Switch to: Citations

References in:

I Ought, Therefore I Can

Philosophical Studies 136 (2):167-216 (2007)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. `Ought implies can' and two kinds of morality.John Kekes - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (137):459-467.
    The principle, Ought implies can, Has two versions. The strong version expresses a necessary condition for the appropriateness of moral judgments; the weak version expresses a possible ground for excusing wrongdoing. The strong version is presupposed by choice-Morality, While the weak one is presupposed by character-Morality. It is argues that the strong version and choice-Morality are mistaken and that the weak version and character-Morality give a much more plausible account of our moral experience. The general conclusion is that choice is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • [Book review] against liberalism. [REVIEW]Wallace Matson - 1997 - Ethics 108 (3):602-606.
  • Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals.Immanuel Kant - 1785 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Thomas E. Hill & Arnulf Zweig.
    In this classic text, Kant sets out to articulate and defend the Categorical Imperative - the fundamental principle that underlies moral reasoning - and to lay the foundation for a comprehensive account of justice and human virtues. This new edition and translation of Kant's work is designed especially for students. An extensive and comprehensive introduction explains the central concepts of Groundwork and looks at Kant's main lines of argument. Detailed notes aim to clarify Kant's thoughts and to correct some common (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1044 citations  
  • Does “ought” imply “can”?Daniel Kading - 1954 - Philosophical Studies 5 (1):11 - 15.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hume's surprise and the logic of belief changes.Ingvar Johansson - 1998 - Synthese 117 (2):275-291.
    If the logic of belief changes is extended to cover belief states which contain both factual and normative beliefs, it is easily shown that a change of a factual belief (an 'Is') in a mixed belief state can imply a change of a normative belief (an 'Ought') in the same state. With regard to Hume's so-called 'Is-Ought problem', this means that one has to distinguish its statics from its dynamics. When this is done, it becomes clear that changes of factual (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Understanding the Logic of Obligation.Frank Jackson & J. E. J. Altham - 1988 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 (1):255 - 283.
  • Is “Ought Implies Can” a Moral Principle?Russell Jacobs - 1985 - Southwest Philosophy Review 2:43-54.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is “Ought Implies Can” a Moral Principle?Russell Jacobs - 1985 - Southwest Philosophy Review 2:43-54.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • First Steps in a Philosophical Taxonomy.I. L. Humberstone - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (3):476-478.
    A.N. Prior once showed that on certain apparently reasonable assumptions, a thesis sometimes associated with the name of Hume to the effect that no set of factual statements can ever entail an evaluative statement, is quite untenable. We assume only that there is at least one statement of each kind, and that the negation of a factual statement is factual — a principle we may call ‘N'. Now consider the disjunction F V E of some factual with some evaluative statement. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • First Steps in Philosophical Taxonomy.I. L. Humberstone - 1982 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (3):467-478.
    A.N. Prior once showed that on certain apparently reasonable assumptions, a thesis sometimes associated with the name of Hume to the effect that no set of factual statements can ever entail an evaluative statement, is quite untenable. We assume only that there is at least one statement of each kind, and that the negation of a factual statement is factual — a principle we may call ‘N'. Now consider the disjunction F V E of some factual with some evaluative statement. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A study in philosophical taxonomy.I. L. Humberstone - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 83 (2):121 - 169.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Rejection of Objective Consequentialism.Frances Howard-Snyder - 1997 - Utilitas 9 (2):241-248.
    Objective consequentialism is often criticized because it is impossible to know which of our actions will have the best consequences. Why exactly does this undermine objective consequentialism? I offer a new link between the claim that our knowledge of the future is limited and the rejection of objective consequentialism: that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ and we cannot produce the best consequences available to us. I support this apparently paradoxical contention by way of an analogy. I cannot beat Karpov at chess in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Models for Modalities: Selected Essays. [REVIEW]Robert C. Stalnaker - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (15):456-460.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • ‘“Ought” Implies “CAN”’1: PHILOSOPHY.G. P. Henderson - 1966 - Philosophy 41 (156):101-112.
    The dictum ‘“ought” implies “can”’ has a status in moral philosophy in some respects like that of ‘a good player needs good co-ordination’ in talk about ball-games. Clearly, you say something important but not conclusive about proficiency in playing a ball-game when you say that it requires good co-ordination: similarly, you say something important but not conclusive about obligation when you say that it implies a certain possibility or power or ability. Each dictum is a reminder: the one about such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Excuses and.Lawrence L. Heintz - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (3):449-462.
    I will attempt to do two things in this paper.In Part I) I will show that H.A. Prichard failed to appreciate the limitations of the application of the ‘“ought” implies “can”’ principle. Where the ‘can’ is not the ‘can’ of physical impossibility the principle is false; the principle can be shown to be false when it is read this way by an examination of the role of excuses, which is not that of removing obligations. Part II) demonstrates how the misapplication (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • But what should I do?Sven Ove Hansson - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (3-4):433-440.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Symposium: Freedom of the Will.Stuart Hampshire, W. G. Maclagan & R. M. Hare - 1951 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25 (1):161 - 216.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Symposium: Freedom of the Will.Stuart Hampshire, W. G. Maclagan & R. M. Hare - 1951 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25 (1):161-216.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Symposium: Freedom of the Will.Stuart Hampshire, W. G. Maclagan & R. M. Hare - 1951 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 25 (1):161-216.
  • Frankfurt-pairs and varieties of blameworthiness: Epistemic morals. [REVIEW]Ishtiyaque Haji - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (3):351-377.
    I start by using “Frankfurt-type” examples to cast preliminary doubt on the “Objective View” - that one is blameworthy for an action only if that action is objectively wrong, and follow by providing further arguments against this view. Then I sketch a replacement for the Objective View whose core is that one is to blame for performing an action, A, only if one has the belief that it is morally wrong for one to do A, and this belief plays an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Doing the best one can and the principle of alternative possibilities.Ishtiyaque Haji - 1994 - Southwest Philosophy Review 10 (2):113-127.
    I defend the view that if one ought (morally) always to do the best one can, there cannot be a wrong action one cannot avoid performing for which one is morally responsible. I also argue that there cannot be a wrong action to which there are no alternative possibilities for which an agent is morally responsible if the thesis that ought' implies can' is true. My argument against a fully general principle of alternative possibilities does have implications, which I briefly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Epistemic Dimension of Blameworthiness.Ishtiyaque Haji - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (3):523-544.
    The author first argues against the view that an agent is morally blameworthy for performing an action only if it is morally wrong for that agent to perform that action. The author then proposes a replacement for this view whose gist is summarized in the principle: an agent S is morally blameworthy for performing action A only if S has the belief that it is wrong for her to do A and this belief plays an appropriate role in S’s Aing. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs.James Griffin - 1996 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    The book asks how, and how much, we can improve our ethical standards—not lift our behaviour closer to our standards but refine the standards themselves. To answer this question requires answering most of the major questions of ethics. So the book includes a discussion of what a good life is like, where the bounds of the natural world come, how values relate to that world (e.g. naturalism, realism), how great human capacities—the ones important to ethics—are, and where moral norms come (...)
  • Conditional oughts and hypothetical imperatives.P. S. Greenspan - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (10):259-276.
  • "Ought" Implies "Can".G. P. Henderson - 1966 - Philosophy 41 (156):101 - 112.
    The dictum ‘“ought” implies “can”’ has a status in moral philosophy in some respects like that of ‘a good player needs good co-ordination’ in talk about ball-games. Clearly, you say something important but not conclusive about proficiency in playing a ball-game when you say that it requires good co-ordination: similarly, you say something important but not conclusive about obligation when you say that it implies a certain possibility or power or ability. Each dictum is a reminder: the one about such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Innocence lost: an examination of inescapable moral wrongdoing.Christopher W. Gowans - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Our lives are such that moral wrongdoing is sometimes inescapable for us. We have moral responsibilities to persons which may conflict and which it is wrong to violate even when they do conflict. Christopher W. Gowans argues that we must accept this conclusion if we are to make sense of our moral experience and the way in which persons are valuable to us. In defending this position, he critically examines the recent moral dilemmas debate. He maintains that what is important (...)
  • Dated rightness and moral imperfection.Holly S. Goldman - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (4):449-487.
  • The Abilities of Prescriptivism.Margaret Gilbert - 1972 - Analysis 32 (4):141 - 144.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Review of James W. Forrester: Why You Should: The Pragmatics of Deontic Speech.[REVIEW]William Tolhurst - 1990 - Ethics 100 (4):888-888.
  • Recent work on moral responsibility.John Fischer - 1999 - Ethics 110 (1):93–139.
  • ‘Ought-implies-can’, causal determinism and moral responsibility.John Martin Fischer - 2003 - Analysis 63 (3):244–250.
  • 'Ought-implies-can', causal determinism and moral responsibility.J. M. Fischer - 2003 - Analysis 63 (3):244-250.
  • The Definition of Good.Alfred Ewing - 1948 - Philosophy 24 (88):82-83.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • A Difficulty with ‘Ought Implies Can’.Frederick E. Brouwer - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):45-50.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Promises, obligations, and abilities.Julia Driver - 1983 - Philosophical Studies 44 (2):221 - 223.
  • Consistency in Rationalist Moral Systems.Alan Donagan - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (6):291.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • 'Ought-Implies-Can' and Hume's Rule.D. G. Collingridge - 1977 - Philosophy 52 (201):348 - 351.
  • Ought implies can and deontic logic.Norman O. Dahl - 1974 - Philosophia 4 (4):485-511.
  • Defending the principle of alternate possibilities: Blameworthiness and moral responsibility.David Copp - 1997 - Noûs 31 (4):441-456.
    According to the principle of alternate possibilities (PAP), a person is morally responsible for an action only if he could have done otherwise. PAP underlies a familiar argument for the incompatibility of moral responsibility with determinism. I argue that Harry Frankfurt's famous argument against PAP is unsuccessful if PAP is interpreted as a principle about blameworthiness. My argument turns on the maxim that "ought implies can" as well as a "finely-nuanced" view of the object of blame. To reject PAP on (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Some presuppositions of moral judgments.Neil Cooper - 1966 - Mind 75 (297):45-57.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The autonomy of evaluation.David Collingridge - 1980 - Journal of Value Inquiry 14 (2):119-127.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘Ought-lmplies-Can’ and Hume's Rule.D. G. Collingridge - 1977 - Philosophy 52 (201):348.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Justification for a Doctrine of Strict Liability.Stephen Cohen - 1982 - Social Theory and Practice 8 (2):213-229.
  • What Conflict of Duty is Not.Toni Vogel Carey - 1985 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1-2):204-215.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Moral theory and the ought--can principle.James Brown - 1977 - Mind 86 (342):206-223.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Five Types of Ethical Theory.C. D. Broad - 1930 - Humana Mente 5 (19):463-465.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   128 citations  
  • A difficulty with 'ought implies can'.Frederick E. Brouwer - 1969 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):45-50.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Moral Realism: Facts and Norms. [REVIEW]David O. BRINK - 1991 - Ethics 101 (3):610-624.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   479 citations  
  • Moral conflict and its structure.David O. Brink - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (2):215-247.
  • The Kantian versus Frankfurt.Alex Blum - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):287–288.