Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Exploring Minds: Modes of Modeling and Simulation in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2021 - Perspectives on Science 29 (4):409-435.
    The aim of this paper is to grasp the relevant distinctions between various ways in which models and simulations in Artificial Intelligence (AI) relate to cognitive phenomena. In order to get a systematic picture, a taxonomy is developed that is based on the coordinates of formal versus material analogies and theory-guided versus pre-theoretic models in science. These distinctions have parallels in the computational versus mimetic aspects and in analytic versus exploratory types of computer simulation. The proposed taxonomy cuts across the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exploring Minds: Modes of Modelling and Simulation in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2021 - Perspectives on Science 29 (4):409-435.
    -/- The aim of this paper is to grasp the relevant distinctions between various ways in which models and simulations in Artificial Intelligence (AI) relate to cognitive phenomena. In order to get a systematic picture, a taxonomy is developed that is based on the coordinates of formal versus material analogies and theory-guided versus pre-theoretic models in science. These distinctions have parallels in the computational versus mimetic aspects and in analytic versus exploratory types of computer simulation. The proposed taxonomy cuts across (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Analogue Models and Universal Machines. Paradigms of Epistemic Transparency in Artificial Intelligence.Hajo Greif - 2022 - Minds and Machines 32 (1):111-133.
    The problem of epistemic opacity in Artificial Intelligence is often characterised as a problem of intransparent algorithms that give rise to intransparent models. However, the degrees of transparency of an AI model should not be taken as an absolute measure of the properties of its algorithms but of the model’s degree of intelligibility to human users. Its epistemically relevant elements are to be specified on various levels above and beyond the computational one. In order to elucidate this claim, I first (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contents of consciousness: A neuropsychological conjecture.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):659-76.
    Drawing on previous models of anxiety, intermediate memory, the positive symptoms of schizophrenia, and goal-directed behaviour, a neuropsychological hypothesis is proposed for the generation of the contents of consciousness. It is suggested that these correspond to the outputs of a comparator that, on a moment-by-moment basis, compares the current state of the organism's perceptual world with a predicted state. An outline is given of the information-processing functions of the comparator system and of the neural systems which mediate them. The hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Rule systems are not dead: Existential quantifiers are harder.Richard E. Grandy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):351-352.
  • Consciousness and its (dis)contents.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):703-722.
    The first claim in the target article was that there is as yet no transparent, causal account of the relations between consciousness and brain-and-behaviour. That claim remains firm. The second claim was that the contents of consciousness consist, psychologically, of the outputs of a comparator system; the third consisted of a description of the brain mechanisms proposed to instantiate the comparator. In order to defend these claims against criticism, it has been necessary to clarify the distinction between consciousness-as-such and the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uncertainty about information.Ian E. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-146.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teleology and agency in speech production.Robert M. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):525-525.
  • Self-ascription of belief and desire.Robert M. Gordon - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):45-46.
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
  • Theories and illusions.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):90-100.
  • Theories and qualities.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):44-45.
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
  • The relation between epistemology and psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1985 - Synthese 64 (1):29-68.
    In the wake of Frege's attack on psychologism and the subsequent influence of Logical Positivism, psychological considerations in philosophy came to be viewed with suspicion. Philosophical questions, especially epistemological ones, were viewed as 'logical' questions, and logic was sharply separated from psychology. Various efforts have been made of late to reconnect epistemology with psychology. But there is little agreement about how such connections should be made, and doubts about the place of psychology within epistemology are still much in evidence. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The psychology of folk psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):15-28.
    The central mission of cognitive science is to reveal the real nature of the mind, however familiar or foreign that nature may be to naive preconceptions. The existence of naive conceptions is also important, however. Prescientific thought and language contain concepts of the mental, and these concepts deserve attention from cognitive science. Just as scientific psychology studies folk physics (McCloskey 1983, Hayes 1985), viz., the common understanding (or misunderstanding) of physical phenomena, so it must study folk psychology, the common understanding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • On some specific models of intentional behavior.Richard M. Golden - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-145.
  • Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):101-108.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is divided into five topics: (1) Which version(s) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competing accounts of belief-task performance.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):43-44.
  • Ambiguities in “the algorithmic level”.Alvin I. Goldman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):484-485.
  • ERP evidence for task modulations on face perceptual processing at different spatial scales.Valérie Goffaux, Boutheina Jemel, Corentin Jacques, Bruno Rossion & Philippe G. Schyns - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (2):313-325.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why Semantic Properties Won’t Earn their Keep.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 1986 - Philosophical Studies 50 (September):223-36.
  • The strategy used to increase the amplitude of the movement varies with the muscle studied.Emile Godaux - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):219-219.
  • Determining the primary problem of visual perception: A Gibsonian response to the correlation' objection.Philip A. Glotzbach - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (1):69-94.
    Fodor & Pylyshyn (1981) criticize J. J. Gibson's ecological account of perception for failing to address what I call the 'correlation problem' in visual perception. That is, they charge that Gibson cannot explain how perceivers learn to correlate detectable properties of the light with perceptible properties of the environment. Furthermore, they identify the correlation problem as a crucial issue for any theory of visual perception, what I call a 'primary problem'—i.e. a problem which plays a definitive role in establishing the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The study of cognition and instructional design: Mutual nurturance.Robert Glaser - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):483-484.
  • Arousal and the disruption of language production processes in schizophrenia.Per F. Gjerde - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):524-524.
  • If a particular strategy is used, what aspects of the movement are controlled?C. C. A. M. Gielen & J. J. Denier van der Gon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):218-219.
  • Species are individuals: Therefore human nature is a metaphysical delusion.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):77-78.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Strategies are a means to an end.C. Ghez & J. Gordon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):216-218.
  • Challenges to the Modularity Thesis Under the Bayesian Brain Models.Nithin George & Meera Mary Sunny - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.
  • A number of questions about a question of number.Alan Garnham - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):350-351.
  • Why study deduction?Kathleen M. Galotti & Lloyd K. Komatsu - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):350-350.
  • Putting sociobiology in its place.Andrew Futterman & Garland E. Allen - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):76-77.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Not the module does memory make – but the network.Joaquin M. Fuster - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):631-633.
    This commentary questions the target articles inferences from a limited set of empirical data to support this model and conceptual scheme. Especially questionable is the attribution of internal representation properties to an assembly of cells in a discrete cortical module firing at a discrete attractor frequency. Alternative inferences are drawn from cortical cooling and cell-firing data that point to the internal representation as a broad and specific cortical network defined by cortico-cortical connectivity. Active memory, it is proposed, consists in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness is for other people.Chris Frith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-683.
    Gray has expanded his account of schizophrenia to explain consciousness as well. His theory explains neither phenomenon adequately because he treats individual minds in isolation. The primary function of consciousness is to permit high level interactions with other conscious beings. The key symptoms of schizophrenia reflect a failure of this mechanism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Addiction and embodiment.Ellen Fridland & Corinde E. Wiers - 2018 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (1):15-42.
    Recent experiments have shown that when individuals with a substance use disorder are confronted with drug-related cues, they exhibit an automatically activated tendency to approach these cues. The strength of the drug approach bias has been associated with clinically relevant measures, such as increased drug craving and relapse, and activations in brain reward areas. Retraining the approach bias by means of cognitive bias modification has been demonstrated to decrease relapse rates in patients with an alcohol use disorder and to reduce (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mental representation of action.Jennifer J. Freyd - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):145-146.
  • The Hebbian paradigm reintegrated: Local reverberations as internal representations.Walter J. Freeman - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):631-631.
    Recurrent excitation is experimentally well documented in cortical populations. It provides for intracortical excitatory biases that linearize negative feedback interactions and induce macroscopic state transitions during perception. The concept of the local neighborhood should be expanded to spatial patterns as the basis for perception, in which large areas of cortex are bound into cooperative behavior with near-silent columns as important as active columns revealed by unit recording.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ghost is in the other eye: The eidetic image is monocular.David Freides - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):295-296.
  • A Thurstonian's reaction to a componential theory of intelligence.John R. Frederiksen - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):590-591.
  • On seeking the mythical fountain of consciousness.Jeffrey Foss - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-682.
    Because consciousness has an organizational, or functional, center, Gray supposes that there must be a corresponding physical center in the brain. He proposes further that since this center generates consciousness, ablating it would eliminate consciousness, while leaving behavior intact. But the center of consciousness is simply the product of the functional linkages among sensory input, memory, inner speech, and so on, and behavior.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searle on what only brains can do.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):431-432.
  • Is the human sentence parsing mechanism an ATN?Janet Dean Fodor & Lyn Frazier - 1980 - Cognition 8 (4):417-459.
  • How direct is visual perception? Some reflections on Gibson's 'ecological approach'.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 9 (2):139-96.
    Examines the theses that the postulation of mental processing is unnecessary to account for our perceptual relationship with the world, see turvey etal. for a criticque.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   288 citations  
  • Auditory hallucinations, inner speech, and the dominant hemisphere.Pierre Flor-Henry - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):523-524.
  • Speed-insensitive and speed-sensitive strategies in multijoint movements.Tamar Flash - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):215-216.
  • Pulses, bursts, and single-joint movements.Martha Flanders - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):215-215.
  • The Social and Cognitive Dynamics of Paradigmatic Change: A Scientometric Approach.Klaus Fischer - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (1):51-96.
    ArgumentKuhnian phases of paradigmatic development correspond to characteristic variations of citation measures. These correlations can in turn be predicted from a simple model of human information processing when applied to the common environments of scientists. By combining a scientometric and a human information processing approach to the history of scientific thought, structures of disciplinary development, and in particular paradigmatic cycles, can be more reliably assessed than before. Consequently, the quantitative historian of science is liberated to some extent from the vagaries (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mental models and informal logic.Alec Fisher - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):349-349.
  • Deductive reasoning: What are taken to be the premises and how are they interpreted?Samuel Fillenbaum - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):348-349.
  • The argument for mental models is unsound.James H. Fetzer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):347-348.