Results for 'completion of metric spaces'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  41
    Strong completeness of s4 for any dense-in-itself metric space.Philip Kremer - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):545-570.
    In the topological semantics for modal logic, S4 is well-known to be complete for the rational line, for the real line, and for Cantor space: these are special cases of S4’s completeness for any dense-in-itself metric space. The construction used to prove completeness can be slightly amended to show that S4 is not only complete, but also strongly complete, for the rational line. But no similarly easy amendment is available for the real line or for Cantor space and the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  2.  18
    Strong Completeness of Modal Logics Over 0-Dimensional Metric Spaces.Robert Goldblatt & Ian Hodkinson - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):611-632.
    We prove strong completeness results for some modal logics with the universal modality, with respect to their topological semantics over 0-dimensional dense-in-themselves metric spaces. We also use failure of compactness to show that, for some languages and spaces, no standard modal deductive system is strongly complete.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  53
    Notes on Logics of Metric Spaces.Oliver Kutz - 2007 - Studia Logica 85 (1):75-104.
    In [14], we studied the computational behaviour of various first-order and modal languages interpreted in metric or weaker distance spaces. [13] gave an axiomatisation of an expressive and decidable metric logic. The main result of this paper is in showing that the technique of representing metric spaces by means of Kripke frames can be extended to cover the modal (hybrid) language that is expressively complete over metric spaces for the (undecidable) two-variable fragment of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  50
    Dynamic topological logic of metric spaces.David Fernández-Duque - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):308-328.
    Dynamic Topological Logic ( $\mathcal{DTL}$ ) is a modal framework for reasoning about dynamical systems, that is, pairs 〈X, f〉 where X is a topological space and f: X → X a continuous function. In this paper we consider the case where X is a metric space. We first show that any formula which can be satisfied on an arbitrary dynamic topological system can be satisfied on one based on a metric space; in fact, this space can be (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  94
    Categoricity in homogeneous complete metric spaces.Åsa Hirvonen & Tapani Hyttinen - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (3-4):269-322.
    We introduce a new approach to the model theory of metric structures by defining the notion of a metric abstract elementary class (MAEC) closely resembling the notion of an abstract elementary class. Further we define the framework of a homogeneous MAEC were we additionally assume the existence of arbitrarily large models, joint embedding, amalgamation, homogeneity and a property which we call the perturbation property. We also assume that the Löwenheim-Skolem number, which in this setting refers to the density (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  20
    Logic and computation, Proceedings of a workshop held at Carnegie Mellon University, June 30–July 2, 1987, edited by Wilfried Sieg, Contemporary Mathematics, vol. 106, American Mathematical Society, Providence1990, xiv + 297 pp. - Douglas K. Brown. Notions of closed subsets of a complete separable metric space in weak subsystems of second order arithmetic. Pp. 39–50. - Kostas Hatzikiriakou and Stephen G. Simpson. WKL0 and orderings of countable abelian groups. Pp. 177–180. - Jeffry L. Hirst. Marriage theorems and reverse mathematics. Pp. 181–196. - Xiaokang Yu. Radon–Nikodym theorem is equivalent to arithmetical comprehension. Pp. 289–297. - Fernando Ferreira. Polynomial time computable arithmetic. Pp. 137–156. - Wilfried Buchholz and Wilfried Sieg. A note on polynomial time computable arithmetic. Pp. 51–55. - Samuel R. Buss. Axiomatizations and conservation results for fragments of bounded arithmetic. Pp. 57–84. - Gaisi Takeuti. Sharply bounded arithmetic and the function a – 1. Pp. 2. [REVIEW]Jörg Hudelmaier - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):697-699.
  7.  60
    Polish metric spaces: Their classification and isometry groups.John D. Clemens, Su Gao & Alexander S. Kechris - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):361-375.
    § 1. Introduction. In this communication we present some recent results on the classification of Polish metric spaces up to isometry and on the isometry groups of Polish metric spaces. A Polish metric space is a complete separable metric space.Our first goal is to determine the exact complexity of the classification problem of general Polish metric spaces up to isometry. This work was motivated by a paper of Vershik [1998], where he remarks (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  20
    Polish metric spaces with fixed distance set.Riccardo Camerlo, Alberto Marcone & Luca Motto Ros - 2020 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 171 (10):102832.
    We study Polish spaces for which a set of possible distances $A \subseteq R^+$ is fixed in advance. We determine, depending on the properties of A, the complexity of the collection of all Polish metric spaces with distances in A, obtaining also example of sets in some Wadge classes where not many natural examples are known. Moreover we describe the properties that A must have in order that all Polish spaces with distances in that set belong (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  28
    Projective subsets of separable metric spaces.Arnold W. Miller - 1990 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 50 (1):53-69.
    In this paper we will consider two possible definitions of projective subsets of a separable metric space X. A set A subset of or equal to X is Σ11 iff there exists a complete separable metric space Y and Borel set B subset of or equal to X × Y such that A = {x ε X : there existsy ε Y ε B}. Except for the fact that X may not be completely metrizable, this is the classical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  18
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis. Rolle's Theorem and Complete, Totally bounded, Metric Spaces.H. de Swart - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):289-298.
  11.  34
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis. Rolle's Theorem and Complete, Totally bounded, Metric Spaces.H. de Swart - 1976 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 22 (1):289-298.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  14
    Discrete metric spaces: Structure, enumeration, and 0-1 laws.Dhruv Mubayi & Caroline Terry - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (4):1293-1325.
    Fix an integer $r \ge 3$. We consider metric spaces on n points such that the distance between any two points lies in $\left\{ {1, \ldots,r} \right\}$. Our main result describes their approximate structure for large n. As a consequence, we show that the number of these metric spaces is $\left\lceil {{{r + 1} \over 2}} \right\rceil ^{\left + o\left}.$Related results in the continuous setting have recently been proved by Kozma, Meyerovitch, Peled, and Samotij [34]. When (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  34
    Given a divisible ordered abelian group Λ, we call (X, d) a Λ-metric space if d: X× X−→ Λ satisfies the usual axioms of a metric, ie, for all x, y∈ X, d (x, y)− d (y, x)≥ 0 if and only if x= y, and the triangle inequality holds. We can now give the definition of asymptotic cone according to van den Dries and Wilkie.Linus Kramer & Katrin Tent - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):175-185.
    §1. Introduction. Asymptotic cones of metric spaces were first invented by Gromov. They are metric spaces which capture the ‘large-scale structure’ of the underlying metric space. Later, van den Dries and Wilkie gave a more general construction of asymptotic cones using ultrapowers. Certain facts about asymptotic cones, like the completeness of the metric space, now follow rather easily from saturation properties of ultrapowers, and in this survey, we want to present two applications of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  24
    Reverse mathematics of mf spaces.Carl Mummert - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (2):203-232.
    This paper gives a formalization of general topology in second-order arithmetic using countably based MF spaces. This formalization is used to study the reverse mathematics of general topology. For each poset P we let MF denote the set of maximal filters on P endowed with the topology generated by {Np | p ∈ P}, where Np = {F ∈ MF | p ∈ F}. We define a countably based MF space to be a space of the form MF for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  8
    Formal continuity implies uniform continuity near compact images on metric spaces.Erik Palmgren - 2014 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 60 (1-2):66-69.
    The localic completion of a metric space induces a canonical notion of continuous map between metric spaces. It is shown that these maps are continuous in the sense of Bishop constructive mathematics, i.e., uniformly continuous near every compact image.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  20
    Iterating Fixed Point via Generalized Mann’s Iteration in Convex b-Metric Spaces with Application.A. Asif, M. Alansari, N. Hussain, M. Arshad & A. Ali - 2021 - Complexity 2021:1-12.
    This manuscript investigates fixed point of single-valued Hardy-Roger’s type F -contraction globally as well as locally in a convex b -metric space. The paper, using generalized Mann’s iteration, iterates fixed point of the abovementioned contraction; however, the third axiom of the F -contraction is removed, and thus the mapping F is relaxed. An important approach used in the article is, though a subset closed ball of a complete convex b -metric space is not necessarily complete, the convergence of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  11
    Strong Completeness of S4 for the Real Line.Philip Kremer - 2021 - In Ivo Düntsch & Edwin Mares (eds.), Alasdair Urquhart on Nonclassical and Algebraic Logic and Complexity of Proofs. Springer Verlag. pp. 291-302.
    In the topological semantics for modal logic, S4 is well known to be complete for the rational line and for the real line: these are special cases of S4’s completeness for any dense-in-itself metric space. The construction used to prove completeness can be slightly amended to show that S4 is not only complete but strongly complete, for the rational line. But no similarly easy amendment is available for the real line. In an earlier paper, we proved a general theorem: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  15
    Encoding Complete Metric Structures by Classical Structures.Nathanael Leedom Ackerman - 2020 - Logica Universalis 14 (4):421-459.
    We show how to encode, by classical structures, both the objects and the morphisms of the category of complete metric spaces and uniformly continuous maps. The result is a category of, what we call, cognate metric spaces and cognate maps. We show this category relativizes to all models of set theory. We extend this encoding to an encoding of complete metric structures by classical structures. This provide us with a general technique for translating results about (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  48
    Paracompactness of Metric Spaces and the Axiom of Multiple Choice.Paul Howard, K. Keremedis & J. E. Rubin - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (2):219-232.
    The axiom of multiple choice implies that metric spaces are paracompact but the reverse implication cannot be proved in set theory without the axiom of choice.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  14
    Domain representability of metric spaces.Jens Blanck - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 83 (3):225-247.
    We show that metric spaces and continuous functions between them are domain representable using the category of Scott-Ershov domains. A notion of effectivity for metric spaces is thereby inherited from effective domain theory. It is shown that a separable metric space with an effective metric can be represented by an effective domain. For a class of spaces, including the Euclidean spaces, the usual notions of effectivity are obtained. The Banach fixed point theorem (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  39
    Modal logics of metric spaces.Guram Bezhanishvili, David Gabelaia & Joel Lucero-Bryan - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (1):178-191.
  22.  18
    Continuous reducibility and dimension of metric spaces.Philipp Schlicht - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (3-4):329-359.
    If is a Polish metric space of dimension 0, then by Wadge’s lemma, no more than two Borel subsets of X are incomparable with respect to continuous reducibility. In contrast, our main result shows that for any metric space of positive dimension, there are uncountably many Borel subsets of that are pairwise incomparable with respect to continuous reducibility. In general, the reducibility that is given by the collection of continuous functions on a topological space \\) is called the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  55
    Relativistic hadronic mechanics: Nonunitary, axiom-preserving completion of relativistic quantum mechanics.Ruggero Maria Santilli - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (5):625-729.
    The most majestic scientific achievement, of this century in mathematical beauty, axiomatic consistency, and experimental verifications has been special relativity with its unitary structure at the operator level, and canonical structure at the classical levels, which has turned out to be exactly valid for point particles moving in the homogenenous and isotropic vacuum (exterior dynamical problems). In recent decades a number of authors have studied nonunitary and noncanonical theories, here generally calleddeformations for the representation of broader conditions, such as extended (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  16
    Categorical semantics of metric spaces and continuous logic.Simon Cho - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (3):1044-1078.
    Using the category of metric spaces as a template, we develop a metric analogue of the categorical semantics of classical/intuitionistic logic, and show that the natural notion of predicate in this “continuous semantics” is equivalent to the a priori separate notion of predicate in continuous logic, a logic which is independently well-studied by model theorists and which finds various applications. We show this equivalence by exhibiting the real interval $[0,1]$ in the category of metric spaces (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  23
    A Metamathematical Condition Equivalent to the Existence of a Complete Left Invariant Metric for a Polish Group.Alex Thompson - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (4):1108 - 1124.
    Strengthening a theorem of Hjorth this paper gives a new characterization of which Polish groups admit compatible complete left invariant metrics. As a corollary it is proved that any Polish group without a complete left invariant metric has a continuous action on a Polish space whose associated orbit equivalence relation is not essentially countable.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  40
    Metric spaces and the axiom of choice.Omar De la Cruz, Eric Hall, Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis & Jean E. Rubin - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (5):455-466.
    We study conditions for a topological space to be metrizable, properties of metrizable spaces, and the role the axiom of choice plays in these matters.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  24
    Metric complements of overt closed sets.Thierry Coquand, Erik Palmgren & Bas Spitters - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (4):373-378.
    We show that the set of points of an overt closed subspace of a metric completion of a Bishop-locally compact metric space is located. Consequently, if the subspace is, moreover, compact, then its collection of points is Bishop-compact. © 2011 WILEY-VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  25
    Real-valued models with metric equality and uniformly continuous predicates.Michael Katz - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):772-792.
    Two real-valued deduction schemes are introduced, which agree on $\vdash \triangle$ but not on $\Gamma \vdash \triangle$ , where Δ and ▵ are finite sets of formulae. Using the first scheme we axiomatize real-valued equality so that it induces metrics on the domains of appropriate structures. We use the second scheme to reduce substitutivity of equals to uniform continuity, with respect to the metric equality, of interpretations of predicates in structures. This continuity extends from predicates to arbitrary formulae and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  29
    The constructive completion of the space?Satoru Yoshida - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (1):77-82.
    We prove in the framework of Bishop's constructive mathematics that the sequential completion equation image of the space [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT CAPITAL D] is filter-complete. Then it follows as a corollary that the filter-completeness of [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT CAPITAL D] is equivalent to the principle BD-ℕ, which can be proved in classical mathematics, Brouwer's intuitionistic mathematics and constructive recursive mathematics of Markov's school, but does not in Bishop's constructive mathematics. We also show that equation image is identical with the filter-completion (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  21
    On countable choice and sequential spaces.Gonçalo Gutierres - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (2):145-152.
    Under the axiom of choice, every first countable space is a Fréchet-Urysohn space. Although, in its absence even ℝ may fail to be a sequential space.Our goal in this paper is to discuss under which set-theoretic conditions some topological classes, such as the first countable spaces, the metric spaces, or the subspaces of ℝ, are classes of Fréchet-Urysohn or sequential spaces.In this context, it is seen that there are metric spaces which are not sequential (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  37
    Compact Metric Spaces and Weak Forms of the Axiom of Choice.E. Tachtsis & K. Keremedis - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):117-128.
    It is shown that for compact metric spaces the following statements are pairwise equivalent: “X is Loeb”, “X is separable”, “X has a we ordered dense subset”, “X is second countable”, and “X has a dense set G = ∪{Gn : n ∈ ω}, ∣Gn∣ < ω, with limn→∞ diam = 0”. Further, it is shown that the statement: “Compact metric spaces are weakly Loeb” is not provable in ZF0 , the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. The completeness of Kant’s metaphysical exposition of space.Henny Blomme - 2012 - Kant Studien 103 (2):139-162.
    : In the first edition of his book on the completeness of Kant’s table of judgments, Klaus Reich shortly indicates that the B-version of the metaphysical exposition of space in the Critique of pure reason is structured following the inverse order of the table of categories. In this paper, I develop Reich’s claim and provide further evidence for it. My argumentation is as follows: Through analysis of our actually given representation of space as some kind of object, the metaphysical exposition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  62
    From Acoustic Analog of Space, Cancer Therapy, to Acoustic Sachs-Wolfe Theorem: A Model of the Universe as a Guitar.Victor Christianto, Florentin Smarandache & Yunita Umniyati - manuscript
    It has been known for long time that the cosmic sound wave was there since the early epoch of the Universe. Signatures of its existence are abound. However, such an acoustic model of cosmology is rarely developed fully into a complete framework from the notion of space, cancer therapy up to the sky. This paper may be the first attempt towards such a complete description of the Universe based on classical wave equation of sound. It is argued that one can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  8
    Finitary sequence spaces.Mark Mandelkern - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):416-430.
    This paper studies the metric structure of the space Hr of absolutely summable sequences of real numbers with at most r nonzero terms. Hr is complete, and is located and nowhere dense in the space of all absolutely summable sequences. Totally bounded and compact subspaces of Hr are characterized, and large classes of located, totally bounded, compact, and locally compact subspaces are constructed. The methods used are constructive in the strict sense. MSC: 03F65, 54E50.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  17
    Strong completeness of provability logic for ordinal spaces.Juan P. Aguilera & David Fernández-Duque - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (2):608-628.
  36.  33
    Completeness of public announcement logic in topological spaces.C. A. N. Baskent - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):142.
  37. Developing a Metric of Usable Space for Zoo Exhibits.Heather Browning & Terry L. Maple - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:791.
    The size of animal exhibits has important effects on their lives and welfare. However, most references to exhibit size only consider floor space and height dimensions, without considering the space afforded by usable features within the exhibit. In this paper, we develop two possible methods for measuring the usable space of zoo exhibits and apply these to a sample exhibit. Having a metric for usable space in place will provide a better reflection of the quality of different exhibits, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  50
    Metric Boolean algebras and constructive measure theory.Thierry Coquand & Erik Palmgren - 2002 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 41 (7):687-704.
    This work concerns constructive aspects of measure theory. By considering metric completions of Boolean algebras – an approach first suggested by Kolmogorov – one can give a very simple construction of e.g. the Lebesgue measure on the unit interval. The integration spaces of Bishop and Cheng turn out to give examples of such Boolean algebras. We analyse next the notion of Borel subsets. We show that the algebra of such subsets can be characterised in a pointfree and constructive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  14
    Complements of Intersections in Constructive Mathematics.Douglas S. Bridges & Hajime Ishihara - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (1):35-43.
    We examine, from a constructive perspective, the relation between the complements of S, T, and S ∩ T in X, where X is either a metric space or a normed linear space. The fundamental question addressed is: If x is distinct from each element of S ∩ T, if s ϵ S, and if t ϵ T, is x distinct from s or from t? Although the classical answer to this question is trivially affirmative, constructive answers involve Markov's principle (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  33
    On polish groups admitting a compatible complete left-invariant metric.Maciej Malicki - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):437 - 447.
    We prove that the set of all Polish groups admitting a compatible complete left-invariant metric (called CLI) is coanalytic non-Borel as a subset of a standard Borel space of all Polish groups. As an application of this result, we show that there does not exist a weakly universal CLI group. This, in particular, answers in the negative a question of H.Becker.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. A constructive look at the completeness of the space $\mathcal{d} (\mathbb{r})$.Hajime Ishihara & Satoru Yoshida - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1511-1519.
    We show, within the framework of Bishop's constructive mathematics, that (sequential) completeness of the locally convex space $\mathcal{D} (\mathbb{R})$ of test functions is equivalent to the principle BD-N which holds in classical mathemtatics, Brouwer's intuitionism and Markov's constructive recursive mathematics, but does not hold in Bishop's constructivism.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  64
    A constructive look at the completeness of the space (ℝ).Hajime Ishihara & Satoru Yoshida - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (4):1511-1519.
    We show, within the framework of Bishop's constructive mathematics, that (sequential) completeness of the locally convex space $\mathcal{D} (\mathbb{R})$ of test functions is equivalent to the principle BD-N which holds in classical mathemtatics, Brouwer's intuitionism and Markov's constructive recursive mathematics, but does not hold in Bishop's constructivism.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  43.  40
    Completeness of Certain Bimodal Logics for Subset Spaces.M. Angela Weiss & Rohit Parikh - 2002 - Studia Logica 71 (1):1-30.
    Subset Spaces were introduced by L. Moss and R. Parikh in [8]. These spaces model the reasoning about knowledge of changing states.In [2] a kind of subset space called intersection space was considered and the question about the existence of a set of axioms that is complete for the logic of intersection spaces was addressed. In [9] the first author introduced the class of directed spaces and proved that any set of axioms for directed frames also (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44.  6
    On the intermediate logic of open subsets of metric spaces.Timofei Shatrov - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 305-313.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  51
    Topometric spaces and perturbations of metric structures.Itaï Ben Yaacov - 2008 - Logic and Analysis 1 (3-4):235-272.
    We develop the general theory of topometric spaces, i.e., topological spaces equipped with a well-behaved lower semi-continuous metric. Spaces of global and local types in continuous logic are the motivating examples for the study of such spaces. In particular, we develop Cantor-Bendixson analysis of topometric spaces, which can serve as a basis for the study of local stability (extending the ad hoc development in Ben Yaacov I and Usvyatsov A, Continuous first order logic and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46.  60
    On constructing completions.Laura Crosilla, Hajime Ishihara & Peter Schuster - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):969-978.
    The Dedekind cuts in an ordered set form a set in the sense of constructive Zermelo—Fraenkel set theory. We deduce this statement from the principle of refinement, which we distill before from the axiom of fullness. Together with exponentiation, refinement is equivalent to fullness. None of the defining properties of an ordering is needed, and only refinement for two—element coverings is used. In particular, the Dedekind reals form a set; whence we have also refined an earlier result by Aczel and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  67
    A proof of completeness for continuous first-order logic.Itaï Ben Yaacov & Arthur Paul Pedersen - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1):168-190.
    -/- Continuous first-order logic has found interest among model theorists who wish to extend the classical analysis of “algebraic” structures (such as fields, group, and graphs) to various natural classes of complete metric structures (such as probability algebras, Hilbert spaces, and Banach spaces). With research in continuous first-order logic preoccupied with studying the model theory of this framework, we find a natural question calls for attention. Is there an interesting set of axioms yielding a completeness result? -/- (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48.  38
    A Logic for Metric and Topology.Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):795 - 828.
    We propose a logic for reasoning about metric spaces with the induced topologies. It combines the 'qualitative' interior and closure operators with 'quantitative' operators 'somewhere in the sphere of radius r.' including or excluding the boundary. We supply the logic with both the intended metric space semantics and a natural relational semantics, and show that the latter (i) provides finite partial representations of (in general) infinite metric models and (ii) reduces the standard '∈-definitions' of closure and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  15
    A logic for metric and topology.Frank Wolter & Michael Zakharyaschev - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):795-828.
    We propose a logic for reasoning about metric spaces with the induced topologies. It combines the ‘qualitative’ interior and closure operators with ‘quantitative’ operators ‘somewhere in the sphere of radiusr’ including or excluding the boundary. We supply the logic with both the intended metric space semantics and a natural relational semantics, and show that the latter (i) provides finite partial representations of (in general) infinite metric models and (ii) reduces the standard ‘ε-definitions’ of closure and interior (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  14
    On Lindelof Metric Spaces and Weak Forms of the Axiom of Choice.Kyriakos Keremedis & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (1):35-44.
    We show that the countable axiom of choice CAC strictly implies the statements “Lindelöf metric spaces are second countable” “Lindelöf metric spaces are separable”. We also show that CAC is equivalent to the statement: “If is a Lindelöf topological space with respect to the base ℬ, then is Lindelöf”.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000