Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Accommodating Surprise in Taxonomic Tasks: The Role of Expertise.Eugenio Alberdi, Derek H. Sleeman & Meg Korpi - 2000 - Cognitive Science 24 (1):53-91.
    This paper reports a psychological study of human categorization that looked at the procedures used by expert scientists when dealing with puzzling items. Five professional botanists were asked to specify a category from a set of positive and negative instances. The target category in the study was defined by a feature that was unusual, hence situations of uncertainty and puzzlement were generated. Subjects were asked to think aloud while solving the tasks, and their verbal reports were analyzed. A number of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • AlphaGo, Locked Strategies, and Eco-Cognitive Openness.Lorenzo Magnani - 2019 - Philosophies 4 (1):8.
    Locked and unlocked strategies are at the center of this article, as ways of shedding new light on the cognitive aspects of deep learning machines. The character and the role of these cognitive strategies, which are occurring both in humans and in computational machines, is indeed strictly related to the generation of cognitive outputs, which range from weak to strong level of knowledge creativity. I maintain that these differences lead to important consequences when we analyze computational AI programs, such as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Herbert Simon’s Computational Models of Scientific Discovery.Stephen Downes - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):97-108.
    Herbert Simon’s work on scientific discovery deserves serious attention by philosophers of science for several reasons. First, Simon was an early advocate of rational scientific discovery, contra Popper and logical empiricist philosophers of science (Simon 1966). This proposal spurred on investigation of scientific discovery in philosophy of science, as philosophers used and developed Simon’s notions of “problem solving” and “heuristics” in attempts to provide rational accounts of scientific discovery (See Nickles 1980a, Wimsatt 1980). Second, Simon promoted and developed many of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creating a discoverer: Autonomous knowledge seeking agent. [REVIEW]Jan M. Zytkow - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):253-283.
    Construction of a robot discoverer can be treated as the ultimate success of automated discovery. In order to build such an agent we must understand algorithmic details of the discovery processes and the representation of scientific knowledge needed to support the automation. To understand the discovery process we must build automated systems. This paper investigates the anatomy of a robot-discoverer, examining various components developed and refined to a various degree over two decades. We also clarify the notion of autonomy of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rule acquisition events in the discovery of problem‐solving strategies.Kurt VanLehn - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (1):1-47.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Machine discovery in chemistry: new results.Raúl E. Valdés-Pérez - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 74 (1):191-201.
  • Conjecturing hidden entities by means of simplicity and conservation laws.Raúl E. Valdés-Pérez - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 65 (2):247-280.
  • On bureaucracy and science a response to Fuller.Ryan D. Tweney - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (2):203-213.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “What if…”: The Use of Conceptual Simulations in Scientific Reasoning.Susan Bell Trickett & J. Gregory Trafton - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (5):843-875.
    The term conceptual simulation refers to a type of everyday reasoning strategy commonly called “what if” reasoning. It has been suggested in a number of contexts that this type of reasoning plays an important role in scientific discovery; however, little direct evidence exists to support this claim. This article proposes that conceptual simulation is likely to be used in situations of informational uncertainty, and may be used to help scientists resolve that uncertainty. We conducted two studies to investigate the relationship (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • How Do Scientists Respond to Anomalies? Different Strategies Used in Basic and Applied Science.Susan Bell Trickett, J. Gregory Trafton & Christian D. Schunn - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (4):711-729.
    We conducted two in vivo studies to explore how scientists respond to anomalies. Based on prior research, we identify three candidate strategies: mental simulation, mental manipulation of an image, and comparison between images. In Study 1, we compared experts in basic and applied domains (physics and meteorology). We found that the basic scientists used mental simulation to resolve an anomaly, whereas applied science practitioners mentally manipulated the image. In Study 2, we compared novice and expert meteorologists. We found that unlike (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Précis of simple heuristics that make us Smart.Peter M. Todd & Gerd Gigerenzer - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5):727-741.
    How can anyone be rational in a world where knowledge is limited, time is pressing, and deep thought is often an unattainable luxury? Traditional models of unbounded rationality and optimization in cognitive science, economics, and animal behavior have tended to view decision-makers as possessing supernatural powers of reason, limitless knowledge, and endless time. But understanding decisions in the real world requires a more psychologically plausible notion of bounded rationality. In Simple heuristics that make us smart (Gigerenzer et al. 1999), we (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Philosophy and machine learning.Paul Thagard - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):261-76.
    This article discusses the philosophical relevance of recent computational work on inductive inference being conducted in the rapidly growing branch of artificial intelligence called machine learning.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An interactive system for finding complementary literatures: a stimulus to scientific discovery.Don R. Swanson & Neil R. Smalheiser - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 91 (2):183-203.
  • Naturalizing epistemology: Quine, Simon and the prospects for pragmatism.Stephen Stich - 1993 - In C. Hookway & D. Peterson (eds.), Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement. Cambridge University Press. pp. 1-17.
    In recent years there has been a great deal of discussion about the prospects of developing a “naturalized epistemology,” though different authors tend to interpret this label in quite different ways.1 One goal of this paper is to sketch three projects that might lay claim to the “naturalized epistemology” label, and to argue that they are not all equally attractive. Indeed, I’ll maintain that the first of the three – the one I’ll attribute to Quine – is simply incoherent. There (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Naturalizing Epistemology: Quine, Simon and the Prospects for Pragmatism.Stephen Stich - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:1-17.
    In recent years there has been a great deal of discussion about the prospects of developing a ‘naturalized epistemology’, though different authors tend to interpret this label in quite different ways. One goal of this paper is to sketch three projects that might lay claim to the ‘naturalized epistemology’ label, and to argue that they are not all equally attractive. Indeed, I'll maintain that the first of the three—the one I'll attribute to Quine—is simply incoherent. There is no way we (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Scientific discovery as problem solving.Herbert A. Simon, Patrick W. Langley & Gary L. Bradshaw - 1981 - Synthese 47 (1):3 – 14.
  • Scientific discovery as problem solving: Reply to critics.Herbert A. Simon - 1992 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (1):69 – 88.
  • On simulating Simon: His monomania, and its sources in bounded rationality.Herbert Simon - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 32 (3):501-505.
  • Machine discovery.Herbert Simon - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):171-200.
    Human and machine discovery are gradual problem-solving processes of searching large problem spaces for incompletely defined goal objects. Research on problem solving has usually focused on search of an instance space (empirical exploration) and a hypothesis space (generation of theories). In scientific discovery, search must often extend to other spaces as well: spaces of possible problems, of new or improved scientific instruments, of new problem representations, of new concepts, and others. This paper focuses especially on the processes for finding new (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Discovering explanations.Herbert A. Simon - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (1):7-37.
  • The process of discovery.Wei-Min Shen - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):233-251.
    This paper argues that all discoveries, if they can be viewed as autonomous learning from the environment, share a common process. This is the process of model abstraction involving four steps: act, predict, surprise, and refine, all built on top of the discoverer's innate actions, percepts, and mental constructors. The evidence for this process is based on observations on various discoveries, ranging from children playing to animal discoveries of tools, from human problem solving to scientific discovery. Details of this process (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sent Simulating Simon Simulating Scientists.Esther-Mirjam Sent - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 32 (3):479-500.
    The paper consists of a reflexive exercise in which Herbert Simon's views concerning science are applied to his own research. It argues that what connected his ventures into so many different disciplinary domains was a search for complex, hierarchical systems. In the process, the paper establishes a close connection between Simon's insights and his focus on simulation. Instead of simulating Simon on a computer, though, it simulates Simon on paper. This exercise is then contrasted with Simon's own attempts to simulate (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Generality/Specificity of Expertise in Scientific Reasoning.Christian D. Schunn & John R. Anderson - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (3):337-370.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Discovering scientific questions.Roger C. Schank & Lucian P. Hughes - 1992 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (1):57 – 59.
  • Why have a heuristic of scientific discovery?Angelo M. Petroni - 1992 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (1):53 – 55.
  • Conventionalism, scientific discovery and the sociology of knowledge.Angelo M. Petroni - 1993 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (3):225-240.
    In this paper the basic aim of the so‐called ‘strong programme’ in the sociology of knowledge is examined. The ‘strong programme’ is considered (and rightly so) as an extreme version of the anti‐realist view of science. While the problem of scientific realism has normally been dealt with from the point of view of the ‘context of justification’ of theories, the paper focuses on the issues raised by law‐discovery. In this context Herbert Simon's views about the existence of a ‘logic of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Collaborative discovery in a scientific domain.Takeshi Okada & Herbert A. Simon - 1997 - Cognitive Science 21 (2):109-146.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Data-driven approaches to empirical discovery.Pat Langley & Jan M. Zytkow - 1989 - Artificial Intelligence 40 (1-3):283-312.
  • The Influence of Anomalous Data on Solving Human Abductive Tasks.Andreas Keinarh & Josef F. Krems - 1998 - Philosophica 61 (1).
    This paper describes an abductive process model of anomalous data integration. The model makes use of the entrenchment of the current explanation and the probability of alternative explanations. It is hypothesised that increasing confirmation of the anom-aly itself increases the probability of alternative explanations. In an experimental study we found that both the entrenchment of an existing explanation and confirmation of the anomaly clearly influence how people resolve anomalous data. These results are in agreement with the predic-tions of the model.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science as heuristic search: Some comments on Simon 's theory.Philip Johnson‐Laird & Paolo Legrenzi - 1992 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 6 (1):35 – 39.
  • Intelligence and Creativity in Problem Solving: The Importance of Test Features in Cognition Research.Saskia Jaarsveld & Thomas Lachmann - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
  • Scientific Discovery Reloaded.Emiliano Ippoliti - 2020 - Topoi 39 (4):847-856.
    The way scientific discovery has been conceptualized has changed drastically in the last few decades: its relation to logic, inference, methods, and evolution has been deeply reloaded. The ‘philosophical matrix’ moulded by logical empiricism and analytical tradition has been challenged by the ‘friends of discovery’, who opened up the way to a rational investigation of discovery. This has produced not only new theories of discovery, but also new ways of practicing it in a rational and more systematic way. Ampliative rules, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Brownian notions: One historicist philosopher's resistance to psychology of science via three truisms and ecological validity.Arthur Houts & Barry Gholson - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (2):139 – 146.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Anomalous Evidence, Confidence Change, and Theory Change.Joshua A. Hemmerich, Kellie Van Voorhis & Jennifer Wiley - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (6):1534-1560.
    A novel experimental paradigm that measured theory change and confidence in participants' theories was used in three experiments to test the effects of anomalous evidence. Experiment 1 varied the amount of anomalous evidence to see if “dose size” made incremental changes in confidence toward theory change. Experiment 2 varied whether anomalous evidence was convergent or replicating. Experiment 3 varied whether participants were provided with an alternative theory that explained the anomalous evidence. All experiments showed that participants' confidence changes were commensurate (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction to Cognition in Science and Technology.Michael E. Gorman - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (4):675-685.
    Cognitive studies of science and technology have had a long history of largely independent research projects that have appeared in multiple outlets, but rarely together. The emergence of a new International Society for Psychology of Science and Technology suggests that this is a good time to put some of the latest work in this area into topiCS in a way that will both acquaint readers with the cutting edge in this domain and also give them a hint of its history. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Doing Science, Technology and Society in the National Science Foundation: Commentary on: “Engaged, Embedded, Enjoined: Science and Technology Studies in the National Science Foundation”.Michael E. Gorman - 2011 - Science and Engineering Ethics 17 (4):839-849.
    The author describes his efforts to become a participant observer while he was a Program Director at the NSF. He describes his plans for keeping track of his reflections and his goals before he arrived at NSF, then includes sections from his reflective diary and comments after he had completed his two-year rotation. The influx of rotators means the NSF has to be an adaptive, learning organization but there are bureaucratic obstacles in the way.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Confirmation, disconfirmation, and invention: The case of Alexander Graham bell and the telephone.Michael E. Gorman - 1995 - Thinking and Reasoning 1 (1):31 – 53.
  • Mapping Experiment as a Learning Process: How the First Electromagnetic Motor Was Invented.David Gooding - 1990 - Science, Technology and Human Values 15 (2):165-201.
    Narrative accounts misrepresent discovery by reconstructing worlds ordered by success rather than the world as explored. Such worlds rarely contain the personal knowledge that informed actual exploration and experiment. This article describes an attempt to recover situated learning in a material environment, tracing the discovery of the first electromagnetic motor by Michael Faraday in September 1821 to show how he modeled new experience and invented procedures to communicate that novelty. The author introduces a notation to map experiment as an active (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How to Be a Good Empiricist. [REVIEW]David Gooding - 1989 - British Journal for the History of Science 22 (4):419-427.
  • From tools to theories: A heuristic of discovery in cognitive psychology.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1991 - Psychological Review 98 (2):254-267.
  • Discovery in Cognitive Psychology: New Tools Inspire New Theories.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (2):329-350.
    The ArgumentScientific tools—measurement and calculation instruments, techniques of inference—straddle the line between the context of discovery and the context of justification. In discovery, new scientific tools suggest new theoretical metaphors and concepts; and in justification, these tool-derived theoretical metaphors and concepts are morelikely to be accepted by the scientific community if the tools are already entrenched in scientific practice.Techniques of statistical inference and hypothesis testing entered American psychology first as tools in the 1940s and 1950s and then as cognitive theories (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Implications of the Cognitive Sciences for the Philosophy of Science.Ronald N. Giere - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (2):418-430.
    Does recent work in the cognitive sciences have any implications for theories or methods employed within the philosophy of science itself? The answer to this question depends first on one’s conception of the philosophy of science and then on the nature of work being done in the various different fields comprising the cognitive sciences. For example, one might think of the philosophy of science as being an autonomous discipline that is both logically and epistemologically prior to any empirical inquiry. If (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a cognitive psychology of science.Barry Gholson & Arthur Houts - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (2):107 – 127.
  • Discovery by serendipity: A new context for an old Riddle. [REVIEW]Pio García - 2008 - Foundations of Chemistry 11 (1):33-42.
    In the last years there has been a great improvement in the development of computational methods for combinatorial chemistry applied to drug discovery. This approach to drug discovery is sometimes called a “rational way” to manage a well known phenomenon in chemistry: serendipity discoveries. Traditionally, serendipity discoveries are understood as accidental findings made when the discoverer is in quest for something else. This ‘traditional’ pattern of serendipity appears to be a good characterization of discoveries where “luck” plays a key role. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Executive Control of Scientific Discovery.Eric G. Freedman - 1998 - Philosophica 62 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Concept Discovery in a Scientific Domain.Kevin Dunbar - 1993 - Cognitive Science 17 (3):397-434.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • A computational approach to George Boole's discovery of mathematical logic.Luis de Ledesma, Aurora Pérez, Daniel Borrajo & Luis M. Laita - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 91 (2):281-307.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The computer revolution in science: steps towards the realization of computer-supported discovery environments.Hidde de Jong & Arie Rip - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 91 (2):225-256.
  • Shedding computational light on human creativity.Subrata Dasgupta - 2008 - Perspectives on Science 16 (2):pp. 121-136.
    Ever since 1956 when details of the Logic Theorist were published by Newell and Simon, a large literature has accumulated on computational models and theories of the creative process, especially in science, invention and design. But what exactly do these computational models/theories tell us about the way that humans have actually conducted acts of creation in the past? What light has computation shed on our understanding of the creative process? Addressing these questions, we put forth three propositions: (I) Computational models (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Multidisciplinary creativity: the case of Herbert A. Simon.Subrata Dasgupta - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (5):683-707.
    In the twentieth century, no person epitomized more dramatically the “Renaissance mind” than Herbert A. Simon (1916–2001). In aworking life spanning over 60 years, Simon made seminal contributions to administrative theory, axiomatic foundations of physics, economics, sociology, econometrics, cognitive psychology, logic of scientific discovery, and artificial intelligence. Simon's life of the mind, thus, affords nothing less than a “laboratory” in which to observe and examine at close quarters the phenomenon ofmultidisciplinary creativity. In this paper, we attempt to shed some light (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations