Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The grammar of science.Karl Pearson - 1911 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
  • The Scientific Image.William Demopoulos & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):603.
  • Hempel’s Ambiguity.J. Alberto Coffa - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):141 - 163.
  • Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability.Rudolf Carnap & Richard C. Jeffrey (eds.) - 1971 - University of California Press.
    A basic system of inductive logic; An axiomatic foundation for the logic of inductive generalization; A survey of inductive systems; On the condition of partial exchangeability; Representation theorems of the de finetti type; De finetti's generalizations of excahngeability; The structure of probabilities defined on first-order languages; A subjectivit's guide to objective chance.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • On the application of inductive logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 8 (1):133-148.
  • Causal laws and effective strategies.Nancy Cartwright - 1979 - Noûs 13 (4):419-437.
    La autora presenta algunas criticas generales al proyecto de reducir las leyes causales a probabilidades. Además, muestra que las leyes causales son imprescindibles para poder diferenciar las strategias efectivas de las que no lo son y da un criterio para considerar cuando podemos deducir causalidad a través de datos estadísticos.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  • The logic of causal propositions.Arthur W. Burks - 1951 - Mind 60 (239):363-382.
  • The place of the explanation of particular facts in science.William P. Alston - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (1):13-34.
    On the critical side it is argued that, contrary to a widespread view, the explanation of particular facts does not play a central role in pure science and hence that philosophers of science are misguided in supposing that the understanding of such explanations is one of the central tasks of the philosophy of science. It is suggested that the view being attacked may stem in part from an impression that the establishing of a general law is tantamount to the explanation (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Comments on Professor Roger Buck's Paper "Reflexive Predictions.".Adolf Grünbaum - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (4):370 - 372.
    Professor Buck has given an illuminating account of the logical status of reflexive predictions in the social sciences. He tells us that the classification of a prediction as reflexive is predicated on a tacit distinction between the “normal” and the “abnormal” or perturbed conditions under which it is made. This seems to me to be a perceptive and sound circumscription of the class of reflexive predictions as encountered in the social sciences. He goes on to show helpfully how the social (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The nature of explanation.Peter Achinstein - 1983 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Offering a new approach to scientific explanation, this book focuses initially on the explaining act itself.
  • Naming and Necessity: Lectures Given to the Princeton University Philosophy Colloquium.Saul A. Kripke - 1980 - Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Edited by Darragh Byrne & Max Kölbel.
  • Explanatory unification.Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (4):507-531.
    The official model of explanation proposed by the logical empiricists, the covering law model, is subject to familiar objections. The goal of the present paper is to explore an unofficial view of explanation which logical empiricists have sometimes suggested, the view of explanation as unification. I try to show that this view can be developed so as to provide insight into major episodes in the history of science, and that it can overcome some of the most serious difficulties besetting the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   576 citations  
  • Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World.Wesley C. Salmon - 1985 - Princeton University Press.
    The philosophical theory of scientific explanation proposed here involves a radically new treatment of causality that accords with the pervasively statistical character of contemporary science. Wesley C. Salmon describes three fundamental conceptions of scientific explanation--the epistemic, modal, and ontic. He argues that the prevailing view (a version of the epistemic conception) is untenable and that the modal conception is scientifically out-dated. Significantly revising aspects of his earlier work, he defends a causal/mechanical theory that is a version of the ontic conception. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Aspekte wissenschaftlicher Erklärung.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1977 - De Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Wissenschaftstheorie der Naturwissenschaft.Bernulf Kanitscheider - 1981 - New York: de Gruyter.
    No categories
  • Scientific explanation.James Woodward - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):41-67.
    Issues concerning scientific explanation have been a focus of philosophical attention from Pre- Socratic times through the modern period. However, recent discussion really begins with the development of the Deductive-Nomological (DN) model. This model has had many advocates (including Popper 1935, 1959, Braithwaite 1953, Gardiner, 1959, Nagel 1961) but unquestionably the most detailed and influential statement is due to Carl Hempel (Hempel 1942, 1965, and Hempel & Oppenheim 1948). These papers and the reaction to them have structured subsequent discussion concerning (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Elements of symbolic logic.Hans Reichenbach - 1947 - London: Dover Publications.
  • The theory of probability.Hans Reichenbach - 1949 - Berkeley,: University of California Press.
    We must restrict to mere probability not only statements of comparatively great uncertainty, like predictions about the weather, where we would cautiously ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   222 citations  
  • The rise of scientific philosophy.Hans Reichenbach - 1951 - Berkeley,: University of California Press.
    The student of philosophy usually is not irritated by obscure formulations. On the contrary, reading the quoted passage he would presumably be convinced ...
  • The direction of time.Hans Reichenbach - 1956 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications. Edited by Maria Reichenbach.
    The final work of a distinguished physicist, this remarkable volume examines the emotive significance of time, the time order of mechanics, the time direction of thermodynamics and microstatistics, the time direction of macrostatistics, and the time of quantum physics. Coherent discussions include accounts of analytic methods of scientific philosophy in the investigation of probability, quantum mechanics, the theory of relativity, and causality. "[Reichenbach’s] best by a good deal."—Physics Today. 1971 ed.
  • Laws and explanation in history.William H. Dray - 1957 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
  • Philosophical problems of space and time.Adolf Grünbaum - 1963 - Boston,: Reidel.
  • Philosophical Foundations of Physics;.Rudolf Carnap - 1966 - New York: Basic Books.
  • The philosophy of the inductive sciences.William Whewell - 1967 - London,: Cass.
    THE PHILOSOPHY OF THe INDUCTIVE SCIENCES. PART II. OF KNOWLEDGE. ' . VOL. II. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Teleological Explanations.Andrew Woodfield & Larry Wright - 1978 - Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110):86.
  • Maxwell's Condition—Goodman's Problem.Mark Wilson - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):107-123.
  • Explanation, Causation and Deduction.Fred Wilson - 1987 - Philosophy of Science 54 (2):311-313.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inductive explanation.Raimo Tuomela - 1981 - Synthese 48 (2):257 - 294.
  • Morgan on deductive explanation: A rejoinder. [REVIEW]Raimo Tuomela - 1976 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 5 (4):527 - 543.
    This paper is mainly a response to Charles Morgan's criticisms (this journal, pp. 511-25) of the author's model of the (formal aspects of) explanation. It is claimed in the paper that with two modifications and some additional specifications the model withstands Morgan's criticisms.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Explaining explaining.Raimo Tuomela - 1980 - Erkenntnis 15 (2):211 - 243.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Explaining the unpredictable.Patrick Suppes - 1985 - Erkenntnis 22 (1-3):187 - 195.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A probabilistic theory of causality.Patrick Suppes - 1970 - Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co..
  • Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Band I: Wissenschaftliche Erklärung und Begründung.Joseph J. Kockelmans - 1970 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 1 (1):142-150.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Relevant deduction.Gerhard Schurz - 1991 - Erkenntnis 35 (1-3):391 - 437.
    This paper presents an outline of a new theory of relevant deduction which arose from the purpose of solving paradoxes in various fields of analytic philosophy. In distinction to relevance logics, this approach does not replace classical logic by a new one, but distinguishes between relevance and validity. It is argued that irrelevant arguments are, although formally valid, nonsensical and even harmful in practical applications. The basic idea is this: a valid deduction is relevant iff no subformula of the conclusion (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Outline of a theory of scientific understanding.Gerhard Schurz & Karel Lambert - 1994 - Synthese 101 (1):65-120.
    The basic theory of scientific understanding presented in Sections 1–2 exploits three main ideas.First, that to understand a phenomenonP (for a given agent) is to be able to fitP into the cognitive background corpusC (of the agent).Second, that to fitP intoC is to connectP with parts ofC (via arguments in a very broad sense) such that the unification ofC increases.Third, that the cognitive changes involved in unification can be treated as sequences of shifts of phenomena inC. How the theory fits (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Erklären und Verstehen in der Wissenschaft.G. Schurz - 1990 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 44 (4):671-675.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Die wende der philosophie.Moritz Schlick - 1930 - Erkenntnis 1 (1):4-11.
  • The status of prior probabilities in statistical explanation.Wesley C. Salmon - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (2):137-146.
    A consideration of some basic problems that arise in the attempt to provide an adequate characterization of statistical explanation is taken to show that an understanding of the nature of scientific explanation requires us to deal with the philosophical problems connected with the nature of prior probabilities.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On vindicating induction.Wesley C. Salmon - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (3):252-261.
    This paper deals with the problem of vindicating a particular type of inductive rule, a rule to govern inferences from observed frequencies to limits of relative frequencies. Reichenbach's rule of induction is defended. By application of two conditions, normalizing conditions and a criterion of linguistic invariance, it is argued that alternative rules lead to contradiction. It is then argued that the rule of induction does not lead to contradiction when suitable restrictions are placed upon the predicates admitted. Goodman's grue-bleen paradox (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation.Peter Railton - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (2):206-226.
    It has been the dominant view that probabilistic explanations of particular facts must be inductive in character. I argue here that this view is mistaken, and that the aim of probabilistic explanation is not to demonstrate that the explanandum fact was nomically expectable, but to give an account of the chance mechanism(s) responsible for it. To this end, a deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation is developed and defended. Such a model has application only when the probabilities occurring in covering laws (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Logik der Forschung. [REVIEW]E. N. - 1935 - Journal of Philosophy 32 (4):107-108.
  • A critique of Suppes' theory of probabilistic causality.Richard Otte - 1981 - Synthese 48 (2):167 - 189.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Statistical explanation reconsidered.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1981 - Synthese 48 (3):437 - 472.
  • The Structure of Science.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):275-275.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   871 citations  
  • Bemerkungen zur pragmatisch-epistemischen wende in der wissenschaftstheoretischen analyse der ereigniserklärungen.Hans Lenk - 1985 - Erkenntnis 22 (1-3):461 - 473.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ein verbesserter deduktiv-nomologischer Erklärungsbegriff.Michael Küttner - 1976 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 7 (2):274-297.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ein verbesserter deduktiv-nomologischer erklärungsbegriff.Michael Küttner - 1976 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 7 (2):274-297.
    Summary Directly concluded from a set of some well-known and some new conditions of adequacy, a definition of deductive-nomological explanation is given which is able to block all known anomalies, and is immune from the Eberle/Kaplan/Montague trivialization theorems. Among some other results it is further shown that law statements have to be logically equivalent to a conditional form.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the logical conditions of deductive explanation.Jaegwon Kim - 1963 - Philosophy of Science 30 (3):286-291.
    Hempel and Oppenheim have stated in Part III of their paper “Studies in the Logic of Explanation” [2] a set of conditions for deductive explanation. However, their analysis has come under damaging systematic criticisms in a recent paper by Eberle, Kaplan and Montague [1], The principal aim of the present paper is to review the Hempel-Oppenheim analysis and propose a strengthened version of it that avoids the recent criticisms.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Statistical ambiguity and maximal specificity.W. C. Humphreys - 1968 - Philosophy of Science 35 (2):112-115.
  • Aleatory explanations.Paul W. Humphreys - 1981 - Synthese 48 (2):225 - 232.