Works by Husak, Douglas (exact spelling)

55 found
Order:
  1.  47
    Retributivism and Over-Punishment.Douglas Husak - 2022 - Law and Philosophy 41 (2):169-191.
    Lately it has become a commonplace to complain about the injustice of mass incarceration. I share the sentiment that this phenomenon has been an injustice. But it also has become orthodoxy to allege that the acceptance of a retributive penal philosophy has been one of the chief factors that has brought about mass incarceration in the first place. As a self-proclaimed retributivist, I find these allegations to be troubling and unwarranted. The point of this paper is to take steps to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  2.  32
    The Objective(s) of Responsible Brains.Douglas Husak - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (2):267-281.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3. Negligence, Belief, Blame and Criminal Liability: The Special Case of Forgetting.Douglas Husak - 2011 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (2):199-218.
    Commentators seemingly agree about what negligence is—and how it is contrasted from recklessness. They also appear to concur about whether particular examples (both real and hypothetical) portray negligence. I am less confident about each of these matters. I explore the distinction between recklessness and negligence by examining a type of case that has generated a good deal of critical discussion: those in which a defendant forgets that he has created a substantial and unjustifiable risk of harm. Even in this limited (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  4. Paternalism and Consent.Douglas Husak - 2015 - In Thomas Schramme (ed.), New Perspectives on Paternalism and Health Care. Cham: Springer Verlag.
  5.  86
    Retributivism In Extremis.Douglas Husak - 2013 - Law and Philosophy 32 (1):3-31.
    I defend two objections to Tadros’s views on punishment. First, I allege that his criticisms of retributivism are persuasive only against extreme versions that provide no justificatory place for instrumentalist objectives. His attack fails against a version of retributivism that recognizes a chasm between what offenders deserve and the allthings-considered permissibility of treating offenders as they deserve. Second, I critique Tadros’s duty view – his alternative theory of punishment. Inter alia, I object that he derives principles from highly unusual examples (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  6.  81
    On the supposed priority of justification to excuse.Douglas Husak - 2005 - Law and Philosophy 24 (6):557-594.
  7.  62
    Vehicles and Crashes.Douglas Husak - 2004 - Social Theory and Practice 30 (3):351-370.
  8.  73
    The Criminal Law as Last Resort.Douglas Husak - 2004 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 24 (2):207-235.
    In this article I examine one condition a minimalist theory of criminalization might contain: the criminal law should be used only as a last resort. I discuss how this principle should be interpreted and the reasons we have to accept it. I conclude that a theory of criminalization should probably include the (appropriately construed) last resort principle. But this conclusion will prove disappointing to those who hope to employ this principle to bring about fundamental reform in the substantive criminal law. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  9.  78
    The Costs to Criminal Theory of Supposing that Intentions are Irrelevant to Permissibility.Douglas Husak - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (1):51-70.
    I attempt to describe the several costs that criminal theory would be forced to pay by adopting the view (currently fashionable among moral philosophers) that the intentions of the agent are irrelevant to determinations of whether his actions are permissible (or criminal).
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  10.  27
    Criminal Law at the Margins.Douglas Husak - 2020 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 14 (3):381-393.
    I describe how our understanding of some of the central principles long held dear by most criminal theorists may have to be interpreted in light of the need to devise lenient responses for low-level offenders. Several of the most plausible suggestions for how to deal with minor infractions force us to take seriously some ideas that many legal philosophers have tended to resist elsewhere. I briefly touch upon four topics: whether informal can substitute for or count against the appropriate state (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  21
    Larry Alexander and Kimberly Kessler Ferzan on Omissions and Normative Ignorance: A Critical Reply.Douglas Husak - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (3):441-454.
    Reflections on Crime and Culpability seeks to elaborate, extend, and occasionally qualify the insights reached by Larry Alexander and Kim Ferzan in their influential prior collaboration, Crime and Culpability. They deftly explore any number of new issue that all criminal theorists should be encouraged to address. In my essay, I discuss and challenge their positions on omissions as well as on moral ignorance. Their treatment of the latter issue is a clear improvement over that in their earlier book. But their (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  28
    Vehicles and Crashes.Douglas Husak - 2004 - Social Theory and Practice 30 (3):351-370.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13. Mistake of Law and Culpability.Douglas Husak - 2010 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (2):135-159.
    When does a defendant not deserve punishment because he is unaware that his conduct breaches a penal statute? Retributivists must radically rethink their answer to this question to do justice to our moral intuitions. I suggest that modest progress on this topic can be made by modeling our approach to ignorance of law on our familiar approach to ignorance of fact. We need to distinguish different levels of culpability in given mistakes and to differentiate what such mistakes may be about. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  30
    Aspiration, Execution, and Controversy: Reply to My Critics.Douglas Husak - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (2):351-362.
    I respond to Michael Zimmerman and Gideon Yaffe, both of whom have written thoughtful and constructive criticisms of my “Ignorance of Law”. Zimmerman believes I do not go far enough in exculpating morally ignorant wrongdoers; he accuses me of lacking the courage of my convictions in allowing exceptions for reckless wrongdoers and for willfully ignorant wrongdoers. Yaffe, by contrast, thinks I rely on a defective foundation of moral blameworthiness. He proposes an alternative account he alleges to conform more closely to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  14
    Introduction.Douglas Husak - 2021 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3):337-338.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  36
    Abetting a Crime.Douglas Husak - 2014 - Law and Philosophy 33 (1):41-73.
    I focus on the set of problems that arise in identifying both the actus reus and (to an even greater extent) the mens rea needed by an abettor before she should be criminally liable for complicity in a crime. No consensus on these issues has emerged in positive law; commentators are enormously dissatisfied with the decisions courts have reached; and critics disagree radically about what reforms should be implemented to rectify this state of affairs. I explicitly deny that I will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17. Four points about drug decriminalization.Douglas Husak - 2003 - Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (1):21-29.
  18.  43
    Drug Proscriptions as Proxy Crimes.Douglas Husak - 2017 - Law and Philosophy 36 (4):345-366.
    Our drug policy has been widely deemed a failure because the criminalization of drug use has not succeeded in reducing prevalence rates. I contend that the most promising basis to defend the justifiability of drug offenses is to construe them as proxy crimes: offenses designed to prevent the commission of other, more serious crimes. I make a case that many law enforcement officials use drug proscriptions for this purpose in the real world. When construed as proxy crimes, drug prohibitions are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. Intoxication and Culpability.Douglas Husak - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):363-379.
    I tackle the difficult problem of specifying how voluntary intoxication affects criminal culpability generally and recklessness in particular. I contend that the problem need not be conceptualized as an instance of actio libera in causa, namely the situation in which persons do something at t1 to culpably create the conditions of their own defense at t2. Instead, I argue that we need only consider intoxicated defendants at t2 in order to justify their punishment. In the course of defending my view, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Transferred Intent.Douglas Husak - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 10 (1):65-98.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21. Why Punish Attempts at All? Yaffe on 'The Transfer Principle'.Douglas Husak - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):399-410.
    Gideon Yaffe is to be commended for beginning his exhaustive treatment by asking a surprisingly difficult question: Why punish attempts at all? He addresses this inquiry in the context of defending (what he calls) the transfer principle: “If a particular form of conduct is legitimately criminalized, then the attempt to engage in that form of conduct is also legitimately criminalized.” I begin by expressing a few reservations about the transfer principle itself. But my main point is that we are justified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  29
    Gardner on the Philosophy of Criminal Law.Douglas Husak - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (1):169-187.
    Offences and Defences is an outstanding collection of eleven of John Gardner's previously published papers in the philosophy of criminal law. I briefly examine his views on five central issues: his claims about basic responsibility and whether it should be construed as relational; his positions on agent neutrality; his arguments about whether moral and criminal wrongs are typically strict; his thoughts about the structure of defences, and, finally, what his account of rape reveals about the content of the harm principle.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  21
    Is Fair Opportunity a Comprehensive Theory of Responsibility?Douglas Husak - forthcoming - Criminal Law and Philosophy:1-10.
    I challenge the adequacy of David Brink’s “master principle” of culpability. I allege that it fails to account for the moral relevance of ignorance of wrongdoing. I describe three cases in which I believe that Brink’s theory of normative competence cannot account for the significance of a variable that bears on culpability. In most of this paper I attempt to anticipate and reply to the various responses Brink might offer to my challenge.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  4
    Overcriminalization.Douglas Husak - 1996 - In Dennis M. Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell. pp. 621–631.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Meaning of Overcriminalization Why Overcriminalization Is Worrisome Political and Scholarly Causes of Overcriminalization A Normative Theory of Criminalization References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  14
    Require an Act?Douglas Husak - 1998 - In Antony Duff (ed.), Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique. Cambridge University Press. pp. 60.
  26.  25
    The" But-Everyone-Does-That!" Defense.Douglas Husak - 1996 - Public Affairs Quarterly 10 (4):307-334.
  27. In Favor of Drug Decriminalization.Douglas Husak - 2005 - In Andrew I. Cohen & Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 22--335.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  63
    Why Gun Control is So Hard.Douglas Husak - 2019 - Criminal Justice Ethics 38 (1):55-64.
    The issue of gun control is among a growing number of polarizing topics that may seem immune from meaningful compromise and rational debate. Although their intransience may be exaggerated, few citi...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  18
    Convergent Ends, Divergent Means: A Response to My Critics.Douglas Husak - 2009 - Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (1):119-134.
    When writing Overcriminalization, I entertained a fantasy about the reaction my book might produce. I hoped that philosophers would not merely criticize my shortcomings but would join me to produce...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. An alleged act requirement in the criminal law.Douglas Husak - 2011 - In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. A Framework for Punishment: What is the Insight of Hart's 'Prolegomenon'?Douglas Husak - 2014 - In C. G. Pulman (ed.), Hart on Responsibility. New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
  32. Beyond the Justification/Excuse Dichotomy.Douglas Husak - 2011 - In Rowan Cruft, Matthew H. Kramer & Mark R. Reiff (eds.), Crime, Punishment, and Responsibility: The Jurisprudence of Antony Duff. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  5
    Criminal law theory.Douglas Husak - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 107–121.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Need for a Theory of Criminalization The Nature of the Criminal Law Inadequate Theories of Criminalization A Better Approach to Criminalization References Further Reading.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  17
    Ignorance of Law: How to Conceptualize and Maybe Resolve the Issue.Douglas Husak - 2019 - In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law. Springer Verlag. pp. 315-333.
    Under what circumstances should ignorance that someone is violating a moral or criminal rule preclude or lessen his moral responsibility and/or penal liability? In this chapter, I first construct a schema or framework for how to think about this issue. Quite a bit of confusion and uncertainty, I am sure, derives from a failure to understand exactly what this question is asking. I next defend some substantive views about how this question should be answered. If my defense is cogent, I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  43
    Property.Douglas Husak - 1985 - Teaching Philosophy 8 (2):163-165.
  36.  19
    Proportionality in Personal Life.Douglas Husak - 2021 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3):339-360.
    Efforts to apply the principle of proportionality to criminal sentences are notoriously problematic. But even though they are daunting, only a few legal philosophers believe we should give up trying to do so. Perhaps we can make progress overcoming some of the many legal difficulties by attending to how the principle is applied in non-legal contexts—that is, in contexts I call personal life. Proportionality, I believe, is an attractive principle in penal sentencing because it is an attractive principle in ordinary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Reviewed by Kalle Grill, Royal Institute of Technology (KTH), Dept. of Philosophy and the History of Technology, Stockholm.Douglas Husak & Peter de Marneffe - 2007 - Theoria 73 (3):248-255.
  38.  9
    Richard Henson, 1925-2007.Douglas Husak - 2007 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 81 (2):173 -.
  39.  6
    Sentencing Pluralism.Douglas Husak - 2022 - In Matthew C. Altman (ed.), The Palgrave Handbook on the Philosophy of Punishment. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 419-437.
    Husak makes a number of theoretical observations in favor of a general conception of sentencing that he calls sentencing pluralism. This framework is pluralistic in two different respects. In the first part of the chapter, he argues that the goals or objectives of a sentencing scheme are diverse and must draw from the insights supplied by various disciplines. Thus his framework embodies what he calls disciplinary pluralism. In the second part of the chapter, he argues that the sentence offenders deserve (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  6
    The Function and Structure of the Substantive Criminal Law.Douglas Husak - 1999 - Law and Philosophy 18 (1):85-104.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  48
    Time-frames, voluntary acts, and strict liability.Douglas Husak & Brian P. McLaughlin - 1993 - Law and Philosophy 12 (1):95 - 120.
  42.  70
    Thirty Years of Law and Philosophy.Douglas Husak - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (2):141-142.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  41
    Wrongs, Crimes, and Criminalization.Douglas Husak - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (3):393-407.
    I will focus on Tadros’s general views about criminalization and how he contends philosophers should not think about it. Misguided approaches, according to Tadros, include attempts to identify principles that constrain the scope of the criminal law, as well as efforts to establish that given considerations constitute reasons for or against the use of the penal sanction. In what follows, I begin with a few general remarks about the connections between Tadros’s treatment of criminal justice and the real world. Next, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  56
    Social Engineering as an Infringement of the Presumption of Innocence: The Case of Corporate Criminality. [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2014 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (2):353-369.
    I examine how deferred-prosecution agreements employed against suspected corporate criminality amount to a form of social engineering that infringes the presumption. I begin with a broad understanding of the presumption itself. Then I offer a brief description of how these agreements function. Finally I address some of the normative issues that must be confronted if legal philosophers who hold retributivist views on punishment and sentencing hope to assess this device. My judgment tends to be favorable. More importantly, I caution against (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45. The Complete Guide to Consent to Sex: Alan Wertheimer’s Consent to Sexual Relations. [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2005 - Law and Philosophy 25 (2):267-287.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  46.  89
    Why Criminal Law: A Question of Content? [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2008 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (2):99-122.
    I take it as obvious that attempts to justify the criminal law must be sensitive to matters of criminalization—to what conduct is proscribed or permitted. I discuss three additional matters that should be addressed in order to justify the criminal law. First, we must have a rough idea of what degree of deviation is tolerable between the set of criminal laws we ought to have and the set we really have. Second, we need information about how the criminal law at (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  34
    The Philosophy of Criminal Law: Extending the Debates. [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (2):351-365.
    Larry Alexander and Peter Westen each critically examine different topics from my recent collection of essays, The Philosophy of Criminal Law. Alexander focuses on my “Rapes Without Rapists,” “Mistake of Law and Culpability,” and “Already Punished Enough.” Westen offers a more extended commentary on my “Transferred Intent.” I briefly reply to each critic in turn and try to extend the debates in new directions.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  62
    Brudner, Alan . Punishment and Freedom: A Liberal Theory of Penal Justice . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. Pp. 256. $130.00 (cloth). [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2010 - Ethics 120 (4):841-846.
  49.  23
    Answering Duff: R.A. Duff's Answering for Crime. [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (1):101 - 119.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    Editorial: Continuity Through Change. [REVIEW]Douglas Husak - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (2):123-125.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 55