Results for 'Larry Christenson'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  7
    A Response to the Mickelsens.Nordis Christenson & Larry Christenson - 1988 - Transformation: An International Journal of Holistic Mission Studies 5 (3):13-14.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  7
    What One Charismatic Would Like to Say to Some Evangelical Social Activists.Larry Christenson - 1988 - Transformation: An International Journal of Holistic Mission Studies 5 (4):19-19.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  9
    Rethinking the Good: Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning.Larry S. Temkin - 2011 - , US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In choosing between moral alternatives -- choosing between various forms of ethical action -- we typically make calculations of the following kind: A is better than B; B is better than C; therefore A is better than C. These inferences use the principle of transitivity and are fundamental to many forms of practical and theoretical theorizing, not just in moral and ethical theory but in economics. Indeed they are so common as to be almost invisible. What Larry Temkin's book (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  4.  28
    Demystifying Legal Reasoning.Larry Alexander & Emily Sherwin (eds.) - 2008 - Cambridge University Press.
    Demystifying Legal Reasoning defends the proposition that there are no special forms of reasoning peculiar to law. Legal decision makers engage in the same modes of reasoning that all actors use in deciding what to do: open-ended moral reasoning, empirical reasoning, and deduction from authoritative rules. This book addresses common law reasoning when prior judicial decisions determine the law, and interpretation of texts. In both areas, the popular view that legal decision makers practise special forms of reasoning is false.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  5. Consent Does Not Require Communication: A Reply to Dougherty.Larry Alexander, Heidi Hurd & Peter Westen - 2016 - Law and Philosophy 35 (6):655-660.
  6.  20
    In Defense of the Standard Picture: The Basic Challenge.Larry Alexander - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (3):187-206.
    In this article I defend what Mark Greenberg has labeled the standard picture of law against the attack on it by Greenberg and Scott Hershovitz. I point out that law on the standard picture’s conception of it has moral virtues that Greenberg's own moral impact theory and Hershovitz’s similar theory lack. Moreover, it avoids a vicious circularity that bedevils Greenberg’s theory.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  62
    Can Self-Defense Justify Punishment?Larry Alexander - 2013 - Law and Philosophy 32 (2-3):159-175.
    This piece is a review essay on Victor Tadros’s The Ends of Harm. Tadros rejects retributive desert but believes punishment can be justified instrumentally without succumbing to the problems of thoroughgoing consequentialism and endorsing using people as means. He believes he can achieve these results through extension of the right of self-defense. I argue that Tadros fails in this endeavor: he has a defective account of the means principle; his rejection of desert leads to gross mismatches of punishment and culpability; (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8.  14
    Is There a Right of Freedom of Expression?Larry Alexander - 2005 - Cambridge University Press.
    In this provocative book, Alexander offers a sceptical appraisal of the claim that freedom of expression is a human right. He examines the various contexts in which a right to freedom of expression might be asserted and concludes that such a right cannot be supported in any of these contexts. He argues that some legal protection of freedom of expression is surely valuable, though the form such protection will take will vary with historical and cultural circumstances and is not a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  36
    Law and Exclusionary Reasons.Larry Alexander - 1990 - Philosophical Topics 18 (1):5-22.
  10.  97
    Pursuing the good-indirectly.Larry Alexander - 1985 - Ethics 95 (2):315-332.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11. Scalar properties, binary judgments.Larry Alexander - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (2):85–104.
    In the moral realm, our deontic judgments are usually (always?) binary. An act (or omission) is either morally forbidden or morally permissible. 1 Yet the determination of an act's deontic status frequently turns on the existence of properties that are matters of degree. In what follows I shall give several examples of binary moral judgments that turn on scalar properties, and I shall claim that these examples should puzzle us. How can the existence of a property to a specific degree (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  97
    Reconsidering the Relationship among Voluntary Acts, Strict Liability, and Negligence in Criminal Law.Larry Alexander - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):84.
    This essay, as will become obvious, owes a huge debt to Mark Kelman, particularly to his article “Interpretative Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law.” That debt is one of both concept and content. There is rich irony in my aping Kelman's deconstructionist enterprise, for I do not share his enthusiasm for either the “insights” or the political agenda of the Critical Legal Studies movement. I do not believe that either the law in general or the criminal law in particular is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13. What is freedom of association, and what is its denial?Larry Alexander - 2008 - Social Philosophy and Policy 25 (2):1-21.
    Freedom of association, as I understand it, refers to the liberty a person possesses to enter into relationships with others—for any and all purposes, for a momentary or long-term duration, by contract, consent, or acquiescence. It likewise refers to the liberty to refuse to enter into such relationships or to terminate them when not otherwise compelled by one's voluntary assumption of an obligation to maintain the relationship. Freedom of association thus is a quite capacious liberty.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14. Consent, punishment, and proportionality.Larry Alexander - 1986 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (2):178-182.
  15.  70
    Is There a Case for Strict Liability?Larry Alexander - 2018 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 12 (3):531-538.
    In this short paper, I shall answer the title’s question first in the context of criminal law and then in the context of tort law. In that latter section, I shall also mention in passing contractual and other forms of civil liability that are strict, although they will not be my principal focus. My conclusions will be that strict liability is never proper as the basis for retributive punishment; that it is a very crude device for achieving deterrence through nonretributive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  24
    Proportionality’s Function.Larry Alexander - 2021 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3):361-372.
    In this paper I argue that punishment should be proportional to desert; that desert turns solely on culpability and not on results: that culpability is a function of what the actor perceives are the risks of his act to others’ interests and the reasons he perceives that might justify, excuse, or aggravate taking those risks; that because culpability is a complex function, ordinally ranking acts in terms of culpability is quite difficult; that converting the ordinal ranking into cardinal measures of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  11
    International Criminal Tribunals: A Normative Defense.Larry May & Shannon Fyfe - 2017 - Cambridge University Press.
    In the last two decades there has been a meteoric rise of international criminal tribunals and courts and also a strengthening chorus of critics against them. Today it is hard to find strong defenders of international criminal tribunals and courts. This book attempts such a defense against an array of critics. It offers a nuanced defense, accepting many criticisms but arguing that the idea of international criminal tribunals can be defended as providing the fairest way to deal with mass atrocity (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Liberalism, neutrality, and equality of welfare vs. equality of resources.Larry Alexander & Maimon Schwarzschild - 1987 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1):85-110.
  19.  15
    Are Procedural Rights Derivative Substantive Rights?Larry Alexander - 1998 - Law and Philosophy 17 (1):19-42.
  20.  13
    Revisitando el Oficio de Sociólogo: Notas sobre el Habitus de Investigador Social.Larry Andrade - 2010 - Cinta de Moebio 39:153-169.
    En este artículo se revisa el impacto que la formación en investigación tiene sobre los modos en que las decisiones metodológicas son asumidas y, más aún, sobre la propia concepción de metodología con la que se piensa y ejecuta una investigación en ciencias sociales. Precisamente, es desde el interior de este campo y desde la mirada sociológica, que se formulan algunas reflexiones en torno al propio habitus de investigador social, valiéndonos para ello de los aportes de Pierre Bourdieu.This article analyses (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  66
    Fair Equality of Opportunity.Larry A. Alexander - 1985 - Philosophy Research Archives 11:197-208.
    Although discussions of John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice generally refer to Rawls’ two principles of justice, and although Rawls himself labels his principles “the two principles of justice”, Rawls actually sets forth three distinct principles in the following lexical order: the liberty principle, the fair equality of opportunity principle, and the difference principle. Rawls argues at some length for the priority of the liberty principle over the other two. On the other hand, Rawls offers hardly any argument at all (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22. Self-defense, punishment, and proportionality.Larry Alexander - 1991 - Law and Philosophy 10 (3):323 - 328.
  23. Culpability.Larry Alexander - 2011 - In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  11
    Plastic trees and gladiators: Liberalism and aesthetic regulation: Plastic trees and gladiators.Larry Alexander - 2010 - Legal Theory 16 (2):77-90.
    The hallmark of modern liberalism is its embrace of the Millian harm principle and its antipathy to legal moralism. In this article I consider whether aesthetic regulations can be justified under the harm principle as that principle has been elaborated by Joel Feinberg. I conclude that aesthetic and other regulations that most liberals regard as unproblematic are actually instances of legal moralism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  27
    Recklessness, Agent-Relative Prerogatives, and Latent Obligations: Does Belief-Relativity Trump Fact-Relativity with Respect to Our Rights?Larry Alexander - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (5):2639-2655.
    Are our rights—to our bodily integrity, to our possessions, to the goods and services promised us, and so on—matters of fact, or are our rights functions of others’ beliefs about how their acts will affect our rights? The conventional view states that subjective oughts—based on what we believe—determine culpability, whereas objective oughts—based on the facts—determine permissibility. After all, the idea that our beliefs about how our acts would affect others’ rights might affect the contours of those rights themselves appears deeply (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  50
    Facts, Law, Exculpation, and Inculpation: Comments on Simons.Larry Alexander - 2009 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 3 (3):241-245.
    Orthodox criminal law doctrine treats mistakes of law and mistakes of fact differently for purposes of both exculpation and inculpation. Kenneth Simons’ paper in general defends this orthodoxy. I have earlier criticized the criminal law’s attempt to distinguish mistakes of law from mistakes of fact, and I continue to maintain, in opposition to Simons, that the distinction is problematic.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  13
    Reckless Beliefs.Larry Alexander & Kevin Cole - 2019 - In Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law. Springer Verlag. pp. 651-657.
    Existing and proposed provisions of the Model Penal Code refer to believing something “recklessly.” In this chapter, we examine the notion of reckless beliefs and determine what that notion cannot be and what it might be.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  91
    Affirmative duties and the limits of self-sacrifice.Larry Alexander - 1996 - Law and Philosophy 15 (1):65 - 74.
    American criminal law reflects the absence of any general duty of Good Samaritanism. Nonetheless, there are some circumstances in which it imposes affirmative duties to aid others. In those circumstances, however, the duty to aid is canceled whenever aiding subjects the actor to a certain level of risk or sacrifice, a level that can be less than the risk or sacrifice faced by the beneficiary if not aided. In this article, I demonstrate that this approach to limiting affirmative duties to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  25
    Scheffler on the Independence of Agent-Centered Preogatives from Agent-Centered Restrictions.Larry A. Alexander - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (5):277.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. The Seven Deadly Sins of Corporate Doubletalk'.Larry D. Alexander - 1984 - Business and Society Review 48:41-45.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  78
    Response to Critics.Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan - 2010 - Law and Philosophy 29 (4):483-504.
  32.  25
    Slow walking on a treadmill desk does not negatively affect executive abilities: an examination of cognitive control, conflict adaptation, response inhibition, and post-error slowing.Michael J. Larson, James D. LeCheminant, Kaylie Carbine, Kyle R. Hill, Edward Christenson, Travis Masterson & Rick LeCheminant - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  21
    In Defense of the Standard Picture: Overcoming Death by a Thousand Cuts.Larry Alexander - 2023 - Ratio Juris 36 (3):199-213.
    In a previous article, I defended the standard picture of law (or SP), so labeled by its foremost critic, Mark Greenberg. In that article, I addressed Greenberg's root-and-branch critique of the SP and, to a much lesser extent, a related critique by Scott Hershovitz. But the Greenberg and Hershovitz frontal attacks on the SP are not its only threats. Some theorists, while not attacking the SP directly, give accounts of law that the SP cannot accommodate. Those theorists will be challenged (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Recipe for a Theory of Self-Defense.Larry Alexander - 2016 - In Christian Coons & Michael Weber (eds.), The Ethics of Self-Defense. New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    Self-defense and other-defense are uses of force against another person—an attacker—for the purpose of preventing the attacker from harming a victim. When such force is exercised by the victim, it is self-defense; when by a third party, other-defense. Self-defense and other-defense are preemptive uses of force because they occur before the acts they are intended to prevent occur. Thus, they operate in the realm of epistemic uncertainty. Victims and third parties can never be certain the feared acts will occur. They (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. Refereeing in 1996.Avishalom Adam, Brian Baigrie, Alf Bång, H. I. Brown, K. O. L. Burridge, Ferrell Christenson, Richard Collins, Wesley Cragg, Jane Duran & Fred Eidlin - 1999 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 29 (1):160-161.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  39
    Received by 1 November 1985.Daniel M. Hausman, Michael S. McPherson, James Luther Adams, Wilhelm Pauck, Roger-Lincoln Shinn, Julia Annas, Jonathan Barnes, Richard J. Bernstein, Paul Canick & Ronald Christenson - 1986 - Teaching Philosophy 9 (1).
  37. The Philosophy of Criminal Law.Larry Alexander - 2002 - In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  20
    Freedom of Religion and Expression.Larry Alexander - 2016 - In Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee & David Coady (eds.), A Companion to Applied Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley. pp. 424–438.
    In this chapter I analyze two fundamental hallmarks of liberalism—freedom of religion and freedom of expression. No society can rightly be called “liberal” if it does not endorse those freedoms. Yet, what are those freedoms, and are they realizable? I conclude that neither freedom can be given a principled elaboration. The approach to them must be pragmatic and reflect a contingent modus vivendi rather than an accommodation demanded by principle.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  27
    A Reply to Our Critics.Larry Alexander & Kimberly Kessler Ferzan - 2022 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (3):485-502.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  49
    Other People’s Errors.Larry Alexander - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (5):1049-1059.
    The question of when other people’s bad acts belong on our moral ledger arises in a number of different scenarios. Each scenario has received some philosophical attention, but no one has noted the structural similarities of these various scenarios or the implications of a proposed approach to one for how the others should be approached. That is the ambition of this article. In it, seemingly disparate moral phenomena—blunt rules, preemptive restrictions, moral blackmail, complicity, retreat and proportional response, and the duty (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Hart and Punishment for Negligence.Larry Alexander - 2014 - In C. G. Pulman (ed.), Hart on Responsibility. New York, NY: Palgrave-Macmillan.
  42.  11
    The Legal Enforcement of Morality.Larry Alexander - 2003 - In R. G. Frey & Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.), A Companion to Applied Ethics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 128–141.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  11
    Morality, Just Post Bellum and International Law.Larry May & Andrew Forcehimes (eds.) - 2012 - Cambridge University Press.
    This collection of essays brings together some of the leading legal, political and moral theorists to discuss the normative issues that arise when war concludes and when a society strives to regain peace. In the transition from war, mass atrocity or a repressive regime, how should we regard the idea of democracy and human rights? Should regimes be toppled unless they are democratic or is it sufficient that these regimes are less repressive than before? Are there moral reasons for thinking (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  4
    ha-Tsayar hu meragel =.Larry Abramson - 2018 - Bene Beraḳ: ha-Ḳibuts ha-meʼuḥad. Edited by Gannit Ankori.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  10
    Why American Philosophy? Why Now?Larry A. Hickman - 2009 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 1 (1).
    This title presents not two, but three questions. The third question, the one that lies behind and is obscured by the two more obvious ones, concerns the nature of American philosophy. What qualifies as “American” philosophy? Is it, as some have suggested, philosophy as it is practiced in any of the Americas – North, Central, or South? Or is it perhaps philosophy as it is pursued by practitioners living in North America, or even in a more restricted sense, by practitioners (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  76
    Arthur Ripstein, equality, responsibility, and the law.Larry Alexander - 2001 - Law and Philosophy 20 (6):617-635.
  47.  22
    Brettschneider and ‘democratic persuasion’.Larry Alexander - 2017 - Jurisprudence 8 (2):370-379.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  20
    Book ReviewsL. W. Sumner, The Hateful and the Obscene.Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2004. Pp. xi+275. $60.00.Larry Alexander - 2006 - Ethics 116 (4):809-813.
  49.  4
    Constitutionalism.Larry A. Alexander - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 248–258.
    This chapter contains section titled: What Constitutions Are What Constitutions Do Are Constitutions Desirable? References.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  14
    Culpably Creating the Conditions of Justified Acts: Another Look.Larry Alexander - 2020 - Philosophia 49 (1):107-112.
    In this short article I examine whether and how one’s minor culpability in giving rise to an instance of otherwise justified defense affects the defense and affects the act giving rise to it.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000