Results for 'Cartesian closed categories'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Locally cartesian closed categories and type theory.R. A. G. Seely - 1984 - Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 95 (1):33.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  2.  26
    Approximating Cartesian Closed Categories in NF-Style Set Theories.Morgan Thomas - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (1):143-160.
    I criticize, but uphold the conclusion of, an argument by McLarty to the effect that New Foundations style set theories don’t form a suitable foundation for category theory. McLarty’s argument is from the fact that Set and Cat are not Cartesian closed in NF-style set theories. I point out that these categories do still have a property approximating Cartesian closure, making McLarty’s argument not conclusive. After considering and attempting to address other problems with developing category theory (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  30
    Coherence in cartesian closed categories and the generality of proofs.M. E. Szabo - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (3):285 - 297.
    We introduce the notion of an alphabetic trace of a cut-free intuitionistic prepositional proof and show that it serves to characterize the equality of arrows in cartesian closed categories. We also show that alphabetic traces improve on the notion of the generality of proofs proposed in the literature. The main theorem of the paper yields a new and considerably simpler solution of the coherence problem for cartesian closed categories than those in [11, 14].
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  40
    Manufacturing a cartesian closed category with exactly two objects out of a c-monoid.P. H. Rodenburg & F. J. Linden - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (3):279-283.
    A construction is described of a cartesian closed category A with exactly two elements out of a C-monoid such that can be recovered from A without reference to the construction.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  20
    Cartesian closed Dialectica categories.Bodil Biering - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 156 (2):290-307.
    When Gödel developed his functional interpretation, also known as the Dialectica interpretation, his aim was to prove consistency of first order arithmetic by reducing it to a quantifier-free theory with finite types. Like other functional interpretations Gödel’s Dialectica interpretation gives rise to category theoretic constructions that serve both as new models for logic and semantics and as tools for analysing and understanding various aspects of the Dialectica interpretation itself. Gödel’s Dialectica interpretation gives rise to the Dialectica categories , in: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  38
    On the unification problem for cartesian closed categories.Paliath Narendran, Frank Pfenning & Richard Statman - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):636-647.
    Cartesian closed categories (CCCs) have played and continue to play an important role in the study of the semantics of programming languages. An axiomatization of the isomorphisms which hold in all Cartesian closed categories discovered independently by Soloviev and Bruce, Di Cosmo and Longo leads to seven equalities. We show that the unification problem for this theory is undecidable, thus settling an open question. We also show that an important subcase, namely unification modulo the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  59
    A note on Russell's paradox in locally cartesian closed categories.Andrew M. Pitts & Paul Taylor - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (3):377 - 387.
    Working in the fragment of Martin-Löfs extensional type theory [12] which has products (but not sums) of dependent types, we consider two additional assumptions: firstly, that there are (strong) equality types; and secondly, that there is a type which is universal in the sense that terms of that type name all types, up to isomorphism. For such a type theory, we give a version of Russell's paradox showing that each type possesses a closed term and (hence) that all terms (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  12
    Categorial Grammars and Natural Language Structures.Richard T. Oehrle, Emmon W. Bach & Deidre Wheeler (eds.) - 1988 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    For the most part, the papers collected in this volume stern from presentations given at a conference held in Tucson over the weekend of May 31 through June 2, 1985. We wish to record our gratitude to the participants in that conference, as well as to the National Science Foundation and the University of Arizona SBS Research Institute for their financial support. The advice we received from Susan Steele on organizational matters proved invaluable and had many felicitous consequences for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  42
    The breakdown of cartesian metaphysics.Richard A. Watson - 1963 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 1 (2):177-197.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Breakdown of C i M phy " artes an eta sacs RICHARD A. WATSON WITHIN CARTESIANISMthere arose many problems deriving from conflicts between Cartesian principles. Inadequate attempts to solve these problems were crucial reasons for the breakdown of Cartesian metaphysics in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries. The major difficulties derived from the acceptance of a dualism of substances seated in a system which included (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  10.  30
    Internal Diagrams and Archetypal Reasoning in Category Theory.Eduardo Ochs - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (3):291-321.
    We can regard operations that discard information, like specializing to a particular case or dropping the intermediate steps of a proof, as projections, and operations that reconstruct information as liftings. By working with several projections in parallel we can make sense of statements like “Set is the archetypal Cartesian Closed Category”, which means that proofs about CCCs can be done in the “archetypal language” and then lifted to proofs in the general setting. The method works even when our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  48
    Analysis of expressed sequence tag loci on wheat chromosome group 4. Miftahudin, K. Ross, X. -F. Ma, A. A. Mahmoud, J. Layton, M. A. Rodriguez Milla, T. Chikmawati, J. Ramalingam, O. Feril, M. S. Pathan, G. Surlan Momirovic, S. Kim, K. Chema, P. Fang, L. Haule, H. Struxness, J. Birkes, C. Yaghoubian, R. Skinner, J. McAllister, V. Nguyen, L. L. Qi, B. Echalier, B. S. Gill, A. M. Linkiewicz, J. Dubcovsky, E. D. Akhunov, J. Dvořák, M. Dilbirligi, K. S. Gill, J. H. Peng, N. L. V. Lapitan, C. E. Bermudez-Kandianis, M. E. Sorrells, K. G. Hossain, V. Kalavacharla, S. F. Kianian, G. R. Lazo, S. Chao, O. D. Anderson, J. Gonzalez-Hernandez, E. J. Conley, J. A. Anderson, D. -W. Choi, R. D. Fenton, T. J. Close, P. E. McGuire, C. O. Qualset, H. T. Nguyen & J. P. Gustafson - unknown
    A total of 1918 loci, detected by the hybridization of 938 expressed sequence tag unigenes from 26 Triticeae cDNA libraries, were mapped to wheat homoeologous group 4 chromosomes using a set of deletion, ditelosomic, and nulli-tetrasomic lines. The 1918 EST loci were not distributed uniformly among the three group 4 chromosomes; 41, 28, and 31% mapped to chromosomes 4A, 4B, and 4D, respectively. This pattern is in contrast to the cumulative results of EST mapping in all homoeologous groups, as reported (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  27
    Non-well-founded trees in categories.Benno van den Berg & Federico De Marchi - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 146 (1):40-59.
    Non-well-founded trees are used in mathematics and computer science, for modelling non-well-founded sets, as well as non-terminating processes or infinite data structures. Categorically, they arise as final coalgebras for polynomial endofunctors, which we call M-types. We derive existence results for M-types in locally cartesian closed pretoposes with a natural numbers object, using their internal logic. These are then used to prove stability of such categories with M-types under various topos-theoretic constructions; namely, slicing, formation of coalgebras , and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  30
    Closed categories and categorical grammar.Daniel J. Dougherty - 1992 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 34 (1):36-49.
  14.  44
    Propositions as [Types].Steve Awodey & Andrej Bauer - unknown
    Image factorizations in regular categories are stable under pullbacks, so they model a natural modal operator in dependent type theory. This unary type constructor [A] has turned up previously in a syntactic form as a way of erasing computational content, and formalizing a notion of proof irrelevance. Indeed, semantically, the notion of a support is sometimes used as surrogate proposition asserting inhabitation of an indexed family. We give rules for bracket types in dependent type theory and provide complete semantics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  53
    Topological Representation of the Lambda-Calculus.Steve Awodey - 2000 - Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 10 (1):81-96.
    The [lambda]-calculus can be represented topologically by assigning certain spaces to the types and certain continuous maps to the terms. Using a recent result from category theory, the usual calculus of [lambda]-conversion is shown to be deductively complete with respect to such topological semantics. It is also shown to be functionally complete, in the sense that there is always a ‘minimal’ topological model in which every continuous function is [lambda]-definable. These results subsume earlier ones using cartesian closed (...), as well as those employing so-called Henkin and Kripke [lambda]-models. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  35
    Interpolation property for bicartesian closed categories.Djordje Čubrić - 1994 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 33 (4):291-319.
    We show that proofs in the intuitionistic propositional logic factor through interpolants-in this way we prove a stronger interpolation property than the usual one which gives only the existence of interpolants.Translating that to categorical terms, we show that Pushouts (bipushouts) of bicartesian closed categories have the interpolation property (Theorem 3.2).
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  15
    Introduction to Higher Order Categorical Logic.Joachim Lambek & Philip J. Scott - 1986 - Cambridge University Press.
    In this book the authors reconcile two different viewpoints of the foundations of mathematics, namely mathematical logic and category theory. In Part I, they show that typed lambda-calculi, a formulation of higher order logic, and cartesian closed categories are essentially the same. In Part II, it is demonstrated that another formulation of higher order logic is closely related to topos theory. Part III is devoted to recursive functions. Numerous applications of the close relationship between traditional logic and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  41
    A general notion of realizability.Lars Birkedal - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):266-282.
    We present a general notion of realizability encompassing both standard Kleene style realizability over partial combinatory algebras and Kleene style realizability over more general structures, including all partial cartesian closed categories. We shown how the general notion of realizability can be used to get models of dependent predicate logic, thus obtaining as a corollary (the known result) that the category Equ of equilogical spaces models dependent predicate logic. Moreover, we characterize when the general notion of realizability gives (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  34
    Epistemic Horizons and the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics.Jochen Szangolies - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (12):1669-1697.
    In-principle restrictions on the amount of information that can be gathered about a system have been proposed as a foundational principle in several recent reconstructions of the formalism of quantum mechanics. However, it seems unclear precisely why one should be thus restricted. We investigate the notion of paradoxical self-reference as a possible origin of such epistemic horizons by means of a fixed-point theorem in Cartesian closed categories due to Lawvere that illuminates and unifies the different perspectives on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  27
    On the structure of paradoxes.Du?ko Pavlovi? - 1992 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (6):397-406.
    Paradox is a logical phenomenon. Usually, it is produced in type theory, on a type Ω of “truth values”. A formula Ψ (i.e., a term of type Ω) is presented, such that Ψ↔¬Ψ (with negation as a term¬∶Ω→Ω)-whereupon everything can be proved: In Sect. 1 we describe a general pattern which many constructions of the formula Ψ follow: for example, the well known arguments of Cantor, Russell, and Gödel. The structure uncovered behind these paradoxes is generalized in Sect. 2. This (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  50
    Kripke-style models for typed lambda calculus.John C. Mitchell & Eugenio Moggi - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 51 (1-2):99-124.
    Mitchell, J.C. and E. Moggi, Kripke-style models for typed lambda calculus, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 51 99–124. The semantics of typed lambda calculus is usually described using Henkin models, consisting of functions over some collection of sets, or concrete cartesian closed categories, which are essentially equivalent. We describe a more general class of Kripke-style models. In categorical terms, our Kripke lambda models are cartesian closed subcategories of the presheaves over a poset. To those (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  20
    The logic of closed categories.Manfred E. Szabo - 1977 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 18 (3):441-457.
  23.  51
    Mereology on Topological and Convergence Spaces.Daniel R. Patten - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (1):21-31.
    We show that a standard axiomatization of mereology is equivalent to the condition that a topological space is discrete, and consequently, any model of general extensional mereology is indistinguishable from a model of set theory. We generalize these results to the Cartesian closed category of convergence spaces.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  21
    Kripke models and the (in)equational logic of the second-order λ-calculus.Jean Gallier - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 84 (3):257-316.
    We define a new class of Kripke structures for the second-order λ-calculus, and investigate the soundness and completeness of some proof systems for proving inequalities as well as equations. The Kripke structures under consideration are equipped with preorders that correspond to an abstract form of reduction, and they are not necessarily extensional. A novelty of our approach is that we define these structures directly as functors A: → Preor equipped with certain natural transformations corresponding to application and abstraction . We (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. A Categorical Approach To Higher-level Introduction And Elimination Rules.Haydee Poubel & Luiz Pereira - 1994 - Reports on Mathematical Logic:3-19.
    A natural extension of Natural Deduction was defined by Schroder-Heister where not only formulas but also rules could be used as hypotheses and hence discharged. It was shown that this extension allows the definition of higher-level introduction and elimination schemes and that the set $\{ \vee, \wedge, \rightarrow, \bot \}$ of intuitionist sentential operators forms a {\it complete} set of operators modulo the higher level introduction and elimination schemes, i.e., that any operator whose introduction and elimination rules are instances of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  35
    An Intuitionistic Version of Cantor's Theorem.Dario Maguolo & Silvio Valentini - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):446-448.
    An intuitionistic version of Cantor's theorem, which shows that there is no surjective function from the type of the natural numbers N into the type N → N of the functions from N into N, is proved within Martin-Löf's Intuitionistic Type Theory with the universe of the small types.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Tools for the Advancement of Objective Logic: Closed Categories and Toposes.F. William Lawvere - 1994 - In John Macnamara & Gonzalo E. Reyes (eds.), The Logical Foundations of Cognition. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 43-56.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. Cartesian categories in mind-body identity theories.R. de Boer - 1975 - Philosophical Forum 7 (2):139-58.
  29. A Relationship between Equilogical Spaces and Type Two Effectivity.Andrej Bauer - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (S1):1-15.
    In this paper I compare two well studied approaches to topological semantics – the domain-theoretic approach, exemplified by the category of countably based equilogical spaces, Equ and Typ Two Effectivity, exemplified by the category of Baire space representations, Rep . These two categories are both locally cartesian closed extensions of countably based T0-spaces. A natural question to ask is how they are related.First, we show that Rep is equivalent to a full coreflective subcategory of Equ, consisting of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  29
    Cartesian Consciousness and the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Richard E. Aquila - 2016 - In Sally Sedgwick & Dina Emundts (eds.), Bewusstsein/Consciousness. De Gruyter. pp. 3-24.
  31.  49
    Topologies and free constructions.Anna Bucalo & Giuseppe Rosolini - 2013 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 22 (3):327-346.
    The standard presentation of topological spaces relies heavily on (naïve) set theory: a topology consists of a set of subsets of a set (of points). And many of the high-level tools of set theory are required to achieve just the basic results about topological spaces. Concentrating on the mathematical structures, category theory offers the possibility to look synthetically at the structure of continuous transformations between topological spaces addressing specifically how the fundamental notions of point and open come about. As a (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  17
    The Maximality of Cartesian Categories.Z. Petric & K. Dosen - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):137-144.
    It is proved that equations between arrows assumed for cartesian categories are maximal in the sense that extending them with any new equation in the language of free cartesian categories collapses a cartesian category into a preorder. An analogous result holds for categories with binary products, which may lack a terminal object. The proof is based on a coherence result for cartesian categories, which is related to model-theoretic methods of normalization. This maximality (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  33.  28
    Closing the Cartesian Theatre.Andy Young - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):233-233.
  34.  7
    A predicative variant of hyland’s effective topos.Maria Emilia Maietti & Samuele Maschio - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (2):433-447.
    Here, we present a category ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ which can be considered a predicative variant of Hyland's Effective Topos ${{\mathbf {Eff} }}$ for the following reasons. First, its construction is carried in Feferman’s predicative theory of non-iterative fixpoints ${{\widehat {ID_1}}}$. Second, ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ is a list-arithmetic locally cartesian closed pretopos with a full subcategory ${{\mathbf {pEff}_{set}}}$ of small objects having the same categorical structure which is preserved by the embedding in ${\mathbf {pEff}}$ ; furthermore subobjects in ${{\mathbf {pEff}_{set}}}$ are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  34
    Functional completeness of cartesian categories.J. Lambek - 1974 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 6 (3):259.
  36.  30
    Partial Horn logic and cartesian categories.Erik Palmgren & Steven J. Vickers - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 145 (3):314-353.
  37.  58
    Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology.Edmund Husserl & Dorion Cairns (eds.) - 1933 - Martinus Nijhoff.
    The "Cartesian Meditations" translation is based primarily on the printed text, edited by Professor S. Strasser and published in the first volume of Husserliana: Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge, ISBN 90-247-0214-3. Most of Husserl's emendations, as given in the Appendix to that volume, have been treated as if they were part of the text. The others have been translated in footnotes. Secondary consideration has been given to a typescript (cited as "Typescript C") on which Husserl wrote in 1933: "Cartes. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  38.  38
    How similar are semantic categories in closely related languages? A comparison of cutting and breaking in four Germanic languages.Asifa Majid, Marianne Gullberg, Miriam van Staden & Melissa Bowerman - 2007 - Cognitive Linguistics 18 (2).
  39.  14
    Existential Morphisms and Existentially Closed Models of Logical Categories.Ioana Petrescu - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (23‐24):363-370.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  28
    Existential Morphisms and Existentially Closed Models of Logical Categories.Ioana Petrescu - 1981 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 27 (23-24):363-370.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Cartesian Epistemology: Is the theory of the self-transparent mind innate?Peter Carruthers - 2008 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 15 (4):28-53.
    This paper argues that a Cartesian belief in the self-transparency of minds might actually be an innate aspect of our mind-reading faculty. But it acknowledges that some crucial evidence needed to establish this claim hasn’t been looked for or collected. What we require is evidence that a belief in the self-transparency of mind is universal to the human species. The paper closes with a call to anthropologists (and perhaps also developmental psychologists), who are in a position to collect such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  42.  33
    Inconsistent Mathematics.Category Theory.Closed Set Sheaves and Their Categories.Foundations: Provability, Truth and Sets. [REVIEW]Newton C. A. da Costa, Otavio Bueno, Chris Mortensen, Peter Lavers, William James & Joshua Cole - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):683.
  43.  16
    Categories for the Working Mathematician.Saunders Maclane - 1971 - Springer.
    Category Theory has developed rapidly. This book aims to present those ideas and methods which can now be effectively used by Mathe­ maticians working in a variety of other fields of Mathematical research. This occurs at several levels. On the first level, categories provide a convenient conceptual language, based on the notions of category, functor, natural transformation, contravariance, and functor category. These notions are presented, with appropriate examples, in Chapters I and II. Next comes the fundamental idea of an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  44.  60
    Cartesian Reflections: Essays on Descartes's Philosophy.Deborah J. Brown - 2010 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):731-734.
    HOME . ABOUT US . CONTACT US HELP . PUBLISH WITH US . LIBRARIANS Search in or Explore Browse Publications A-Z Browse Subjects A-Z Advanced Search University of Cambridge SIGN IN Register | Why Register? | Sign Out | Got a Voucher? prev abstract next Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes A Devout Catholic? Knowledge of The Mental Thought and Language Descartes as A Natural Philosopher Substance Dualism Notes Two Approaches to Reading the Historical Descartes Author: Desmond M. Clarke (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  52
    Cartesian epistemology and infallible justification.Richard Fumerton - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):4671-4681.
    In this paper I examine contemporary accounts of noninferential justification in light of what I take to be the Cartesian project of building epistemology on foundations made secure by the impossibility of error. I argue that familiar abstract arguments for foundationalism, by themselves, don’t seem to motivate Cartesianism. But I further argue that there is one version of foundationalism that is more closely linked to the way in which Descartes sought ideal knowledge.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  75
    Cartesian epistemology.Peter Carruthers - manuscript
    This paper argues that a Cartesian belief in the self-transparency of minds might actually be an innate aspect of our mind-reading faculty. But it acknowledges that some crucial evidence needed to establish this claim hasn’t been looked for or collected. What we require is evidence that a belief in the self-transparency of mind is universal to the human species. The paper closes with a call to anthropologists (and perhaps also developmental psychologists), who are in a position to collect such (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    The Cartesian Projection.Gavin Ardley - 1957 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 7:83-100.
    WHATEVER one may think of the merits and demerits of the Cartesian system one must acknowledge the great vitality of the Cartesian principles. They were launched with a passion, a sincerity, an engagement rarely equalled. The principles in some way met a deeply-felt need stirring in many breasts in the 17th century; a half-unconscious aspiration which many struggled to articulate and expressed in a variety of ways. Bacon, Galileo, Descartes, each in his own way helped to formulate and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Cartesian causation: Continuous, instantaneous, overdetermined.Geoffrey Gorham - 2004 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (4):389-423.
    : Descartes provides an original and puzzling argument for the traditional theological doctrine that the world is continuously created by God. His key premise is that the parts of the duration of anything are "completely independent" of one another. I argue that Descartes derives this temporal independence thesis simply from the principle that causes are necessarily simultaneous with their effects. I argue further that it follows from Descartes's version of the continuous creation doctrine that God is the instantaneous and total (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  49.  76
    Cartesian truth.Thomas C. Vinci - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues that science and metaphysics are closely and inseparably interwoven in the work of Descartes, such that the metaphysics cannot be understood without the science and vice versa. In order to make his case, Thomas Vinci offers a careful philosophical reconstruction of central parts of Descartes' metaphysics and of his theory of perception, each considered in relation to Descartes' epistemology. Many authors of late have written on the relation between Descartes' metaphysics and his physics, especially insofar as the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  50. Category mistakes and figurative language.Ofra Magidor - 2015 - Philosophical Studies (1):1-14.
    Category mistakes are sentences such as ”The number two is blue’ or ”Green ideas sleep furiously’. Such sentences are highly infelicitous and thus a prominent view claims that they are meaningless. Category mistakes are also highly prevalent in figurative language. That is to say, it is very common for sentences which are used figuratively to be such that, if taken literally, they would constitute category mistakes. In this paper I argue that the view that category mistakes are meaningless is inconsistent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000