Results for 'Seidenberg, Mark'

997 found
Order:
  1.  29
    A distributed, developmental model of word recognition and naming.Mark S. Seidenberg & James L. McClelland - 1989 - Psychological Review 96 (4):523-568.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   416 citations  
  2.  28
    Signing behavior in apes: A critical review.Mark S. Seidenberg & Laura A. Petitto - 1979 - Cognition 7 (2):177-215.
  3.  26
    The time course of phonological code activation in two writing systems.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Cognition 19 (1):1-30.
  4.  20
    Constraining models of word recognition.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Cognition 20 (2):169-190.
  5.  36
    A Probabilistic Constraints Approach to Language Acquisition and Processing.Mark S. Seidenberg & Maryellen C. MacDonald - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (4):569-588.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  6.  21
    Steps toward an ethological science.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):377-377.
  7.  32
    Distributional structure in language: Contributions to noun–verb difficulty differences in infant word recognition.Jon A. Willits, Mark S. Seidenberg & Jenny R. Saffran - 2014 - Cognition 132 (3):429-436.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  8.  32
    Computing the Meanings of Words in Reading: Cooperative Division of Labor Between Visual and Phonological Processes.Michael W. Harm & Mark S. Seidenberg - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (3):662-720.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  9.  53
    Quasiregularity and Its Discontents: The Legacy of the Past Tense Debate.Mark S. Seidenberg & David C. Plaut - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (6):1190-1228.
    Rumelhart and McClelland's chapter about learning the past tense created a degree of controversy extraordinary even in the adversarial culture of modern science. It also stimulated a vast amount of research that advanced the understanding of the past tense, inflectional morphology in English and other languages, the nature of linguistic representations, relations between language and other phenomena such as reading and object recognition, the properties of artificial neural networks, and other topics. We examine the impact of the Rumelhart and McClelland (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  13
    More words but still no lexicon: Reply to Besner et al. (1990).Mark S. Seidenberg & James L. McClelland - 1990 - Psychological Review 97 (3):447-452.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  28
    Phonology, reading acquisition, and dyslexia: Insights from connectionist models.Michael W. Harm & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1999 - Psychological Review 106 (3):491-528.
  12.  35
    On the bases of two subtypes of development dyslexia.Franklin R. Manis, Mark S. Seidenberg, Lisa M. Doi, Catherine McBride-Chang & Alan Petersen - 1996 - Cognition 58 (2):157-195.
  13.  13
    Language and connectionism: the developing interface.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1994 - Cognition 50 (1-3):385-401.
  14. Consistency effects in the generation of past tense morphology.Mark S. Seidenberg & Maggie Bruck - 1990 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 28 (6):522-522.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  67
    Specific language impairment: a deficit in grammar or processing?Marc F. Joanisse & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1998 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2 (7):240-247.
  16.  56
    Rules Versus Statistics: Insights From a Highly Inflected Language.Jelena Mirković, Mark S. Seidenberg & Marc F. Joanisse - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (4):638-681.
    Inflectional morphology has been taken as a paradigmatic example of rule-governed grammatical knowledge (Pinker, 1999). The plausibility of this claim may be related to the fact that it is mainly based on studies of English, which has a very simple inflectional system. We examined the representation of inflectional morphology in Serbian, which encodes number, gender, and case for nouns. Linguists standardly characterize this system as a complex set of rules, with disagreements about their exact form. We present analyses of a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17.  28
    Explanatory adequacy and models of word recognition.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):724-726.
  18.  24
    Lexicon as module.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):31-32.
  19.  48
    Writing systems: Not optimal, but good enough.Mark S. Seidenberg & Ram Frost - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (5):305.
    Languages and writing systems result from satisfying multiple constraints related to learning, comprehension, production, and their biological bases. Orthographies are not optimal because these constraints often conflict, with further deviations due to accidents of history and geography. Things tend to even out because writing systems and the languages they represent exhibit systematic trade-offs between orthographic depth and morphological complexity.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Books etcetera-talking nets: An oral history of neural networks.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1999 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3 (3):120-121.
  21.  11
    Box 1. Main types of morphological structure.Mark S. Seidenberg & Laura M. Gonnerman - 2000 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (9):353-361.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Connectionist models of reading.Mark S. Seidenberg - 2009 - In Gareth Gaskell (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Psycholinguistics. Oxford University Press.
  23. Evidence from great apes concerning the biological bases of language.Mark S. Seidenberg - 1986 - In William Demopoulos (ed.), Language Learning and Concept Acquisition. Ablex.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  25
    Writing systems: Not optimal, but good enough – Erratum.Mark S. Seidenberg - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (6):467-467.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  26
    Distinguishing literal from metaphorical applications of Bayesian approaches.Timothy T. Rogers & Mark S. Seidenberg - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (4):211-212.
    We distinguish between literal and metaphorical applications of Bayesian models. When intended literally, an isomorphism exists between the elements of representation assumed by the rational analysis and the mechanism that implements the computation. Thus, observation of the implementation can externally validate assumptions underlying the rational analysis. In other applications, no such isomorphism exists, so it is not clear how the assumptions that allow a Bayesian model to fit data can be independently validated.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Acquisition and representation of grammatical categories: Grammatical gender in a connectionist network.Jelena Mirkovic, Mark S. Seidenberg & Maryellen C. MacDonald - 2008 - In B. C. Love, K. McRae & V. M. Sloutsky (eds.), Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society. pp. 1954--1959.
  27.  24
    Computational bases of two types of developmental dyslexia.Michael W. Harm & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1996 - In Garrison W. Cottrell (ed.), Proceedings of the Eighteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Lawrence Erlbaum. pp. 18--364.
  28. Using connectionist networks to examine the role of prior constraints in human learning.Michael Harm, Lori Altmann & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1994 - In Ashwin Ram & Kurt Eiselt (eds.), Proceedings of the Sixteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Erlbaum. pp. 392--396.
  29.  21
    Understanding normal and impaired word reading: Computational principles in quasi-regular domains.David C. Plaut, James L. McClelland, Mark S. Seidenberg & Karalyn Patterson - 1996 - Psychological Review 103 (1):56-115.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  30.  31
    The lexical nature of syntactic ambiguity resolution.Maryellen C. MacDonald, Neal J. Pearlmutter & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1994 - Psychological Review 101 (4):676-703.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  31.  91
    Letting structure emerge: connectionist and dynamical systems approaches to cognition.James L. McClelland, Matthew M. Botvinick, David C. Noelle, David C. Plaut, Timothy T. Rogers, Mark S. Seidenberg & Linda B. Smith - 2010 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (8):348-356.
  32.  66
    On the nature and scope of featural representations of word meaning.Ken McRae, Virginia R. de Sa & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1997 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 126 (2):99-130.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  33.  31
    Efforts to Encourage Multidisciplinarity in the Cognitive Science Society.James G. Greeno, William J. Clancey, Clayton Lewis, Mark Seidenberg, Sharon Derry, Morton Ann Gernsbacher, Patrick Langley, Michael Shafto, Dedre Gentner, Alan Lesgold & Colleen M. Seifert - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (1):131-132.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  44
    Impact of dialect use on a basic component of learning to read.Megan C. Brown, Daragh E. Sibley, Julie A. Washington, Timothy T. Rogers, Jan R. Edwards, Maryellen C. MacDonald & Mark S. Seidenberg - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  10
    Preface.Morten H. Christiansen, Nick Chater & Mark S. Seidenberg - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (4):415-415.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  23
    Error, error everywhere: A look at megastudies of word reading.Daragh E. Sibley, Christopher T. Kello & Mark S. Seidenberg - 2009 - In N. A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (eds.), Proceedings of the 31st Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. pp. 1036--1041.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  65
    Letting Structure Emerge: Connectionist and Dynamical Systems Approaches to Cognition.Linda B. Smith James L. McClelland, Matthew M. Botvinick, David C. Noelle, David C. Plaut, Timothy T. Rogers, Mark S. Seidenberg - 2010 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (8):348.
  38. The Unreasonable Uncooperativeness of Mathematics in The Natural Sciences.Mark Wilson - 2000 - The Monist 83 (2):296-314.
    Let us begin with the simple observation that applied mathematics can be very tough! It is a common occurrence that basic physical principle instructs us to construct some syntactically simple set of differential equations, but it then proves almost impossible to extract salient information from them. As Charles Peirce once remarked, you can’t get a set of such equations to divulge their secrets by simply tilting at them like Don Quixote. As a consequence, applied mathematicians are often forced to pursue (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  39. Inference and Correlational Truth.Mark Wilson - 2000 - In Andre Chapuis & Anil Gupta (eds.), Circularity, Definition and Truth. New Delhi, India: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers Pvt. Ltd. in Association with Indian Council of Philosophical Research, New Delhi.
    This is one of those cases to which Dr. 8 oodhouse's remark applies with all its force, that a method which leads to true results must have its logic — H.S Smith (" On Some of the Methods at Present in Use in Pure Geometry," p. 6) A goodly amount of modern metaphysics has concerned itself, in one form or another, with the question: what attitude should we take in regard to a language whose semantic underpinnings seem less than certain? (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  40.  10
    Being measured: truth and falsehood in Aristotle's Metaphysics.Mark Richard Wheeler - 2019 - Albany, New York: State University of New York Press.
    On the basis of careful textual exegesis and philosophical analysis, and contrary to the received view, Mark R. Wheeler demonstrates that Aristotle presents and systematically explicates his definition of the essence of the truth in the Metaphysics. Aristotle states the nominal definitions of the terms "truth" and "falsehood" as part of his arguments in defense of the logical axioms. These nominal definitions express conceptions of truth and falsehood his philosophical opponents would have recognized and accepted in the context of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Ghost world: A context for Frege's context principle.Mark Wilson - 2005 - In Michael Beaney & Erich H. Reck (eds.), Gottlob Frege: Frege's philosophy of mathematics. London: Routledge. pp. 157-175.
    There is considerable likelihood that Gottlob Frege began writing his Foundations of Arithmetic with the expectation that he could introduce his numbers, not with sets, but through some algebraic techniques borrowed from earlier writers of the Gottingen school. These rewriting techniques, had they worked, would have required strong philosophical justification provided by Frege's celebrated "context principle," which otherwise serves little evident purpose in the published Foundations.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42.  22
    The ritual origin of counting.A. Seidenberg - 1962 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 2 (1):1-40.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  43. Beware the Blob: Cautions for Would-Be Metaphysicians.Mark Wilson - 2008 - In Dean Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics: Volume 4. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Animals as reflexive thinkers: The aponoian paradigm.Mark Rowlands & Susana Monsó - 2017 - In Linda Kalof (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Animal Studies. Oxford University Press. pp. 319-341.
    The ability to engage in reflexive thought—in thought about thought or about other mental states more generally—is regarded as a complex intellectual achievement that is beyond the capacities of most nonhuman animals. To the extent that reflexive thought capacities are believed necessary for the possession of many other psychological states or capacities, including consciousness, belief, emotion, and empathy, the inability of animals to engage in reflexive thought calls into question their other psychological abilities. This chapter attacks the idea that reflexive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. The Ubiquity of State-Given Reasons.Mark Schroeder - 2012 - Ethics 122 (3):457-488.
    Philosophers have come to distinguish between ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ kinds of reasons for belief, intention, and other attitudes. Several theories about the nature of this distinction have been offered, by far the most prevalent of which is the idea that it is, at bottom, the distinction between what are known as ‘object-given’ and ‘state-given’ reasons. This paper argues that the object-given/state-given theory vastly overgeneralizes on a small set of data points, and in particular that any adequate account of the distinction (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  46. Stakes, withholding, and pragmatic encroachment on knowledge.Mark Schroeder - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 160 (2):265 - 285.
    Several authors have recently endorsed the thesis that there is what has been called pragmatic encroachment on knowledge—in other words, that two people who are in the same situation with respect to truth-related factors may differ in whether they know something, due to a difference in their practical circumstances. This paper aims not to defend this thesis, but to explore how it could be true. What I aim to do, is to show how practical factors could play a role in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  47. Self, no self?: perspectives from analytical, phenomenological, and Indian traditions.Mark Siderits, Evan Thompson & Dan Zahavi (eds.) - 2011 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    It is time to bring the rich resources of these traditions into the contemporary debate about the nature of self. This volume is the first of its kind.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  48.  45
    The ritual origin of geometry.A. Seidenberg - 1961 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 1 (5):488-527.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  49. Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 143 (2):223 - 248.
    Intentions matter. They have some kind of normative impact on our agency. Something goes wrong when an agent intends some end and fails to carry out the means she believes to be necessary for it, and something goes right when, intending the end, she adopts the means she thinks are required. This has even been claimed to be one of the only uncontroversial truths in ethical theory. But not only is there widespread disagreement about why this is so, there is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  50.  9
    Did Euclid's elements, book I, develop geometry axiomatically?A. Seidenberg - 1975 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 14 (4):263-295.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 997