Results for 'Chemical Atomism'

1000+ found
Order:
See also
  1.  76
    Chemical atomism: a case study in confirmation and ontology.Joshua D. K. Brown - 2015 - Synthese 192 (2):453-485.
    Quine, taking the molecular constitution of matter as a paradigmatic example, offers an account of the relation between theory confirmation and ontology. Elsewhere, he deploys a similar ontological methodology to argue for the existence of mathematical objects. Penelope Maddy considers the atomic/molecular theory in more historical detail. She argues that the actual ontological practices of science display a positivistic demand for “direct observation,” and that fulfillment of this demand allows us to distinguish molecules and other physical objects from mathematical abstracta. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  61
    Resisting Chemical Atomism: Duhem’s Argument.Paul Needham - 2008 - Philosophy of Science 75 (5):921-931.
    Late nineteenth‐century opponents of atomism questioned whether the evidence required any notion of an atom. In this spirit, Duhem developed an account of the import of chemical formulas that is clearly neutral on the atomic question rather than antiatomistic. The argument is supplemented with specific inadequacies of atomic theories of chemical combination and considerably strengthened by the theory of chemical combination provided by thermodynamics. Despite possible counterevidence available at the time, which should have tempered some of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  12
    Chemical atomism at the seventeenth century, its development in the molecular atomism of Gassendi, and its influence in the young Leibniz.Manuel Higueras - 2013 - Cultura:255-270.
    El objetivo del presente escrito es presentar los principales rasgos del atomismo quí­mico que se desarrolla a principios del siglo XVII, ver cómo se desarrolla en el atomismo de Gassendi y la influencia que tienen en la filosofía del joven Leibniz. Tanto la influencia de la corriente alquímica e iatroquímica en este tipo de atomismo, como la separación de algu­nos postulados fundamentales del mecanicismo, tienen una clara influencia en los primeros escritos de Leibniz.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  12
    Chemical Atomism in the Nineteenth Century by Alan J. Rocke. [REVIEW]David Knight - 1985 - Isis 76:129-130.
  5.  9
    The Reception of Chemical Atomism in Germany.Alan J. Rocke - 1979 - Isis 70 (4):519-536.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  78
    Alan J. Rocke, Chemical Atomism in the Nineteenth Century: From Dalton to Cannizzaro. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1984. Pp. xviii + 386. ISBN 0-8142-0360-4. $27.50. [REVIEW]W. H. Brock - 1985 - British Journal for the History of Science 18 (3):345-347.
  7. Atomists, Antiatomists, and the Change of a Chemical Concept. [REVIEW]Klaus Ruthenberg - 2000 - Hyle 6:187-188.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  28
    Atomism and 'subtlety' in Francis Bacon's philosophy.Graham Rees - 1980 - Annals of Science 37 (5):549-571.
    Francis Bacon's reflections on atomism have generally been misunderstood because they have never been systematically studied in relation to the speculative chemical philosophy which he developed in the interval between about 1592 and his death in 1626. This philosophy, in many respects unknown to historians until quite recently, was the only body of positive science which Bacon ever accepted. The speculative philosophy was, on the whole, chemical and non-mechanical, and consequently not consistent with atomist doctrines. In fact, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  10
    Pioneering Ideas for the Physical and Chemical Sciences: Josef Loschmidt's Contributions and Modern Developments in Structural Organic Chemistry, Atomistics, and Statistical Mechanics. W. Fleischhacker, T. Schönfeld. [REVIEW]Carlo Cercignani - 2001 - Isis 92 (2):405-406.
  10.  57
    Has Daltonian atomism provided chemistry with any explanations?Paul Needham - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):1038-1047.
    Philosophers frequently cite Dalton's chemical atomism, and its nineteenth century developments, as a prime example of inference to the best explanation. This was a controversial issue in its time. But the critics are dismissed as positivist‐inspired antirealists with no interest in explanation. Is this a reasonable assessment?
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  11. Classical Atomism in Chemistry: Not a Success Story.Paul Needham - 2020 - In Ugo Zilioli (ed.), Atomism in Philosophy: A History from Antiquity to the Present. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 457-469.
    Classical atoms—“part-less, ontologically irreducible simples” as the conference flyer puts it—are not the atoms of modern chemistry and analogies with the latter can be construed in various ways. They have figured in the historical development of concepts of chemical affinity but without, as Alan Chalmers and I have independently argued, making any significant contribution to empirically justified theories. A purely combinatorial conception of the formation of compounds by juxtaposing atoms is associated with Daltonian atomism. I review the merits (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  49
    Dalton’s Chemical Atoms versus Duhem’s Chemical Equivalents.Karen R. Zwier - 2011 - Philosophy of Science 78 (5):842-853.
    Paul Needham has claimed in several recent papers that Dalton’s chemical atomism was not explanatory. I respond to his criticism of Dalton by arguing that explanation admits of degrees and that under a view that allows for a spectrum of explanatory value, it is possible to see ample worth in Dalton’s atomistic explanations. Furthermore, I argue that even Duhem, who rejected atomism, acknowledged the explanatory worth of Dalton’s atomism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  16
    Berthelot's anti-atomism: A 'matter of taste'?Mary Jo Nye - 1981 - Annals of Science 38 (5):585-590.
    The influential French chemist Marcelin Berthelot spoke against the use of Dalton's atomic theory and Avogadro's hypothesis in the second half of the nineteenth century. This paper argues that Berthelot conceded that atomism might be acceptable as a system of conventions, but he feared the power of such conventions in constructing a realistic picture of atoms which was not warranted empirically. Equally, Berthelot's anti-atomism was a last-ditch effort to assert the place of chemistry within the tradition of natural (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Mendeleev’s Periodic Law and the 19th Century Debates on Atomism.Pieter Thyssen - forthcoming - In Martin Eisvogel & Klaus Ruthenberg (eds.), Wald, Positivism and Chemistry.
    The heated debates and severe conflicts between the atomists and the anti-atomists of the latter half of the nineteenth century are well known to the historian of science. The position of Dmitrii Ivanovich Mendeleev towards these nineteenth century debates on atomism will be studied in this paper. A first attempt will thus be offered to reconcile Mendeleev’s seemingly contradictory comments and ambiguous standpoints into one coherent view.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  59
    Atomic notation and atomistic hypotheses translated by Paul Needham.Paul Needham - 2000 - Foundations of Chemistry 2 (2):127-180.
    This article was first published as “Notation atomique et hypothèses atomistiques”, Revue des questions scientifiques, 31 (1892), 391– 457. It is the second of a series of articles Duhem was to publish in the Catholic journal Revue des questions scientifiques, in which he presents his understanding of what can justifiably be said about the structure of chemical substances as captured by chemical formulas. The argument unfolds following a broadly historical development of events throughout the course of the century (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  87
    Causal concepts in chemical vernaculars.Rom Harré - 2010 - Foundations of Chemistry 12 (2):101-115.
    Though causality seems to have a natural place in chemical thought, the analysis of the underlying causal concepts requires attention to two different research styles. In Part One I attempt a classification and critical analysis of several philosophical accounts of causal concepts which appear to be very diverse. I summarize this diversity which ranges from causality as displayed in regular concomitances of types of events to causality as the activity of agents. Part Two is concerned with the analysis of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element.F. A. Paneth - 1962 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 13 (50):144-160.
    This article is a translation into english of a lecture given by paneth in 1931. The content of the work is described by the section titles: (1) the need for epistemological clarification of the fundamental concepts of chemistry, (2) the concept of substance in chemistry, (3) the epistemological standpoint of the ancient atomists, (4) the epistemological position of the concept of element introduced by lavoisier, (5) the double meaning of the chemical concept of element: 'basic substance' and 'simple substance', (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  18. The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element (I).F. A. Paneth - 1962 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 13 (49):1-14.
    This article is a translation into english of a lecture given by paneth in 1931. The content of the work is described by the section titles: (1) the need for epistemological clarification of the fundamental concepts of chemistry, (2) the concept of substance in chemistry, (3) the epistemological standpoint of the ancient atomists, (4) the epistemological position of the concept of element introduced by lavoisier, (5) the double meaning of the chemical concept of element: 'basic substance' and 'simple substance', (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  19. The epistemological status of the chemical concept of element.F. A. Paneth - 2003 - Foundations of Chemistry 5 (2):113-145.
    This article is a translation into english of a lecture given by paneth in 1931. The content of the work is described by the section titles: (1) the need for epistemological clarification of the fundamental concepts of chemistry, (2) the concept of substance in chemistry, (3) the epistemological standpoint of the ancient atomists, (4) the epistemological position of the concept of element introduced by lavoisier, (5) the double meaning of the chemical concept of element: 'basic substance' and 'simple substance', (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  20.  29
    Nineteenth-century chemical theory: correction of a misunderstanding.Paul Needham - 2013 - Foundations of Chemistry 16 (2):165-167.
    I reply in this short note to some criticisms that Alan Rocke has recently made in this journal.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21. Recommended questions on the road towards a scientific explanation of the periodic system of chemical elements with the help of the concepts of quantum physics.W. H. Eugen Schwarz - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 9 (2):139-188.
    Periodic tables (PTs) are the ‘ultimate paper tools’ of general and inorganic chemistry. There are three fields of open questions concerning the relation between PTs and physics: (i) the relation between the chemical facts and the concept of a periodic system (PS) of chemical elements (CEs) as represented by PTs; (ii) the internal structure of the PS; (iii)␣The relation between the PS and atomistic quantum chemistry. The main open questions refer to (i). The fuzziness of the concepts of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  35
    Alexander W. Williamson on the atomic theory: A study of nineteenth-century British atomism.E. Robert Paul - 1978 - Annals of Science 35 (1):17-31.
    Although not universally accepted at the time, the atomic hypothesis during the 19th century provided a definite ordering scheme for certain relatively sophisticated chemical phenomena. As such, it was conceptually responsible for the formulation and precise articulation of important seminal ideas in chemical studies. In this paper we will explore this claim with regard to the views of the British chemist Alexander W. Williamson.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  70
    What did “theory” mean to nineteenth-century chemists?Alan Rocke - 2013 - Foundations of Chemistry 15 (2):145-156.
    Some recent philosophers of science have argued that chemistry in the nineteenth century “largely lacked theoretical foundations, and showed little progress in supplying such foundations” until around 1900, or even later. In particular, nineteenth-century atomic theory, it is said, “played no useful part” in the crowning achievement of nineteenth-century chemistry, the powerful subdiscipline of organic chemistry. This paper offers a contrary view. The idea that chemistry only gained useful theoretical foundations when it began to merge with physics, it will be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  57
    John Dalton’s puzzles: from meteorology to chemistry.Karen R. Zwier - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):58-66.
    Historical research on John Dalton has been dominated by an attempt to reconstruct the origins of his so-called "chemical atomic theory". I show that Dalton's theory is difficult to define in any concise manner, and that there has been no consensus as to its unique content among his contemporaries, later chemists, and modern historians. I propose an approach which, instead of attempting to work backward from Dalton's theory, works forward, by identifying the research questions that Dalton posed to himself (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Chemistry without Atoms.Klaus Ruthenberg & Pieter Thyssen (eds.) - forthcoming - Würzburg: Königshausen and Neumann.
  26.  28
    Response to a letter to the editor.Alan Rocke - 2013 - Foundations of Chemistry 16 (2):169-170.
    Professor Needham tells me that I have misunderstood him, and I am sure he is right that I need to work harder to understand his arguments more fully and more precisely. But he has also misunderstood me, as well—no doubt because I have not expressed myself as carefully as I ought to have done. He writes that I have “clearly” argued that “the only possibility of representing nineteenth-century chemistry as a theoretical pursuit” is based on chemical atomism. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  88
    Gender in the Substance of Chemistry, Part 1: The Ideal Gas.Ágnes Kovács - 2012 - Hyle 18 (2):95 - 120.
    This two-part paper is about the possibility of analyzing the content of chemistry from a gender perspective. The first part provides an example of what such an analysis would look like. The second part is an outline of the theoretical perspective that makes the analysis possible. The example is the model of the ideal gas, the cornerstone of the theory of matter in chemical thermodynamics. I argue that this model is built on fundamental philosophical assumptions (Platonic idealism, hierarchy among (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  75
    When did atoms begin to do any explanatory work in chemistry?Paul Needham - 2004 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18 (2 & 3):199 – 219.
    During the 19th century atomism was a controversial issue in chemistry. It is an oversimplification to dismiss the critics' arguments as all falling under the general positivist view that what can't be seen can't be. The more interesting lines of argument either questioned whether any coherent notion of an atom had ever been formulated or questioned whether atoms were ever really given any explanatory role. At what point, and for what reasons, did atomistic hypotheses begin to explain anything in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  29. The Works of the Honourable Robert Boyle.Robert Boyle - 1999 - Thoemmes Press.
    'almost every branch of modern science can trace phases of its origin in his writings... in the broad field of science Boyle made a greater number and variety of discoveries than one man is ever likely to make again' - John Fulton, Boyle's bibliographer Robert Boyle (1627-91) was one of the most influential scientists and philosophers of the seventeenth century. The founder of modern chemistry, he headed the movement that turned it from an occult science into a subject well-grounded in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  30.  57
    Chemistry in the French tradition of philosophy of science: Duhem, Meyerson, Metzger and Bachelard.Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (4):627-649.
    At first glance twentieth-century philosophy of science seems virtually to ignore chemistry. However this paper argues that a focus on chemistry helped shape the French philosophical reflections about the aims and foundations of scientific methods. Despite patent philosophical disagreements between Duhem, Meyerson, Metzger and Bachelard it is possible to identify the continuity of a tradition that is rooted in their common interest for chemistry. Two distinctive features of the French tradition originated in the attention to what was going on in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  31.  19
    The Chemists' Style of Thinking.Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent - 2009 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 32 (4):365-378.
    Der Denkstil der Chemiker. Der Aufsatz diskutiert die Tragfähigkeit des Begriffes “Denkstil”, wie er von Alistair Crombie eingeführt und Ian Hacking aufgegriffen wurde, für das Verständnis dessen, wie das Fach Chemie historisch seine Identität ausgeprägt hat. Obwohl weder Crombie noch Hacking den Begriff “Denkstil” in Bezug auf einzelne Disziplinen verwendet haben, erscheint im Fall der Chemie seine Anwendung besonders vielversprechend, weil er hier hilft, ein zentrales Problem zu thematisieren – nämlich die Frage, wie es Chemikern trotz wechselnder Gegenstandsbereiche und theoretischer (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32.  24
    Early theoretical chemistry: Plato’s chemistry in Timaeus.Francesco Di Giacomo - 2020 - Foundations of Chemistry 23 (1):17-30.
    The Timaeus is the dialogue that was for many centuries the most influential of Plato’s works. Among its readers we find Descartes, Boyle, Kepler and Heisenberg. In the first division of Timaeus Plato deals with the theory of celestial motion, in the second he presents us with the first mathematical theory of the structure of matter. Here, in a gigantic step forward with respect to the preceding Democritean atomistic theory with its unalterable micro-entities, he introduces the intertransformability of elementary corpuscles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  99
    Philosophy of chemistry.Michael Weisberg, Paul Needham & Robin Hendry - 2011 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Chemistry is the study of the structure and transformation of matter. When Aristotle founded the field in the 4th century BCE, his conceptual grasp of the nature of matter was tailored to accommodate a relatively simple range of observable phenomena. In the 21st century, chemistry has become the largest scientific discipline, producing over half a million publications a year ranging from direct empirical investigations to substantial theoretical work. However, the specialized interest in the conceptual issues arising in chemistry, hereafter Philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34.  49
    Harvey's and Highmore's Accounts of Chick Generation.Karin Ekholm - 2008 - Early Science and Medicine 13 (6):568-614.
    Harvey and Highmore experimented together on chick fetuses at Oxford in the early 1640s, yet in 1651 published significantly different treatises on generation that emphasize their reliance on observations and dissections of fetal chicks at different stages of incubation. The key differences follow from their views on matter and souls. Harvey conceives of living bodies as governed by Aristotelian souls and faculties. Highmore views matter as made of corpuscles and describes organs as involved in chemical procedures. Highmore's treatise is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  16
    Dualistische Entwürfe zur Einheit der Naturphänomene und die Anfänge der Romantischen Naturphilosophie.Alexander Rüger - 1985 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 8 (4):219-232.
    The importance of German Naturphilosophie for the development of a unified view of nature is often emphasized. The search for ultimate unity of natural phenomena, however, was already too common among physicists of the waning 18th century to ascribe its popularity to the influence of philosophers. To avoid the plethora of imponderable fluids, many „atomists”︁ reduced electric, magnetic, thermal, and chemical phenomena to a dualism of contrary principles, thereby prefiguring the „dynamic”︁ ideas of romantic Naturphilosophen.In particular we show how (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  20
    Common empirical foundations, different theoretical choices: The Berthollet-Proust controversy and Dalton’s resolution.Yachun Xu, Yichen Tong & Jiangyang Yuan - 2023 - Foundations of Chemistry 25 (3):439-455.
    Based upon the demarcation between Elementalism and Atomism Chemistry from the perspective of the long-term history of chemistry, the authors re-examine the Berthollet-Proust controversy on the three types of chemical compounds, pointing out that Berthollet proposed the law of indefinite proportions by deduction, while Proust proposed the law of definite proportions by induction. The controversy is beyond the framework of affinity chemistry and entail a synthesis of meta-chemical thinking and experiments. Proust’s discovery of the law of definite (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Atom and aether in nineteenth-century physical science.Alan F. Chalmers - 2008 - Foundations of Chemistry 10 (3):157-166.
    This paper suggests that the cases made for atoms and the aether in nineteenth-century physical science were analogous, with the implication that the case for the atom was less than compelling, since there is no aether. It is argued that atoms did not play a productive role in nineteenth-century chemistry any more than the aether did in physics. Atoms and molecules did eventually find an indispensable home in chemistry but by the time that they did so they were different kinds (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38.  29
    Was ist ganzheitskausalität?A. Mittasch - 1938 - Acta Biotheoretica 4 (1):73-84.
    The article discusses the concept of “holistic” causality which has superseded that of “mechanistic causality”, “mechanism”.In a sequence of events a causal nexus is mentally established, attention being directed either to the initiation, the starting, the incitation of the process or to the conservation of matter and energy in the initiated transformation: initiation causality and conservation causality .As a rule, the two kinds of causality are intimately interlinked, though they often are easily to be distinguished; for instance, catalytic causation and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  12
    Modern Postmodernity and Discursive Power: Part II.Algis Mickūnas - 2023 - Filosofija. Sociologija 34 (1).
    The discussion follows the logic of Western modern metaphysics (mathematical) and ontology (atomistic materialism) in order to demonstrate how scientific discourses assumed a power to construct the environment. A discourse of any discipline is constructed on the basis of its value to be applied on the material, homogeneous environment, to yield desired technical products, including genetic, chemical, electronic, physiological, etc. Thus, each discourse contains the ‘power’ to remake the environment in accordance with its rules. The result is the following: (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  95
    editorial: Substances versus Reactions.Joachim Schummer - 2004 - Hyle 10 (1):3 - 4.
    Is chemistry primarily about things or about processes, about chemical substances or about chemical reactions? Is a chemical reaction defined by the change of certain substances, or are substances defined by their characteristic chemical reactions? What appears to be a play on words to the modern scientist, is actually one of the most fundamental ontological question since antiquity, prompted by the most radical change – the chemical change or the ‘coming-to-be and passing-away’ as Aristotle’s treatise (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. The Promise and Pursuit of Scientific Theories.Laurie Anne Whitt - 1985 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada)
    Recent research in philosophy of science suggests that the relationship which scientists have towards the artifacts of science, i.e. their theories, is considerably richer than many traditional accounts of scientific appraisal would lead us to believe. Problem-solving methodologists, in particular, advocating a pragmatic account of scientific theories, argue that traditional methodologies have tended to focus exclusively on one modality of appraisal--that of theory acceptance, and have advanced normative proposals which provide only for assessments of the empirical well-foundedness of scientific theories. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  30
    Entre atomisme, alchimie et théologie: La réception des thèses d'Antoine de Villon et étienne de Clave contre Aristote, Paracelse et les 'cabalistes'. [REVIEW]Didier Kahn - 2001 - Annals of Science 58 (3):241-286.
    We study here the reception by their contemporaries of Antoine de Villon's and étienne de Clave's anti-Aristotelian, almost materialistic and atomistic theses, which they intended to support publicly in Paris in 1624, using chemical experiments to this purpose. After surveying the intellectual context which could have then nourished an atomism based upon chemical experiments, we go on to show how these theses, far from having been perceived as prominently atomistic, were condemned by the contemporaries above all because (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  7
    Entre atomisme, alchimie et théologie: La réception des thèses d'Antoine de Villon et étienne de Clave contre Aristote, Paracelse et les 'cabalistes' (24-25 août 1624). [REVIEW]Didier Kahn - 2001 - Annals of Science 58 (3):241-286.
    We study here the reception by their contemporaries of Antoine de Villon's and étienne de Clave's anti-Aristotelian, almost materialistic and atomistic theses, which they intended to support publicly in Paris in 1624, using (al)chemical experiments to this purpose. After surveying the intellectual context which could have then nourished an atomism based upon (al)chemical experiments, we go on to show how these theses, far from having been perceived as prominently atomistic, were condemned by the contemporaries above all because (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44. Atomism, Monism, and Causation in the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish.Karen Detlefsen - 2006 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3:199-240.
    Between 1653 and 1655 Margaret Cavendish makes a radical transition in her theory of matter, rejecting her earlier atomism in favour of an infinitely-extended and infinitely-divisible material plenum, with matter being ubiquitously self-moving, sensing, and rational. It is unclear, however, if Cavendish can actually dispense of atomism. One of her arguments against atomism, for example, depends upon the created world being harmonious and orderly, a premise Cavendish herself repeatedly undermines by noting nature’s many disorders. I argue that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  45.  40
    Atomism in late medieval philosophy and theology.Christophe Grellard & Aurélien Robert (eds.) - 2009 - Boston: Brill.
    DMet 10: Prime matter is the origin of all quantities. Hence it is the origin of every dimension of continuous quantity whatever. ...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. Atomism and Semantics in the Philosophy of Jerrold Katz.Keith Begley - 2020 - In Ugo Zilioli (ed.), Atomism in Philosophy: A History from Antiquity to the Present. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 312-330.
    Jerrold J. Katz often explained his semantic theory by way of an analogy with physical atomism and an attendant analogy with chemistry. In this chapter, I track the origin and uses of these analogies by Katz, both in explaining and defending his decompositional semantic theory, through the various phases of his work throughout his career.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Biological Atomism and Cell Theory.Daniel J. Nicholson - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41 (3):202-211.
    Biological atomism postulates that all life is composed of elementary and indivisible vital units. The activity of a living organism is thus conceived as the result of the activities and interactions of its elementary constituents, each of which individually already exhibits all the attributes proper to life. This paper surveys some of the key episodes in the history of biological atomism, and situates cell theory within this tradition. The atomistic foundations of cell theory are subsequently dissected and discussed, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  48.  26
    Atomism in Philosophy: A History from Antiquity to the Present.Ugo Zilioli (ed.) - 2020 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    The nature of matter and the idea of indivisible parts has fascinated philosophers, historians, scientists and physicists from antiquity to the present day. This collection covers the richness of its history, starting with how the Ancient Greeks came to assume the existence of atoms and concluding with contemporary metaphysical debates about structure, time and reality. Focusing on important moments in the history of human thought when the debate about atomism was particularly flourishing and transformative for the scientific and philosophical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  3
    Modern atomism.J. Pasupathy (ed.) - 2017 - New Delhi: Project of History of Indian Science, Philosophy and Culture, Sub-Project: Consciousness, Science, Society, Value, and Yoga, Centre for Studies in Civilizations.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Beyond Atomism.Aaron Cotnoir - 2013 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (1):67-72.
    Contemporary metaphysicians have been drawn to a certain attractive picture of the structure of the world. This picture consists in classical mereology, the priority of parts over wholes, and the well-foundedness of metaphysical priority. In this short note, I show that this combination of theses entails superatomism, which is a significant strengthening of mereological atomism. This commitment has been missed in the literature due to certain sorts of models of mereology being overlooked. But the entailment is an important one: (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000