Results for ' penal sentence'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  23
    Sentencing guidelines and penal aims in Minnesota.Andrew von Hirsch - 1994 - Criminal Justice Ethics 13 (1):39-49.
  2. Sentencing in Cyprus: Structure, penal aims and case law.Andreas Kapardis - 2003 - Rechtstheorie 34 (1):85-95.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  25
    Remorse, Penal Theory and Sentencing Hannah Maslen, 2015 Oxford and Portland, OR, Hart Publishing xvi 212 pp. £40.00. [REVIEW]Steven Tudor - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (3):n/a-n/a.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  23
    Remorse, Penal Theory and Sentencing Hannah Maslen, 2015 Oxford and Portland, OR, Hart Publishing xvi 212 pp. £40.00. [REVIEW]Steven Tudor - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (2):281-283.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  5
    Penal censure: engagements within and beyond desert theory.Antje du Bois-Pedain & Anthony E. Bottoms (eds.) - 2019 - New York: Hart Publishing.
    The exploration of penal censure in this book is inspired by the fortieth anniversary in 2016 of the publication of Andreas von Hirsch's Doing Justice, which opened up a fresh set of issues in theorisation about punishment that eventually led von Hirsch to ground his proposed model of desert-based sentencing on the notion of penal censure. Von Hirsch's work thus provides an obvious starting-point for an exploration of the importance of censure for the justification of punishment, both within (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Proportionate Sentencing: Exploring the Principles.Andrew Von Hirsch & Andrew Ashworth - 2005 - Oxford University Press UK.
    The principle that a sentence should be proportionate to the seriousness of the offence remains at the centre of penal practice and scholarly debate. This volume explores highly topical aspects of proportionality theory that require examination and further analysis. von Hirsch and Ashworth explore the relevance of the principle of proportionality to the sentencing of young offenders, the possible reasons for departing from the principle when sentencing dangerous offenders, and the application of the principle to socially deprived offenders. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  7.  29
    Retributivism, Penal Censure, and Life Imprisonment without Parole.Netanel Dagan & Julian V. Roberts - 2019 - Criminal Justice Ethics 38 (1):1-18.
    This article advances a censure-based case against sentences of life imprisonment without the possibility of parole. Our argument justifies a retributive “second look” assessment of long-term priso...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  26
    Sentencing and Artificial Intelligence.Jesper Ryberg & Julian V. Roberts - 2022 - Oxford: OUP.
    Is it morally acceptable to use artificial intelligence (AI) in the form of computer-driven algorithms in the determination of sentences on those who have broken the law? If so, how should such algorithms be used? This book is the first collective work devoted exclusively to the ethical and penal theoretical considerations of the use of AI at sentencing. It deals with a wide range of highly pertinent issues, such as the following: Should algorithmic-based decision-making be transparent? If so, what (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Lowering the Boom: A Brief for Penal Leniency.Benjamin S. Yost - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (2):251-270.
    This paper advocates for a general policy of penal leniency: judges should often sentence offenders to a punishment less severe than initially preferred. The argument’s keystone is the relatively uncontroversial Minimal Invasion Principle (MIP). MIP says that when more than one course of action satisfies a state’s legitimate aim, only the least invasive is permissibly pursued. I contend that MIP applies in two common sentencing situations. In the first, all sentences within a statutorily specified range are equally proportionate. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Do we believe in penal substitution?David K. Lewis - 1997 - Philosophical Papers 26 (3):203 - 209.
    If a guilty offender is justly sentenced to be punished and an innocent volunteer agrees to be punished instead, is that any reason to leave the offender unpunished? In the context of mundane criminal justice, we mostly think not. But in a religious context, some Christians do believe in penal substitution as a theory of the atonement. However, it is not just these Christians, but most of us, who are of two minds. If the punishment is an imprisonment or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  11.  19
    Review of Hannah Maslen: Remorse, Penal Theory and Sentencing: Hart Publishing, Oxford, 2015, 212 pp. [REVIEW]Jonathan Peterson - 2019 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 13 (4):667-672.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Dollars, sense, and penal reform: Social movements and the future of the carceral state.Marie Gottschalk - 2007 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 74 (2):669-694.
    Nearly one in every 100 adults in the United States is in jail or prison today. In a period dominated by calls to roll back the government in all areas of social and economic policy, we have witnessed its massive expansion in the realm of penal policy since the 1970s. The U.S. incarceration rate is now more than 737 per 100,000 people, or five to 12 times the rate of Western European countries and Japan . The reach of the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  6
    Sentencing the Self-Convicted: The Ethics of Pleading Guilty.Julian V. Roberts & Jesper Ryberg (eds.) - 2023 - Bloomsbury.
    This book addresses the fundamental ethical and legal aspects, penal consequences, and social context arising from a citizen's acceptance of guilt. The focus is upon sentencing people who have pleaded guilty; in short, post-adjudication, rather than issues arising from discussions in the pretrial phase of the criminal process. The vast majority of defendants across all common law jurisdictions plead guilty and as a result receive a reduced sentence. Concessions by a defendant attract more lenient State punishment in all (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  54
    Inscripta in Fronte: Penal Tattooing in Late Antiquity.W. Mark Gustafson - 1997 - Classical Antiquity 16 (1):79-105.
    The origins of tattooing are very ancient, and the modern fascination with the practice serves to remind us that it has been an enduring fixture in human history. Its functions are many and often overlap, but the particular focus here is on the tattoo as an aspect of punishment. Comparative evidence, however, is welcomed whenever it proves useful. This article first marshals and examines the late antique literary evidence extending from North Africa in the third century to Constantinople in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  7
    Sentenced desires: punishing “homosexuals” in annexed Alsace (1940-1945). [REVIEW]Régis Schlagdenhauffen - 2014 - Clio 39:83-104.
    Cet article questionne la fabrique de la décision pénale en temps de guerre et en situation d’annexion. Il s’appuie sur les jugements pour homosexualité rendus par le tribunal de Strasbourg entre 1942 et 1945. Les données statistiques recueillies permettent d’établir que les Alsaciens jugés durant cette période sont majoritairement jeunes et appartiennent aux classes populaires. Ils sont condamnés pour la plupart à de lourdes peines de prison pouvant aller jusqu’à la perpétuité et cela « dans l’intérêt de la préservation du (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  11
    Judge and Punish: The Penal State on Trial.Geoffroy de Lagasnerie - 2018 - Stanford, California: Stanford University Press. Edited by Lara Vergnaud.
    What remains anti-democratic in our criminal justice systems, and where does it come from? Geoffroy de Lagasnerie spent years sitting in on trials, watching as individuals were judged and sentenced for armed robbery, assault, rape, and murder. His experience led to this original reflection on the penal state, power, and violence that identifies a paradox in the way justice is exercised in liberal democracies. In order to pronounce a judgment, a trial must construct an individualizing story of actors and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  24
    Crime, Character, and the Evolution of the Penal Message.Adiel Zimran & Netanel Dagan - forthcoming - Criminal Law and Philosophy:1-22.
    Scholars depict punishment as a moral dialogue between the community and the offender, which addresses both the offender’s crime and character. However, how the penal message evolves vis a vis that crime and character as it passes through the different stages of the criminal process has remained under-theorized. This article, building on communicative theory, explores the interrelation between crime and character along the penal process, from sentencing, through prison, to parole release. We argue that in the penal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Iudicium ex Machinae – The Ethical Challenges of Automated Decision-Making in Criminal Sentencing.Frej Thomsen - 2022 - In Julian Roberts & Jesper Ryberg (eds.), Principled Sentencing and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford University Press.
    Automated decision making for sentencing is the use of a software algorithm to analyse a convicted offender’s case and deliver a sentence. This chapter reviews the moral arguments for and against employing automated decision making for sentencing and finds that its use is in principle morally permissible. Specifically, it argues that well-designed automated decision making for sentencing will better approximate the just sentence than human sentencers. Moreover, it dismisses common concerns about transparency, privacy and bias as unpersuasive or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. ""The" Desert" Model for Sentencing: Its Influence, Prospects, and Alternatives.Andrew von Hirsch - 2007 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 74 (2):413-434.
    The decline of the rehabilitative ethos in sentencing theory in the post_1960's is a story that has been told often , and need not be rehearsed here. Penal treatment programs, once tested for their effectiveness, showed scant success _ or at most, succeeded only in limited categories of cases. Doubts grew also about the fairness of making the severity of a person's sentence depend upon his responsiveness to treatment. As penal rehabilitation diminished in influence, the key question (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Pinkerton Short-Circuits the Model Penal Code.Andrew Ingram - 2019 - Villanova Law Review 64 (1):71-99.
    I show that the Pinkerton rule in conspiracy law is doctrinally and morally flawed. Unlike past critics of the rule, I propose a statutory fix that preserves and reforms it rather than abolishing it entirely. As I will show, this accommodates authors like Neil Katyal who have defended the rule as an important crime fighting tool while also fixing most of the traditional problems with it identified by critics like Wayne LaFave. Pinkerton is a vicarious liability rule that makes conspirators (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The "Desert" Model for Sentencing: Its Influence, Prospects, and Alternatives.Andrew von Hirsch - 2007 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 74:413-434.
    The decline of the rehabilitative ethos in sentencing theory in the post_1960's is a story that has been told often, and need not be rehearsed here. Penal treatment programs, once tested for their effectiveness, showed scant success _ or at most, succeeded only in limited categories of cases. Doubts grew also about the fairness of making the severity of a person's sentence depend upon his responsiveness to treatment. As penal rehabilitation diminished in influence, the key question for (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. The crime-preventive impact of penal sanctions.Anthony Bottoms & Andrew von Hirsch - 2010 - In Peter Cane & Herbert M. Kritzer (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Empirical Legal Research. Oxford University Press.
    This article opens with the consequentialist–deontologist debate, with the former concerned about the relevance of punitive measures against their crime reducing potentials, while the latter highlights punishment as censure of wrongful acts and the proportion of the punishment to the degree of crime. The article briefly discusses the empirical research on the impact of penal sanctions and focuses on three main kinds of empirical research into possible general deterrent effects—namely, association studies, quasi-experimental studies, and contextual and perceptual studies. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  11
    Retributivism and Current Sentencing Practices.Margaret R. Holmgren - 2014 - Criminal Justice Ethics 33 (1):58-69.
    Retributivism Has a Past: Has It a Future? is the first volume of a series to be published by Oxford University Press: Studies in Penal Theory and Philosophy. Clearly the series is off to a fine st...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  6
    Between Redemption and Retribution: Justifying Commutations for Life-without-parole Sentences in California.Doris Schartmueller - 2024 - Criminal Justice Ethics 43 (1):57-83.
    For persons serving life-without-parole (LWOP) sentences in California, a commutation usually offers them the sole glimpse of hope for release from prison. While governors were reluctant to consider any sentence reductions from 1975 to 2016, commutations—including those for LWOP—have become a more frequent occurrence since. Yet, little is still known about how governors have justified reducing a sentence that initially offered no prospect of release from prison. Given the apparent change in practice, themes emerging from the content of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  8
    Justificación de Una dogmática.JuRÍdiCo-PenaL en MéXiCo - 2008 - In Ricardo Franco Guzmán (ed.), Homenaje a Ricardo Franco Guzmán: 50 años de vida académica. México, D.F.: Instituto Nacional de Ciencias Penales.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Dealing with potential terrorists within a censure-based model of sentencing.Alessandro Corda - 2019 - In Antje du Bois-Pedain & Anthony E. Bottoms (eds.), Penal censure: engagements within and beyond desert theory. New York: Hart Publishing.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Ivano caponigro and daphna Heller.Specificational Sentences - 2007 - In Chris Barker & Pauline I. Jacobson (eds.), Direct Compositionality. Oxford University Press. pp. 14--237.
  28. John Lyons.Locative Sentences - forthcoming - Foundations of Language.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Many toys are in box.Existential Sentences - 1971 - Foundations of Language: International Journal of Language and Philosophy 7.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Philip Hugly and Charles Sayward.Null Sentences - 1999 - Iyyun 48:23.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. La boadi.Existential Sentences In Akan - 1971 - Foundations of Language 7:19.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Lisa Green/Aspectual be–type Constructions and Coercion in African American English Yoad Winter/Distributivity and Dependency Instructions for Authors.Pauline Jacobson, Paycheck Pronouns, Bach-Peters Sentences, Inflectional Head, Thomas Ede Zimmermann, Free Choice Disjunction, Epistemic Possibility, Sigrid Beck & Uli Sauerland - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (373).
  33.  1
    The Ethics of Punishment.William Temple & Howard League for Penal Reform - 1930 - Howard League for Penal Reform.
  34. Coercion and the Neurocorrective Offer.Jonathan Pugh - forthcoming - In David Rhys Birks & Thomas Douglas (eds.), reatment for Crime: Philosophical Essays on Neurointerventions in Criminal Justice. Oxford, UK:
    According to what Douglas calls ‘the consent requirement’, neuro-correctives can only permissibly be provided with the valid consent of the offender who will undergo the intervention. Some of those who endorse the consent requirement have claimed that even though the requirement prohibits the imposition of mandatory neurocorrectives on criminal offenders, it may yet be permissible to offer offenders the opportunity to consent to undergoing such an intervention, in return for a reduction to their penal sentence. I call this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  19
    Proportionality in Personal Life.Douglas Husak - 2021 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (3):339-360.
    Efforts to apply the principle of proportionality to criminal sentences are notoriously problematic. But even though they are daunting, only a few legal philosophers believe we should give up trying to do so. Perhaps we can make progress overcoming some of the many legal difficulties by attending to how the principle is applied in non-legal contexts—that is, in contexts I call personal life. Proportionality, I believe, is an attractive principle in penal sentencing because it is an attractive principle in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  12
    Disenfranchisement as Distancing from Offenders?Gustavo A. Beade - 2023 - Criminal Justice Ethics 42 (3):238-257.
    This paper questions the notion that states may be justified in denying certain prisoners the right to vote as a means of distancing themselves from particularly grave wrongs. Christopher Bennett has recently defended prisoner disenfranchisement as a fair and deserved retributive punishment for crimes, and Mary Sigler and Andrew Altman have argued in favor of prisoner disenfranchisement as a civil restriction. All three proponents agree that disenfranchisement should be reserved for those guilty of the most serious offenses. I assert that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  98
    From the Consulting Room to the Court Room? Taking the Clinical Model of Responsibility Without Blame into the Legal Realm.Nicola Lacey & Hanna Pickard - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (1):1-29.
    Within contemporary penal philosophy, the view that punishment can only be justified if the offender is a moral agent who is responsible and hence blameworthy for their offence is one of the few areas on which a consensus prevails. In recent literature, this precept is associated with the retributive tradition, in the modern form of ‘just deserts’. Turning its back on the rehabilitative ideal, this tradition forges a strong association between the justification of punishment, the attribution of responsible agency (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  38.  26
    Trust, Business Ethics and Crime Prevention – Corporate Criminal Liability in Finland.Matti Tolvanen - 2009 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 115 (1):335-358.
    According to the Finnish Penal Code a corporation may be sentenced to a corporate fine if a person who is part of its statutory organ or other management or who exercises actual decision-making authority therein 1) has been an accomplice in an offence or allowed the commission of the offence, or 2) if the care and diligence necessary for the prevention of the offence has not been observed in the operations of the corporation. Criminal liability of legal persons is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. On Predicting Recidivism: Epistemic Risk, Tradeoffs, and Values in Machine Learning.Justin B. Biddle - 2022 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):321-341.
    Recent scholarship in philosophy of science and technology has shown that scientific and technological decision making are laden with values, including values of a social, political, and/or ethical character. This paper examines the role of value judgments in the design of machine-learning systems generally and in recidivism-prediction algorithms specifically. Drawing on work on inductive and epistemic risk, the paper argues that ML systems are value laden in ways similar to human decision making, because the development and design of ML systems (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  40. Punishment, Communication, and Community.R. A. Duff - 2001 - Oup Usa.
    Part of the Studies in Crime and Public Policy series, this book, written by one of the top philosophers of punishment, examines the main trends in penal theorizing over the past three decades. Duff asks what can justify criminal punishment, and then explores the legitimacy of actual practices by examining what would count as adequate justification for them. Duff argues that a "communicative conception of punishment," which he presents as a third way between consequentialist and retributive theories, offers the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  41.  41
    Censure and Sanctions.Andrew Von Hirsch - 1996 - Oxford University Press UK.
    A number of jurisdictions, including England and Wales after their adoption of the 1991 Criminal Justice Act, require that sentences be `proportionate' to the severity of the crime. This book, written by the leading architect of `just deserts' sentencing theory, discusses how sentences may be scaled proportionately to the gravity of the crime. Topics dealt with include how the idea of a penal censure justifies proportionate sentences; how a penalty scale should be `anchored' to reduce overall punishment levels; how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  42. Justice without Retribution: An Epistemic Argument against Retributive Criminal Punishment.Gregg D. Caruso - 2018 - Neuroethics 13 (1):13-28.
    Within the United States, the most prominent justification for criminal punishment is retributivism. This retributivist justification for punishment maintains that punishment of a wrongdoer is justified for the reason that she deserves something bad to happen to her just because she has knowingly done wrong—this could include pain, deprivation, or death. For the retributivist, it is the basic desert attached to the criminal’s immoral action alone that provides the justification for punishment. This means that the retributivist position is not reducible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  43. Punishment, communication and community.Antony Duff - 2002 - In Derek Matravers & Jonathan Pike (eds.), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology. Routledge, in Association with the Open University.
    The question "What can justify criminal punishment ?" becomes especially insistent at times, like our own, of penal crisis, when serious doubts are raised not only about the justice or efficacy of particular modes of punishment, but about the very legitimacy of the whole penal system. Recent theorizing about punishment offers a variety of answers to that question-answers that try to make plausible sense of the idea that punishment is justified as being deserved for past crimes; answers that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  44. Neuro-interventions as Criminal Rehabilitation: An Ethical Review.Jonathan Pugh & Thomas Douglas - 2016 - In Jonathan Jacobs & Jonathan Jackson (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Criminal Justice Ethics. Routledge.
    According to a number of influential views in penal theory, 1 one of the primary goals of the criminal justice system is to rehabilitate offenders. Rehabilitativemeasures are commonly included as a part of a criminal sentence. For example, in some jurisdictions judges may order violent offenders to attend anger management classes or to undergo cognitive behavioural therapy as a part of their sentences. In a limited number of cases, neurointerventions — interventions that exert a direct biological effect on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45. ‘Drugs That Make You Feel Bad’? Remorse-Based Mitigation and Neurointerventions.Jonathan Pugh & Hannah Maslen - 2017 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3):499-522.
    In many jurisdictions, an offender’s remorse is considered to be a relevant factor to take into account in mitigation at sentencing. The growing philosophical interest in the use of neurointerventions in criminal justice raises an important question about such remorse-based mitigation: to what extent should technologically facilitated remorse be honoured such that it is permitted the same penal significance as standard instances of remorse? To motivate this question, we begin by sketching a tripartite account of remorse that distinguishes cognitive, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46.  74
    The Intrusion of Mercy.R. A. Duff - 2007 - Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 4:361-87.
    On the basis of a communicative theory of criminal punishment, I show how mercy has a significant but limited role to play in the criminal law—in particular (although not only) in criminal sentencing. Mercy involves an intrusion into the realm of criminal law of values and concerns that are not themselves part of the perspective of criminal law: a merciful sentencer acts beyond the limits of her legal role, on the basis of moral considerations that conflict with the demands of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  47.  98
    The Practice of Punishment: Towards a Theory of Restorative Justice.Wesley Cragg - 1992 - New York: Routledge.
    This study focuses on the practice of punishment, as it is inflicted by the state. The author's first-hand experience with penal reform, combined with philosophical reflection, has led him to develop a theory of punishment that identifies the principles of sentencing and corrections on which modern correctional systems should be built. This new theory of punishment is built on the view that the central function of the law is to reduce the need to use force in the resolution of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48. Can Neurointerventions Communicate Censure? (And So What If They Can’t?).David Birks - 2018 - In David Birks & Thomas Douglas (eds.), Treatment for Crime: Philosophical Essays on Neurointerventions in Criminal Justice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    According to some philosophers, a necessary condition of morally permissible punishment is that it communicates deserved censure for the offender’s wrongdoing. The author calls this the Communicative Condition of punishment. The chapter considers whether the use of mandatory crime-preventing neurointerventions is compatible with the Communicative Condition. The author argues that it is not. If we accept the Communicative Condition, it follows that it is impermissible to administer mandatory neurointerventions on offenders as punishment. The author then considers whether it is permissible (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  45
    The Intrusion of Mercy.Antony Duff - unknown
    On the basis of a communicative theory of criminal punishment, I show how mercy has a significant but limited role to play in the criminal law—in particular (although not only) in criminal sentencing. Mercy involves an intrusion into the realm of criminal law of values and concerns that are not themselves part of the perspective of criminal law: a merciful sentencer acts beyond the limits of her legal role, on the basis of moral considerations that conflict with the demands of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  19
    Plea Bargaining with Wrong Reasons: Coercive Plea-Offers and Responding to the Wrong Kind of Reason.Benjamin Newman - 2024 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 18 (2):369-393.
    The notion of a defendant submitting a false guilty plea due to the penal incentive offered is not an uncommon phenomenon. While the practice has been legitimised based on the defendant’s voluntary informed consent, it has often been argued that the structure of the plea-bargaining practice is coercive. Such can be the case whenever the plea offer entails a significant sentence differential, discrepancy in the form of punishment (a non-custodial sentence relative to a custodial one), or when (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000