Results for ' semantic preference'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  9
    Implicit learning of semantic preferences of English words by Chinese learners.Fengying Li, Chenlu Zhao & Weijian Li - 2020 - Consciousness and Cognition 84:102986.
  2. A Preference Semantics for Imperatives.William B. Starr - 2020 - Semantics and Pragmatics 20.
    Imperative sentences like Dance! do not seem to represent the world. Recent modal analyses challenge this idea, but its intuitive and historical appeal remain strong. This paper presents three new challenges for a non-representational analysis, showing that the obstacles facing it are even steeper than previously appreciated. I will argue that the only way for the non-representationalist to meet these three challenges is to adopt a dynamic semantics. Such a dynamic semantics is proposed here: imperatives introduce preferences between alternatives. This (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  3. Preference semantics for deontic logic. Part I: Simple models.Lou Goble - 2003 - Logique Et Analyse 46:383-418.
  4.  37
    Preferential Semantics using Non-smooth Preference Relations.Frederik Van De Putte & Christian Straßer - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (5):903-942.
    This paper studies the properties of eight semantic consequence relations defined from a Tarski-logic L and a preference relation ≺. They are equivalent to Shoham’s so-called preferential entailment for smooth model structures, but avoid certain problems of the latter in non-smooth configurations. Each of the logics can be characterized in terms of what we call multi-selection semantics. After discussing this type of semantics, we focus on some concrete proposals from the literature, checking a number of meta-theoretic properties and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. Preference Semantics for Deontic Logic - Part II: Multiplex Models.Lou Goble - 2004 - Logique Et Analyse 47.
  6.  5
    Preference Logic Grammars: Fixed point semantics and application to data standardization.Baoqiu Cui & Terrance Swift - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence 138 (1-2):117-147.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Single-peakedness and semantic dimensions of preferences.Daniele Porello - 2016 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 24 (4).
    Among the possible solutions to the paradoxes of collective preferences, single-peakedness is significant because it has been associated to a suggestive conceptual interpretation: a single-peaked preference profile entails that, although individuals may disagree on which option is the best, they conceptualize the choice along a shared unique dimension, i.e. they agree on the rationale of the collective decision. In this article, we discuss the relationship between the structural property of singlepeakedness and its suggested interpretation as uni-dimensionality of a social (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  67
    A new semantical approach to the logic of preference.Sven Ove Hansson - 1989 - Erkenntnis 31 (1):1 - 42.
    A possible world semantics for preference is developed. The remainder operator () is used to give precision to the notion that two states of the world are as similar as possible, given a specified difference between them. A general structure is introduced for preference relations between states of affairs, and three types of such preference relations are defined. It is argued that one of them, actual preference, corresponds closely to the concept of preference in informal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  36
    The Irrationality of Adaptive Preferences: A Psychological and Semantic Account.Seena Eftekhari - 2021 - Utilitas 33 (1):68-84.
    There is little agreement among moral and political philosophers when it comes to determining what it is that makes adaptive preferences problematic. The large number of competing explanations offered by philosophers illustrates the absence of any consensus. The most prominent versions of these explanations have recently come under attack by Dale Dorsey, who argues that adaptive preferences are a red herring: the problematic nature of adaptive preferences is not explained by the fact of adaptation but by an appeal to some (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  29
    Variants of Rescher's semantics for preference logic and some completeness theorems.Dirk Dalen - 1974 - Studia Logica 33 (2):163 - 181.
  11.  15
    A selective semantics for logic programs with preferences.Alfredo Gabaldon - 2012 - In Luis Farinas del Cerro, Andreas Herzig & Jerome Mengin (eds.), Logics in Artificial Intelligence. Springer. pp. 215--227.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  40
    An inkblot for sexual preference: A semantic variant of the Affect Misattribution Procedure.Roland Imhoff, Alexander F. Schmidt, Johanna Bernhardt, Andreas Dierksmeier & Rainer Banse - 2011 - Cognition and Emotion 25 (4):676-690.
  13. A Fully Model-Theoretic Semantics for Model-Preference Default Systems', Istituto di Elaborazione dell'Informazione, Pisa.F. Sebastiani - forthcoming - Studia Logica.
  14. Kripke-type semantics for preference logic.Krister Segerberg - 1970 - In Thorild Dahlquist & Tom Pauli (eds.), Logic and Value. Uppsala,[Filosofiska Föreningen Och Filosofiska Institutionen Vid Uppsala Universitet].
  15.  36
    Variants of Rescher's semantics for preference logic and some completeness theorems.Dirk van Dalen - 1974 - Studia Logica 33 (2):163-181.
  16.  33
    A note on Rescher's 'Semantic Foundations for the Logic of Preference'.Anthony Willing - 1976 - Theory and Decision 7 (3):221-229.
    In ‘Semantic Foundations for the Logic of Preference’ (Rescher, ed.,The Logic of Decision and Action, University Press, Pittsburgh, 1967), Nicholas Rescher claims that, on the semantics developed in that paper, a certain principle - call it ‘Q’ turns out to be ‘unacceptable’. I argue, however, that, given certain assumptions that Rescher invokes in that same paper,Q can in fact be shown to be a ‘preference-tautology’, and henceQ should be classified as ‘acceptable’ on Rescher's theory.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  9
    Algorithms for decision problems in argument systems under preferred semantics.Samer Nofal, Katie Atkinson & Paul E. Dunne - 2014 - Artificial Intelligence 207 (C):23-51.
  18.  19
    Combining totalitarian and Ceteris Paribus semantics in database preference queries.Rui da Silva Neves & Souhila Kaci - 2010 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 18 (3):464-483.
    Preference queries from databases aim to retrieve the best answers w.r.t. user's requirements. The integration of preferences in database queries has known many advances in the last decade. Most of works however are based on comparative preference statements obeying more or less strong semantics. Representing and reasoning about comparative preference statements has also been widely investigated in Artificial Intelligence. In this paper, we bridge the two frameworks and develop a simple and unified framework to reason about preferences (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Preference logic, conditionals and solution concepts in games.Johan van Benthem - unknown
    Preference is a basic notion in human behaviour, underlying such varied phenomena as individual rationality in the philosophy of action and game theory, obligations in deontic logic (we should aim for the best of all possible worlds), or collective decisions in social choice theory. Also, in a more abstract sense, preference orderings are used in conditional logic or non-monotonic reasoning as a way of arranging worlds into more or less plausible ones. The field of preference logic (cf. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  20.  25
    Using corpus methodology for semantic and pragmatic analyses: What can corpora tell us about the linguistic expression of emotions?Ulrike Oster - 2010 - Cognitive Linguistics 21 (4):727-763.
    The aim of this paper is to explore some of the possibilities, advantages and difficulties of corpus-based analyses of semantic and pragmatic aspects of language in one particular field, namely the linguistic expression of emotion concepts. For this purpose, a methodological procedure is proposed and an exemplary analysis of the emotion concept “fear” in English is performed. The procedure combines Kövecses' lexical approach and Stefanowitsch's metaphorical pattern analysis with additional concepts from corpus linguistics such as semantic preference (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  21. Conditional preferences and practical conditionals.Nate Charlow - 2013 - Linguistics and Philosophy 36 (6):463-511.
    I argue that taking the Practical Conditionals Thesis seriously demands a new understanding of the semantics of such conditionals. Practical Conditionals Thesis: A practical conditional [if A][ought] expresses B’s conditional preferability given A Paul Weirich has argued that the conditional utility of a state of affairs B on A is to be identified as the degree to which it is desired under indicative supposition that A. Similarly, exploiting the PCT, I will argue that the proper analysis of indicative practical conditionals (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  22. On preferring.Kyle Blumberg - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (6):1315-1344.
    In this paper, I draw attention to comparative preference claims, i.e. sentences of the form \S prefers p to q\. I show that preference claims exhibit interesting patterns, and try to develop a semantics that captures them. Then I use my account of preference to provide an analysis of desire. The resulting entry for desire ascriptions is independently motivated, and finds support from a wide range of phenomena.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  58
    Preference-based deontic logic (PDL).Sven Ove Hansson - 1990 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 19 (1):75 - 93.
    A new possible world semantics for deontic logic is proposed. Its intuitive basis is that prohibitive predicates (such as "wrong" and "prohibited") have the property of negativity, i.e. that what is worse than something wrong is itself wrong. The logic of prohibitive predicates is built on this property and on preference logic. Prescriptive predicates are defined in terms of prohibitive predicates, according to the wellknown formula "ought" = "wrong that not". In this preference-based deontic logic (PDL), those theorems (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  24.  80
    Competing semantics of vagueness: Many values versus super-truth.David H. Saford - 1976 - Synthese 33 (2-4):195--210.
    A semantics of vagueness should reject the principle that every statement has a truth-value yet retain the classical tautologies. A many-value, non-truth-functional semantics and a semantics of super-valuations each have this result. According to the super-valuation approach, 'if a man with n hairs on his head is bald, then a man with n plus one hairs on his head is also bald' is false because it comes out false no matter how the vague predicate 'is bald' is appropriately made precise. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. A preference for sense and reference.Gabriel Segal - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (2):73-89.
    The topic of this paper is the semantic structure of belief reports of the form 'a believes that p'. it is argued that no existing theory of these sentences satisfactorily accounts for anaphoric relations linking expressions within the embedded complement sentence to expressions outside. a new account of belief reports is proposed which assigns to embedded expressions their normal semantic values but which also exploits frege's idea of using senses to explain the apparent failures of extensionality in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  26.  9
    Semantics of Proper Names as a Philosophical Problem.Alexey Chenyak - 2016 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 49 (3):70-87.
    Standard semantics of proper names assigns them the function of reference to individual things. This presupposes that to understand the meaning of a proper name is to understand what it denotes in the context of its referential use. But unambiguous identification of the referent of a proper name in its normal (referential) use looks like an unsolvable problem. Senses associated with referential uses of such names don't allow ascribing them singular referents in their contexts; and what concerns contexts themselves, they (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Conceptual role semantics for moral terms.Ralph Wedgwood - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):1-30.
    This paper outlines a new approach to the task of giving an account of the meaning of moral statements: a sort of "conceptual role semantics", according to which the meaning of moral terms is given by their role in practical reasoning. This role is sufficient both to distinguish the meaning of any moral term from that of other terms, and to determine the property or relation (if any) that the term stands for. The paper ends by suggesting reasons for regarding (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  28. Pragmatics, semantic undetermination and the referential/attributive distinction.A. Bezuidenhout - 1997 - Mind 106 (423):375-409.
    It has long ben recognised that there are referential uses of definite descriptions. It is not as widely recognised that there are atttributives uses of idexicals and other such paradigmatically singular terms. I offer an account of the referential/attributive distinction which is intended to give a unified treatment of both sorts of cases. I argue that the best way to account for the referential/attributive distinction is to treat is as semantically underdetermined which sort of propositions is expressed in a context. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  29.  66
    Multiplex semantics for deontic logic.Lou Goble - 2000 - Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 5 (2):113-134.
    This multiplex semantics incorporates multiple relations of deontic accessibility or multiple preference rankings on alternative worlds to represent distinct normative standards. This provides a convenient framework for deontic logic that allows conflicts of obligation, due either to conflicts between normative standards or to incoherence within a single standard. With the multiplex structures, two general senses of "ought" may be distinguished, an indefinite sense under which something is obligatory when it is enjoined by some normative standard and a core sense (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  30.  7
    Semantic games for first-order entailment with algorithmic players.Emmanuel Genot & Justine Jacot - unknown
    If semantic consequence is analyzed with extensive games, logical reasoning can be accounted for by looking at how players solve entailment games. However, earlier approaches to game semantics cannot achieve this reduction, by want of explicitly dened preferences for players. Moreover, although entailment games can naturally translate the idea of argumentation about a common ground, a cognitive interpretation is undermined by the complexity of strategic reasoning. We thus describe a class of semantic extensive entailment game with algorithmic players, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  19
    The Semantics of Aesthetic Judgements.James O. Young (ed.) - 2017 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Are aesthetic judgements simply expressions of personal preference? If two people disagree about the beauty of a painting are both judgements valid or can someone be mistaken about the aesthetic value of an artwork? This volume brings together some of the leading philosophers of art and language to debate the status of aesthetic judgements.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32. Binding, Compositionality, and Semantic Values.Michael Glanzberg & Jeffrey C. King - 2020 - Philosophers' Imprint 20.
    In this paper, we defend a traditional approach to semantics, that holds that the outputs of compositional semantics are propositional, i.e. truth conditions. Though traditional, this view has been challenged on a number of fronts over the years. Since classic work of Lewis, arguments have been offered which purport to show that semantic composition requires values that are relativized, e.g. to times, or other parameters that render them no longer propositional. Focusing in recent variants of these arguments involving quantification (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  36
    Semantic Interpretation as Computation in Nonmonotonic Logic: The Real Meaning of the Suppression Task.Keith Stenning & Michiel Lambalgen - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (6):919-960.
    Interpretation is the process whereby a hearer reasons to an interpretation of a speaker's discourse. The hearer normally adopts a credulous attitude to the discourse, at least for the purposes of interpreting it. That is to say the hearer tries to accommodate the truth of all the speaker's utterances in deriving an intended model. We present a nonmonotonic logical model of this process which defines unique minimal preferred models and efficiently simulates a kind of closed-world reasoning of particular interest for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  34.  53
    Does Semantics Need Normativity? Comments on Allan Gibbard, Meaning and Normativity.Åsa Wikforss - 2018 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (7):755-766.
    In the book Gibbard proposes, first, that statements about meaning are normative statements and, second, that they can be given an expressivist treatment, along the lines of Gibbard’s preferred metaethics. In my paper, I examine the first step: The claim that meaning statements are to be construed as being normative, as involving ‘oughts’. Gibbard distinguishes two versions of the normativity of meaning thesis – a weak version, according to which every means implies an ought, and a strong version, according to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. A Semantic Approach to Nonmonotonic Reasoning: Inference Operations and Choice, Uppsala Prints and Preprints in Philosophy, 1994, no 10.Sten Lindström - manuscript
    This paper presents a uniform semantic treatment of nonmonotonic inference operations that allow for inferences from infinite sets of premises. The semantics is formulated in terms of selection functions and is a generalization of the preferential semantics of Shoham (1987), (1988), Kraus, Lehman, and Magidor (1990) and Makinson (1989), (1993). A selection function picks out from a given set of possible states (worlds, situations, models) a subset consisting of those states that are, in some sense, the most preferred ones. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  23
    Semantic Interpretation as Computation in Nonmonotonic Logic: The Real Meaning of the Suppression Task.Keith Stenning & Michiel van Lambalgen - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (6):919-960.
    Interpretation is the process whereby a hearer reasons to an interpretation of a speaker's discourse. The hearer normally adopts a credulous attitude to the discourse, at least for the purposes of interpreting it. That is to say the hearer tries to accommodate the truth of all the speaker's utterances in deriving an intended model. We present a nonmonotonic logical model of this process which defines unique minimal preferred models and efficiently simulates a kind of closed-world reasoning of particular interest for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  37. Is Semantics Really Psychologically Real?Mihaela Popa-Wyatt - 2009 - In L. Larrazabal J. & Zubeldia (ed.), Meaning, Content and Argument. Proceedings of the ILCLI International Workshop on Semantics, Pragmatics, and Rhetoric. University of the Basque Country Press.. pp. 497-514.
    The starting point for this paper is a critical discussion of claims of psychological reality articulated within Borg’s (forth.) minimal semantics and Carpintero’s (2007) character*-semantics. It has been proposed, for independent reasons, that their respective accounts can accommodate, or at least avoid the challenge from psychological evidence. I outline their respective motivations, suggesting various shortcomings in their efforts of preserving the virtues of an uncontaminated semantics in the face of psychological objection (I-II), and try to make the case that, at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  14
    Preferences in the use of overabundance: predictors of lexical bias in Estonian.Mari Aigro & Virve-Anneli Vihman - 2024 - Cognitive Linguistics 35 (2):289-312.
    This study of morphological overabundance focuses on the (non-)synonymy of parallel forms in Estonian illative case (‘into’) and the type of entrenchment behind it. We focus on the lexical level, testing whether the form preferred for a lexeme depends on semantic or morphophonological factors, or both. Using multifactorial regression analyses, we compare three corpus datasets: lexemes biased toward long forms, those biased toward short forms and lexemes with balanced form distribution. This is the first study to investigate realised overabundance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  44
    Semantics for Dual Preferential Entailment.Katarina Britz, Johannes Heidema & Willem Labuschagne - 2009 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (4):433-446.
    We introduce and explore the notion of duality for entailment relations induced by preference orderings on states. We discuss the relationship between these preferential entailment relations from the perspectives of Boolean algebra, inference rules, and modal axiomatisation. Interpreting the preference relations as accessibility relations establishes modular Gödel-Löb logic as a suitable modal framework for rational preferential reasoning.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  87
    Conceptual engineering and semantic deference.Joey Pollock - 2019 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 12:81-98.
    Many ameliorative projects aim at moral goods such as social equality. For example, the amelioration of the concept MARRIAGE forms part of efforts to achieve equal rights for the LGBT+ community. What does implementation of such an ameliorated concept consist in? In this paper, I argue that, for some ameliorated concepts, successful implementation requires that individuals eschew semantic deference, at least with respect to relevant dimensions of the concept. My argument appeals to consideration of the aims of conceptual engineers (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  41. Semantic triangulation.Peter Pagin - manuscript
    Suppose you are stranded on an island and you want to get over to the nearby mainland. Your only option is to swim. But is the other shore close enough? If you embark and it isn’t, you drown. So you prefer to know before taking off. Happily, you are well equipped. You have not only a yardstick, but also a theodolite for measuring angles, and a good knowledge of trigonometry. You then determine the distance to the other shore by means (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  42. Metaphysical semantics versus ground on questions of realism.Rohan Sud - 2022 - Analysis 82 (3):464-472.
    One desideratum for a theory of fundamentality is to give us the conceptual tools to articulate fruitful metaphysical distinctions between the assortment of ‘realist’ and ‘anti-realist’ positions in a given domain such as meta-ethics. The ability to articulate such distinctions gives us a way to assess rival theories of fundamentality, such as Fine’s grounding theory and Sider’s metaphysical semantic theory. Indeed, Sider has argued that metaphysical semantic theories have an edge with respect to this desideratum and takes this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  36
    Preference‐Conditioned Necessities: Detachment and Practical Reasoning.Sven Lauer & Cleo Condoravdi - 2014 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4):584-621.
    This article is about conditionalized modal statements whose antecedents concern a preferential attitude of an agent. The focus is on anankastic conditionals or, as they are known in the philosophical literature, hypothetical imperatives. We present a linguistically-motivated analysis of anankastic and related conditionals and use it to address challenges for semantic theories of natural language conditionals motivated by certain philosophical concerns about practical reasoning and the requirements of rationality.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  13
    Semantic Games for Algorithmic Players.Emmanuel Genot & Justine Jacot - unknown
    We describe a class of semantic extensive entailment game with algorithmic players, related to game-theoretic semantics, and generalized to classical first-order semantic entailment. Players have preferences for parsimonious spending of computational resources, and compute partial strategies, under qualitative uncertainty about future histories. We prove the existence of local preferences for moves, and strategic fixpoints, that allow to map eeg game-tree to the building rules and closure rules of Smullyan's semantic tableaux. We also exhibit a strategy profile that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  21
    Semantic Stipulation and Knowledge De Re.Chris Tillman & Joshua Spencer - 2012 - In William Kabasenche, Michael O’Rourke & Matthew Slater (eds.), Reference and Referring: Topics in Contemporary Philosophy, Volume 10. Cambridge, MA: pp. 119-148.
    Kripke's discussion in Naming and Necessity strongly suggests that semantic stipulation allows us to have new de re thoughts and make new de re claims. For example, it seems we could name the winning ticket in the next lottery 'Tickie' and thereby come to have singular thoughts about Tickie as opposed to merely general thoughts about the winning ticket (whichever one that is). This, in turn, seems to put us into a position to know that Tickie is the winning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Semantics for more plausible deontic logics.Sven Ove Hansson - manuscript
    In order to avoid the paradoxes of standard deontic logic, we have to give up the semantic construction that identifies obligatory status with presence in all elements of a subset of the set of possible worlds. It is proposed that deontic logic should instead be based on a preference relation, according to the principle that whatever is better than something permitted is itself permitted. Close connections hold between the logical properties of a preference relation and those of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  51
    Biased Questions and Hamblin Semantics.Anton Zimmerling - 2023 - Typology of Morphosyntactic Parameters 6 (2):92-135.
    This paper takes a stand on Hamblin semantics and its relation to the semantics-to-pragmatics interface. Biased questions, where the speaker finds one of the options more likely and expects the confirmation that p is true, raise a concern about the limits of Hamblin semantics. I argue that biased questions have modified Hamblin semantics, while unbiased questions have unconstrained Hamblin semantics. The optional bias feature explains compositionally. It is triggered by likelihood presuppositions ranging Hamblin sets and highlighting the preferred alternative(s). Biased (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    A Semantic Profile of Early Sanskrit “buddhi”.James L. Fitzgerald - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (4):669-709.
    The word buddhi is an important term of Indian philosophical discourse, but some aspects of its use have caused confusion and continue to occasion difficulties. This paper undertakes a survey of the usage of the word buddhi in general Sanskrit literature from its earliest late Vedic occurrences up to the middle of the first millennium CE. Signifying fundamentally “awareness,” the word “buddhi” is shown to refer often to a being’s persisting capacity or faculty of awareness and also, often, to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  14
    A Semantic Profile of Early Sanskrit “buddhi”.James L. Fitzgerald - 2017 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 45 (4):669-709.
    The word buddhi is an important term of Indian philosophical discourse, but some aspects of its use have caused confusion and continue to occasion difficulties. This paper undertakes a survey of the usage of the word buddhi in general Sanskrit literature from its earliest late Vedic occurrences up to the middle of the first millennium CE. Signifying fundamentally “awareness,” the word “buddhi” is shown to refer often to a being’s persisting capacity or faculty of awareness and also, often, to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  25
    Herbert A. Simon. The logic of rational decision. The British journal for the philosophy of science, vol. 16 no. 63 , pp. 169–186. - Herbert A. Simon. The logic of heuristic decision making. The logic of decision and action, edited by Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh1967, pp. 1–20. - Robert Binkley. Comments on H. Simon's “The logic of heuristic decision making.”The logic of decision and action, edited by Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh1967, pp. 21–26. - Nuel D. Belnap Jr. Comments on H. Simon's “The logic of heuristic decision making.”The logic of decision and action, edited by Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh1967, pp. 27–31. - Herbert A. Simon. Reply to comments. The logic of decision and action, edited by Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh1967, pp. 32–35. - Nicholas Rescher. Semantic foundations for the logic of preference. The logic of decision and action, edited by Nichol. [REVIEW]Edward E. Dawson - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):135-144.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000