive a notion of minimal belief change, for two different representations of belief: First, for beliefs represented by a theory – a deductively closed set of sentences or propositions – and second for beliefs represented by an axiomatic base for a theory. Three postulates exactly characterize Pareto-minimal revisions of theories, yielding a weaker set of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  18
    A model-theoretic characterization of the weak pigeonhole principle.Neil Thapen - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 118 (1-2):175-195.
    We bring together some facts about the weak pigeonhole principle from bounded arithmetic, complexity theory, cryptography and abstract model theory. We characterize the models of arithmetic in which WPHP fails as those which are determined by an initial segment and prove a conditional separation result in bounded arithmetic, that PV + lies strictly between PV and S21 in strength, assuming that the cryptosystem RSA is secure.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  48.  13
    Dual weak pigeonhole principle, pseudo-surjective functions, and provability of circuit lower bounds.Jan Kraj�?Ek - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (1):265-286.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49.  57
    Health care and the prospective pareto principle.Allan Gibbard - 1984 - Ethics 94 (2):261-282.
  50.  19
    The Weak Choice Principle WISC may Fail in the Category of Sets.David Michael Roberts - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (5):1005-1017.
    The set-theoretic axiom WISC states that for every set there is a set of surjections to it cofinal in all such surjections. By constructing an unbounded topos over the category of sets and using an extension of the internal logic of a topos due to Shulman, we show that WISC is independent of the rest of the axioms of the set theory given by a well-pointed topos. This also gives an example of a topos that is not a predicative topos (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000