Results for 'Neuroscientists'

696 found
Order:
  1.  19
    The neuroscientist's summary.J. Z. Young - 2009 - Brain and Mind 908:397.
  2.  48
    A Neuroscientist’s Perspective on Debates about the Nature of Emotion.Joseph LeDoux - 2012 - Emotion Review 4 (4):375-379.
    The target articles by Dixon (2012), Scarantino (2012), and Mulligan and Scherer (2012) explore the nature of emotion from philosophical and psychological perspectives. I discuss how neuroscience can also contribute to debates about the nature of emotion. I focus on the aspects of emotion that usually fall within the topic of basic emotions, but conclude that we may need to revise how we conceive and study these kinds of emotional states in relation to the brain.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3.  6
    The Neuroscientist’s Memoir: Dramatic Irony and Disorders of Consciousness.Ralph James Savarese - 2022 - Substance 51 (3):54-70.
    Abstract:This essay explores new technologies of communication, mischievously suggesting that an ordinary memoir, on some fundamental level, is no different from what occurred with a young woman in a persistent vegetative state who “willfully modulated [her] brain activity.” If, as Elaine Scarry famously suggested, readers produce mental imagery “under the instruction of a writer,” then thinking about the role of alternative and augmentative communication (AAC) in providing such instruction might help us to think through the relationship between cognition and generic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  16
    What Neuroscientists Think, and Don’t Think, About Consciousness.Peter D. Kitchener & Colin G. Hales - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16.
    The approach the majority of neuroscientists take to the question of how consciousness is generated, it is probably fair to say, is to ignore it. Although there are active research programs looking at correlates of consciousness, and explorations of informational properties of what might be relevant neural ensembles, the tacitly implied mechanism of consciousness in these approaches is that it somehow just happens. This reliance on a “magical emergence” of consciousness does not address the “objectively unreasonable” proposition that elements (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  34
    Free will: philosophers and neuroscientists in conversation.Uri Maoz & Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (eds.) - 2022 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    What is free will? Can it exist in a determined universe? How can we determine who, if anyone, possesses it? Philosophers have been debating these questions for millennia. In recent decades neuroscientists have joined the fray with questions of their own. Which neural mechanisms could enable conscious control of action? What are intentional actions? Do contemporary developments in neuroscience rule out free will or, instead, illuminate how it works? Over the past few years, neuroscientists and philosophers have increasingly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6. A neuroscientist's field guide In W. Bechtel, P. Mandik, J. Mundale & RS Stufflebeam.Paul M. Churchland & Patricia S. Churchland - 2001 - In William P. Bechtel, Pete Mandik, Jennifer Mundale & Robert S. Stufflebeam (eds.), Philosophy and the Neurosciences: A Reader. Blackwell. pp. 419--430.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  42
    Neuroscientists need to be evolutionarily challenged.Robert A. Barton - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (1):13-14.
    Evolutionary theory and methods are central to understanding the design of organisms, including their brains. This book does much to demonstrate the value of evolutionary neuroscience. Further work is needed to clarify the ways that neural systems evolved in general (specifically, the interaction between mosaic and coordinated evolution of brain components), and phylogenetic methods should be given a more prominent role in the analysis of comparative data.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Views of Addiction Neuroscientists and Clinicians on the Clinical Impact of a 'Brain Disease Model of Addiction'.Stephanie Bell, Adrian Carter, Rebecca Mathews, Coral Gartner, Jayne Lucke & Wayne Hall - 2013 - Neuroethics 7 (1):19-27.
    Addiction is increasingly described as a “chronic and relapsing brain disease”. The potential impact of the brain disease model on the treatment of addiction or addicted individuals’ treatment behaviour remains uncertain. We conducted a qualitative study to examine: (i) the extent to which leading Australian addiction neuroscientists and clinicians accept the brain disease view of addiction; and (ii) their views on the likely impacts of this view on addicted individuals’ beliefs and behaviour. Thirty-one Australian addiction neuroscientists and clinicians (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9. Intertheoretic reduction: A neuroscientist's field guide.Paul M. Churchland & Patricia S. Churchland - 1992 - In Y. Christen & P. S. Churchland (eds.), Neurophilosophy and Alzheimer's Disease. Cambridge: Springer Verlag. pp. 18--29.
  10.  5
    Is the neuroscientist's grandmother in the notebook? Integrated information and reference frames in the search for consciousness.Giuseppe Riva - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    This commentary suggests that the physical substrate of integrated information is dependent on the reference frame used to observe it. Furthermore, it uses a thought experiment – can a neuroscientist, locked in a closed room and connected through Zoom with his grandmother to demonstrate that the consciousness of his grannie is NOT in the PC? – to underline the problems that neglecting reference frames may cause to consciousness research.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue About Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain.Jean-Pierre Changeux & Paul Ricoeur - 2000 - Princeton.
    In a remarkable exchange between neuroscientist Jean-Pierre Changeux and philosopher Paul Ricoeur, this book explores the vexed territory between these...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  12. One for the neuroscientist.Adam S. Wilkins - 1999 - Bioessays 21 (4):361-361.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  16
    Basic stereology for biologists and neuroscientists.Mark J. West - 2012 - Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press: Cold Spring Harbor, New York.
    Stereological techniques allow biologists to create quantitative, three-dimensional descriptions of biological structures from two- dimensional images of tissue viewed under the microscope. For example, they can accurately estimate the size of a particular organelle, the total length of a mass of capillaries, or the number of neurons or synapses in a particular region of the brain. This book provides a practical guide to designing and critically evaluating stereological studies of the nervous system and other tissues. It explains the basic concepts (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Intertheoretic reduction: A neuroscientist’s field guide.P. M. Churchland & P. S. Churchland - 1998 - In Y. Christen & P. Churchland (eds.), Neurophilosophy and Alzheimer’s Disease. Springer.
  15.  9
    One for the neuroscientist.D. A. Brown - 1999 - Bioessays 21 (4):361-361.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Compatibilism(s) for neuroscientists.Michael S. Moore - 2014 - In Enrique Villanueva (ed.), Law and the Philosophy of Action. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Brill | Rodopi.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  66
    States of mind: a neuroscientist searches for the seat of consciousness. [REVIEW]Ned Block - 2024 - Science 384 (6696):629.
  18.  17
    On the Nature of Explanations Offered by Network Science: A Perspective From and for Practicing Neuroscientists.Maxwell A. Bertolero & Danielle S. Bassett - 2020 - Topics in Cognitive Science 12 (4):1272-1293.
    Network neuroscience represents the brain as a collection of regions and inter-regional connections. Given its ability to formalize systems-level models, network neuroscience has generated unique explanations of neural function and behavior. The mechanistic status of these explanations and how they can contribute to and fit within the field of neuroscience as a whole has received careful treatment from philosophers. However, these philosophical contributions have not yet reached many neuroscientists. Here we complement formal philosophical efforts by providing an applied perspective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  95
    Control and Responsibility in Addicted Individuals: What do Addiction Neuroscientists and Clinicians Think?Adrian Carter, Rebecca Mathews, Stephanie Bell, Jayne Lucke & Wayne Hall - 2013 - Neuroethics 7 (2):205-214.
    Impaired control over drug use is a defining characteristic of addiction in the major diagnostic systems. However there is significant debate about the extent of this impairment. This qualitative study examines the extent to which leading Australian addiction neuroscientists and clinicians believe that addicted individuals have control over their drug use and are responsible for their behaviour. One hour semi-structured interviews were conducted during 2009 and 2010 with 31 Australian addiction neuroscientists and clinicians (10 females and 21 males; (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. in The Future of the Brain: Essays by the World’s Leading Neuroscientists.Gary Marcus & Jeremy Freeman (eds.) - 2014 - Princeton University Press.
  21.  22
    Between the bench, the bedside and the office: The need to build bridges between working neuroscientists and ethicists.Caragh Brosnan & Alan Cribb - 2014 - Clinical Ethics 9 (4):113-119.
    This paper presents findings from an empirical study that explored the meaning of ethics in the everyday work of neuroscientists. Observation and interviews were carried out in one neuroscience research group that was involved in bench-to-bedside translational research. We focus here specifically on the scientists’ perceptions of bioethics. Interviewees were often unfamiliar with bioethics as a discipline, particularly the more junior members of the group. Those who were aware of its existence largely viewed it as something distant from them, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  6
    What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue About Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain.M. B. DeBevoise (ed.) - 2002 - Princeton University Press.
    Will understanding our brains help us to know our minds? Or is there an unbridgeable distance between the work of neuroscience and the workings of human consciousness? In a remarkable exchange between neuroscientist Jean-Pierre Changeux and philosopher Paul Ricoeur, this book explores the vexed territory between these divergent approaches--and comes to a deeper, more complex perspective on human nature.Ranging across diverse traditions, from phrenology to PET scans and from Spinoza to Charles Taylor, What Makes Us Think? revolves around a central (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  73
    Are current philosophical theories of consciousness useful to neuroscientists?Philip R. Sullivan - 2006 - Behavior and Philosophy 34:59-70.
    Two radically different families of theory currently compete for acceptance among theorists of human consciousness. The majority of theorists believe that the human brain somehow causes consciousness, but a significant minority holds that how the brain would cause this property is not only currently incomprehensible, but unlikely to become comprehensible despite continuing advances in brain science. Some of these latter theorists hold an alternate view that consciousness may well be one of the fundamentals in nature, and that the extremely complex (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Scientific Reforms, Feminist Interventions, and the Politics of Knowing: An Auto‐ethnography of a Feminist Neuroscientist.Sara Giordano - 2014 - Hypatia 29 (4):755-773.
    Feminist science studies scholars have documented the historical and cultural contingency of scientific knowledge production. It follows that political and social activism has impacted the practice of science today; however, little has been done to examine the current cultures of science in light of feminist critiques and activism. In this article, I argue that, although critiques have changed the cultures of science both directly and indirectly, fundamental epistemological questions have largely been ignored and neutralized through these policy reforms. I provide (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricreur, What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain Reviewed by.Chang-Seong Hong - 2002 - Philosophy in Review 22 (2):102-103.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Phenomenology as another toolbox for neuroscientists?[author unknown] - manuscript
    “[I]t has become next to impossible for a single mind fully to command more than a small specialized portion of it. I can see no other escape from this dilemma […] than that some of us should venture to..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  4
    The Brain as a Tool: A Neuroscientist's Account.Ray Guillery - 2017 - Oxford University Press.
    The Brain as a Tool considers two distinct views about the functions of the brain and how it interacts with the world. The book relates neural events to our sense of self and consciousness, summarizing important evidence which links neuroscience with cognitive psychology and philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. A psychologist's reply Ross Buck LeDoux and I clearly agree that psychologists studying emotion must be aware of the work of neuroscientists to provide a framework for their ideas, and that psychological theory and research may provide leads for neuroscientists.Ross Buck - 1986 - In David A. Oakley (ed.), Mind and Brain. Methuen. pp. 359.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  19
    Into the Grey Zone: A Neuroscientist Explores the Border Between Life and Death by Adrian Owen.Edward F. Kelly - 2018 - Journal of Scientific Exploration 32 (2).
    Dramatic modern advances in emergency and resuscitation medicine, starting perhaps with the development of effective mechanical ventilators in the mid-20th century, have created a large class of persons who in earlier times would almost certainly have died, but who can now go on existing, suspended at least temporarily in a state somewhere between death and the conscious life they formerly pursued. A very wide range of brain injuries lead first to coma, in which the patient shows no sign of conscious (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  46
    An emerging dialogue among social scientists and neuroscientists on the causal bases of emotion.Marc D. Lewis - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (2):223-234.
    The target article developed a dynamic systems framework that viewed the causal basis of emotion as a self-organizing process giving rise to cognitive appraisal concurrently. Commentators on the article evaluated this framework and the principles and mechanisms it incorporated. They also suggested additional principles, mechanisms, modeling strategies, and phenomena related to emotion and appraisal, in place of or extending from those already proposed. There was general agreement that nonlinear causal processes are fundamental to the psychology and neurobiology of emotion.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  63
    Beware of the Small-World Neuroscientist!David Papo, Massimiliano Zanin, Johann H. Martínez & Javier M. Buldú - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
  32.  10
    Jesus and Hume among the Neuroscientists: Haidt, Greene, and the Unwitting Return of Moral Sense Theory.John Perry - 2016 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 36 (1):69-85.
    The latest trend in ethics, sometimes dismissed as a fad, is the effort to connect ethics to empirical science. Two different versions of this “latest thing” can be found in the work of Jonathan Haidt and Joshua Greene. Their projects are, at least partly, unwitting recoveries of eighteenth-century Christian moral sense theory. Such similarities need not worry Christian ethicists but should instead inspire a careful retrieval of sentimentalism. It provides much of what today’s empirical ethicists hope to deliver without the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  99
    God Soul Mind Brain: A Neuroscientist's Reflections on the Spirit World by Michael S.A. Graziano.Gregory R. Peterson - 2011 - Zygon 46 (2):503-504.
  34.  52
    Happiness doesnt come in bottles. Neuroscientists learn that joy comes through dancing, not drugs.Walter J. Freeman - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (1):67-70.
    Too little has been written about the biology of joy. Most of the articles in the medical literature about brains and emotions are devoted to explaining how we feel fear, anger, anxiety and despair. This is understandable, because we don't go to doctors when we are feeling optimistic, happy and joyful. Most of what we know about the chemistry of our emotions has been learned from the disorders and the treatments of people who are sad and depressed. -/- But we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  5
    What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature and the Brain. [REVIEW]Paul Gyllenhammer - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):867-868.
    Centered on the question of normativity and ethics, neuroscientist Jean-Pierre Changeux and philosopher Paul Ricoeur engage in a lively and informative dialogue. They share a common insight concerning ethics, but let us first look at some of their differences.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  46
    What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain: Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur, translated by M. B. DeBevoise, Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2000, x+335 pp., $29.95 , ISBN 0-691-00940-6. [REVIEW]Kenneth Williford - 2005 - Minds and Machines 15 (1):91-97.
  37.  52
    Changeux, Jean-Pierre, and Paul Ricoeur. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature and the Brain. [REVIEW]Paul Gyllenhammer - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):867-868.
  38.  35
    Book Review: What Makes Us Think?: A Neuroscientist and a Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. [REVIEW]David Kaplan - 2004 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 1 (1):115-118.
  39.  39
    Review of Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur. 2000. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. [REVIEW]Robert H. Blank - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (4):69-70.
  40.  21
    Review of Jean-Pierre Changeux and Paul Ricoeur. 2000. What Makes Us Think? A Neuroscientist and Philosopher Argue about Ethics, Human Nature, and the Brain. [REVIEW]Robert H. Blank - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (4):69-70.
  41.  81
    The social implications of neurobiological explanations of resistible compulsions.Adrian Carter & Wayne Hall - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (1):15 – 17.
    The authors comments on several articles on addiction. Research suggests that addicted individuals have substantial impairments in cognitive control of behavior. The authors maintain that a proper study of addiction must include a neurobiological model of addiction to draw the attention of bioethicists and addiction neurobiologists. They also state that more addiction neuroscientists like S. E. Hyman are needed as they understand the limits of their research. Accession Number: 24077921; Authors: Carter, Adrian 1; Email Address: [email protected] Hall, Wayne 1; (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  9
    Philosophy, Psychiatry and Neuroscience: Three Approaches to the Mind: A Synthetic Analysis of the Varieties of Human Experience.Edward M. Hundert - 1989 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This book proposes a new, unified view of the mind which integrates the insights of philosophers, psychologists, and neuroscientists. Through a detailed discussion of major theories from all these, and related disciplines, the author gradually reveals fundamental links between these previously unconnected approaches to human thought and experience. The author has studied medicine, philosophy, mathematics and history, and is currently a practising psychiatrist and a teacher at the Harvard Medical School. He discusses diverse fields of thought with depth and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The autonomy of psychology in the age of neuroscience.Ken Aizawa & Carl Gillet - 2011 - In Phyllis McKay Illari Federica Russo (ed.), Causality in the Sciences. Oxford University Press. pp. 202--223.
    Sometimes neuroscientists discover distinct realizations for a single psychological property. In considering such cases, some philosophers have maintained that scientists will abandon the single multiply realized psychological property in favor of one or more uniquely realized psychological properties. In this paper, we build on the Dimensioned theory of realization and a companion theory of multiple realization to argue that this is not the case. Whether scientists postulate unique realizations or multiple realizations is not determined by the neuroscience alone, but (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  44. Investigating neural representations: the tale of place cells.William Bechtel - 2016 - Synthese 193 (5):1287-1321.
    While neuroscientists often characterize brain activity as representational, many philosophers have construed these accounts as just theorists’ glosses on the mechanism. Moreover, philosophical discussions commonly focus on finished accounts of explanation, not research in progress. I adopt a different perspective, considering how characterizations of neural activity as representational contributes to the development of mechanistic accounts, guiding the investigations neuroscientists pursue as they work from an initial proposal to a more detailed understanding of a mechanism. I develop one illustrative (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  45.  96
    The physical basis of memory.C. R. Gallistel - 2021 - Cognition 213 (C):104533.
    Neuroscientists are searching for the engram within the conceptual framework established by John Locke's theory of mind. This framework was elaborated before the development of information theory, before the development of information processing machines and the science of computation, before the discovery that molecules carry hereditary information, before the discovery of the codon code and the molecular machinery for editing the messages written in this code and translating it into transcription factors that mark abstract features of organic structure such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  46.  31
    Functional Neuroimaging: Technical, Logical, and Social Perspectives.Geoffrey K. Aguirre - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (s2):8-18.
    Neuroscientists have long sought to study the dynamic activity of the human brain—what's happening in the brain, that is, while people are thinking, feeling, and acting. Ideally, an inside look at brain function would simultaneously and continuously measure the biochemical state of every cell in the central nervous system. While such a miraculous method is science fiction, a century of progress in neuroimaging technologies has made such simultaneous and continuous measurement a plausible fiction. Despite this progress, practitioners of modern (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  93
    Brains as analog-model computers.Oron Shagrir - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3):271-279.
    Computational neuroscientists not only employ computer models and simulations in studying brain functions. They also view the modeled nervous system itself as computing. What does it mean to say that the brain computes? And what is the utility of the ‘brain-as-computer’ assumption in studying brain functions? In previous work, I have argued that a structural conception of computation is not adequate to address these questions. Here I outline an alternative conception of computation, which I call the analog-model. The term (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  48. The Mental States of Persons and their Brains.Tim Crane - 2015 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 76:253-270.
    Cognitive neuroscientists frequently talk about the brain representing the world. Some philosophers claim that this is a confusion. This paper argues that there is no confusion, and outlines one thing that might mean, using the notion of a model derived from the philosophy of science. This description is then extended to make apply to propositional attitude attributions. A number of problems about propositional attitude attributions can be solved or dissolved by treating propositional attitudes as models.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  49. Our brains are not us.Walter Glannon - 2009 - Bioethics 23 (6):321-329.
    Many neuroscientists have claimed that our minds are just a function of and thus reducible to our brains. I challenge neuroreductionism by arguing that the mind emerges from and is shaped by interaction among the brain, body, and environment. The mind is not located in the brain but is distributed among these three entities. I then explore the implications of the distributed mind for neuroethics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50.  50
    Weighing in on decisions in the brain: neural representations of pre-awareness practical intention.Robyn Repko Waller - 2021 - Synthese 199 (1-2):5175-5203.
    Neuroscientists have located brain activity that prepares or encodes action plans before agents are aware of intending to act. On the basis of these findings and broader agency research, activity in these regions has been proposed as the neural realizers of practical intention. My aim in this paper is to evaluate the case for taking these neural states to be neural representations of intention. I draw on work in philosophy of action on the role and nature of practical intentions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 696