Results for ' Weismann'

(not author) ( search as author name )
72 found
Order:
  1.  6
    Les mauvaises graines. Retentissement des problématiques d'infertilité sur le jeu des identifications croisées parents/enfants.Catherine Weismann-Arcache - 2013 - Dialogue: Families & Couples 199 (1):33-41.
    À partir de psychothérapies de femmes infertiles et de rencontres cliniques avec des enfants issus de la procréation médicale assistée, l’article propose une analyse de l’impact de ces techniques médicales sur les théories sexuelles infantiles, voire familiales. La différence des générations peut être balayée par ce processus de réalisation du désir d’enfant qui devient visible car médicalisé, et le bébé imaginaire devient l’affaire de toute la famille, depuis les grands-parents jusqu’aux enfants déjà nés. Une fillette « œdipienne » interroge ainsi (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  2
    Les mauvaises graines. Retentissement des problématiques d'infertilité sur le jeu des identifications croisées parents/enfants.Catherine Weismann-Arcache - 2013 - Dialogue: Families & Couples 199 (1):33-41.
    À partir de psychothérapies de femmes infertiles et de rencontres cliniques avec des enfants issus de la procréation médicale assistée, l’article propose une analyse de l’impact de ces techniques médicales sur les théories sexuelles infantiles, voire familiales. La différence des générations peut être balayée par ce processus de réalisation du désir d’enfant qui devient visible car médicalisé, et le bébé imaginaire devient l’affaire de toute la famille, depuis les grands-parents jusqu’aux enfants déjà nés. Une fillette « œdipienne » interroge ainsi (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Weismann rules! OK? Epigenetics and the Lamarckian temptation.David Haig - 2007 - Biology and Philosophy 22 (3):415-428.
    August Weismann rejected the inheritance of acquired characters on the grounds that changes to the soma cannot produce the kind of changes to the germ-plasm that would result in the altered character being transmitted to subsequent generations. His intended distinction, between germ-plasm and soma, was closer to the modern distinction between genotype and phenotype than to the modern distinction between germ cells and somatic cells. Recently, systems of epigenetic inheritance have been claimed to make possible the inheritance of acquired (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  4.  7
    Weismann’s Barrier and Crick’s Barrier Still Preclude Two Kinds of Lamarckism.Koen B. Tanghe - 2021 - Biosemiotics 14 (3):675-682.
    In his target article ‘The Illusions of the Modern Synthesis’, Denis Noble argues that the Modern Synthesis is undermined by the major findings of molecular biology. The supposed falsification of Weisman’s Barrier and of standard interpretations of Francis Crick’s Central Dogma has paved the way for Lamarckian forms of inheritance which are prohibited by that theory of evolution. I argue that August Weismann postulated two barriers against two kinds of Lamarckism. However, his second barrier was speculative. It was made (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  33
    August Weismann Embraces the Protozoa.Frederick B. Churchill - 2010 - Journal of the History of Biology 43 (4):767 - 800.
    This paper examines the contents and institutional context of August Weismann's long essay on Amphimixis (1891). Therein he presented detailed discussions of his on-going studies of reduction division and parthenogenesis, but more to the point, he included an elaborate examination of Émile Maupas's two major publications in protozoology. To understand the relevance of this part to the other two, the author briefly reviews highpoints in earlier nineteenth century protozoology and concludes that only in the mid-1870s and 1880s did protozoa (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. August Weismann on Germ-Plasm Variation.Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther - 2001 - Journal of the History of Biology 34 (3):517-555.
    August Weismann is famous for having argued against the inheritance of acquired characters. However, an analysis of his work indicates that Weismann always held that changes in external conditions, acting during development, were the necessary causes of variation in the hereditary material. For much of his career he held that acquired germ-plasm variation was inherited. An irony, which is in tension with much of the standard twentieth-century history of biology, thus exists – Weismann was not a Weismannian. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  7.  33
    Weismann and evolution.Ernst Mayr - 1985 - Journal of the History of Biology 18 (3):295-329.
  8.  31
    August Weismann and a break from tradition.Frederick B. Churchill - 1968 - Journal of the History of Biology 1 (1):91-112.
  9.  85
    Weismann, Wittgenstein and the homunculus fallacy.Harry Smit - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41 (3):263-271.
    A problem that has troubled both neo-Darwinists and neo-Lamarckians is whether instincts involve knowledge. This paper discusses the contributions to this problem of the evolutionary biologist August Weismann and the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein. Weismann discussed an empirical homunculus fallacy: Lamarck’s theory mistakenly presupposes a homunculus in the germ cells. Wittgenstein discussed a conceptual homunculus fallacy which applies to Lamarck’s theory: it is mistaken to suppose that knowledge is stored in the brain or DNA. The upshot of these two (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10.  12
    Hertwig, Weismann, and the Meaning of Reduction Division circa 1890.Frederick B. Churchill - 1970 - Isis 61 (4):429-457.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  11.  37
    Weismann Versus Morgan Revisited: Clashing Interpretations on Animal Regeneration. [REVIEW]Maurizio Esposito - 2013 - Journal of the History of Biology 46 (3):511-541.
    This paper has three principal aims: first, through a detailed analysis of the hypotheses and assumptions underlying Weismann’s and Morgan’s disagreement on the nature of animal regeneration, it seeks to readdress the imbalance in coverage of their discussion, providing, at the same time, a fascinating case-study for those interested in general issues related to controversies in science. Second, contrary to Morgan’s beliefs according to which Weismann employed a speculative and unempirical method of scientific investigation, the article shows that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  34
    August Weismann and Theoretical Biology.Manfred D. Laubichler & Hans-Jörg Rheinberger - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (2):195-198.
  13.  50
    August Weismann's Theory of the Germ-Plasm and the Problem of Unconceived Alternatives.P. Kyle Stanford - 2005 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 27 (2):163 - 199.
    I have argued elsewhere that scientific realism is most significantly challenged neither by traditional arguments from underdetermination of theories by the evidence, nor by the traditional pessimistic induction, but by a rather different historical pattern: our repeated failure to conceive of alternatives to extant scientific theories, even when those alternatives were both (1) well-confirmed by the evidence available at the time and (2) sufficiently scientifically serious as to be later embraced by actual scientific communities. Here I use August Weismann's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  25
    In Weismann's Footsteps: The Cyto-Rebellion of CD Darlington.Oren Harman - 2008 - In Oren Harman & Michael Dietrich (eds.), Rebels, Mavericks, and Heretics in Biology. Yale University Press. pp. 103.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  42
    Dr. Weismann on Heredity and Progress.C. Lloyd Morgan - 1893 - The Monist 4 (1):20-30.
  16.  28
    Weismann, Wittgenstein and the homunculus fallacy.Harry Smit - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41 (3):263-271.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17. Dr. Weismann on Heredity and Progress.C. L. Morgan - 1894 - Philosophical Review 3:238.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  6
    Dr. Weismann on Heredity and Progress.C. Lloyd Morgan - 1893 - The Monist 4 (1):20-30.
  19.  10
    Dr. Weismann on Heredity and Progress.C. Lloyd Morgan - 1893 - The Monist 4 (1):20-30.
  20.  71
    Werner Weismann: Kirche und Schauspiele. Die Schauspiele im Urteil der lateinischen Kirchenväter unter besonderer Berücksichtigung von Augustin, in: Sammlung CASSICIACUM, hrgg. von A. Kunzelmann OSA und A. Zumkeller OSA, Band XXVII. Augustinus-Verlag Würzburg 1972, 243 pp. [REVIEW]Hans G. Klemm - 1973 - Zeitschrift für Religions- Und Geistesgeschichte 25 (3):277-278.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  34
    The Reactions on Hugo de Vries's "Intracellular Pangenesis"; The Discussion with August Weismann.Ida H. Stamhuis - 2003 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (1):119-152.
    In 1889 Hugo de Vries published " Intracellular Pangenesis " in which he formulated his ideas on heredity. The high expectations of the impression these ideas would make did not come true and publication was negated or reviewed critically. From the reactions of his Dutch colleagues and the discussion with the famous German zoologist August Weismann we conclude that the assertion that each cell contains all hereditary material was controversial and even more the claim that characters are inherited independently (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  24
    Images of cell trees, cell lines, and cell fates: the legacy of Ernst Haeckel and August Weismann in stem cell research.Dröscher Ariane - 2014 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 36 (2):157-186.
    Stem cells did not become a proper research object until the 1960 s. Yet the term and the basic mind-set—namely the conception of single undifferentiated cells, be they embryonic or adult, as the basic units responsible for a directed process of development, differentiation and increasing specialisation—were already in place at the end of the nineteenth century and then transmitted on a non-linear path in the form of tropes and diagrams. Ernst Haeckel and August Weismann played a special role in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  14
    Of germ-plasm and zymoplasm: August Weismann, Carlo Emery and the debate about the transmission of acquired characteristics.Ariane Dröscher - 2015 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 36 (3):394-403.
    In this essay I discuss the contents and the context of Italian zoologist and entomologist Carlo Emery’s discussion of the germ-plasm theory. August Weismann considered him one of his very few creditable supporters, and encouraged him to publish his theoretical reflections. In his Gedanken zur Descendenz- und Vererbungstheorie, which appeared between 1893 and 1903 as a series of five essays in the journal Biologisches Zentralblatt, Emery developed a very personal account, applying the concept of determinants to problems like atavism, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  7
    The discussion between Spencer and Weismann.Henry F. Osborn - 1894 - Psychological Review 1 (3):312-315.
  25.  61
    ¿Desarrollo progresivo de la ciencia sin continuidad referencial? Acerca del realismo de Psillos y la teoría del germoplasma de Weismann.Mariana Córdoba - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (3):335-348.
    In this paper I argue for the idea that, throughout the history of science, there are some cases of theory change that would show how science develops with no referential continuity. For this purpose, I analyze Psillos’ proposal of a theory of reference used to account for referential continuity in conceptual transitions. This kind of continuity is requested by Psillos —as by other philosophers— in his defense of scientific realism. By means of a historical case, the theory of germplasm of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  12
    Frederick B. Churchill. August Weismann: Development, Heredity, and Evolution. xii + 700 pp., illus., app., index. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2015. $49.95 . ISBN 9780674736894. [REVIEW]Manfred D. Laubichler - 2019 - Isis 110 (3):620-621.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. La nouvelle theorie de l'heredite de Weismann.Y. Delage - 1893 - Philosophical Review 2:622.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  63
    El empleo de retórica en la controversia entre Weismann y Spencer acerca de la selección natural y el efecto de uso y desuso.Roberto de Andrade Martins - 2008 - In Roberto de Andrade Martins, Cibelle Celestino Silva, Juliana Mesquita Hidalgo Ferreira & Lilian Al-Chueyr Pereira Martins (eds.), Filosofia E História da Ciência no Cone Sul. Seleção de Trabalhos do 5o Encontro. Associação de Filosofia e História da Ciência do Cone Sul, AFHIC. pp. 533-539.
  29.  34
    The Origins of Species: The Debate between August Weismann and Moritz Wagner. [REVIEW]Charlotte Weissman - 2010 - Journal of the History of Biology 43 (4):727 - 766.
    Weismann's ideas on species transmutation were first expressed in his famous debate with Moritz Wagner on the mechanism of speciation. Wagner suggested that the isolation of a colony from its original source is a preliminary and necessary factor for speciation. Weismann accepted a secondary, facilitating role for isolation, but argued that natural and sexual selection are the primary driving forces of species transmutation, and are always necessary and often sufficient causes for its occurrence. The debate with Wagner, which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  21
    On the Legitimacy of the Darwinian Theory – August Weismann's First Creed.Charlotte Weissman - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (1):173-179.
    ArgumentIn his inaugural lecture, “On the Legitimacy of the Darwinian Theory,” August Weismann followed closely in Darwin's footsteps, but provided at the same time an outline of the essentials of his future theory of heredity, development, variation, and speciation. This was Weismann's first support of the evolutionary theory, and it shows his commitment to natural selection as the mechanism of evolution. For Weismann, “Darwin's Theory” meant natural selection. Natural selection, and more generally selectionism, became Weismann's major (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  16
    ¿Desarrollo progresivo de la ciencia sin continuidad referencial? Acerca del realismo de Psillos y la teoría del germoplasma de Weismann[REVIEW]Mariana Córdoba - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (3):335-348.
    In this paper I argue for the idea that, throughout the history of science, there are some cases of theory change that would show how science develops with no referential continuity. For this purpose, I analyze Psillos’ proposal of a theory of reference used to account for referential continuity in conceptual transitions. This kind of continuity is requested by Psillos —as by other philosophers— in his defense of scientific realism. By means of a historical case, the theory of germplasm of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  89
    From DNA- to NA-centrism and the conditions for gene-centrism revisited.Alexis De Tiège, Koen Tanghe, Johan Braeckman & Yves Van de Peer - 2014 - Biology and Philosophy 29 (1):55-69.
    First the ‘Weismann barrier’ and later on Francis Crick’s ‘central dogma’ of molecular biology nourished the gene-centric paradigm of life, i.e., the conception of the gene/genome as a ‘central source’ from which hereditary specificity unidirectionally flows or radiates into cellular biochemistry and development. Today, due to advances in molecular genetics and epigenetics, such as the discovery of complex post-genomic and epigenetic processes in which genes are causally integrated, many theorists argue that a gene-centric conception of the organism has become (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  21
    Sex, Death, and Evolution in Proto- and Metazoa, 1876–1913.A. J. Lustig - 2000 - Journal of the History of Biology 33 (2):221 - 246.
    In the period 1875-1920, a debate about the generality and applicability of evolutionary theory to all organisms was motivated by work on unicellular ciliates like Paramecium because of their peculiar nuclear dualism and life cycles. The French cytologist Emile Maupas and the German zoologist August Weismann argued in the 1880s about the evolutionary origins and functions of sex (which in the ciliates is not linked to reproduction), and death (which appeared to be the inevitable fate of lineages denied sexual (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  10
    Formando y deformando conceptos científicos: El caso de la herencia de caracteres adquiridos.Susana Gisela Lamas - 2023 - Filosofia E História da Biologia 18 (2):243-260.
    Este trabajo muestra cómo una modificación en el sentido del término caracter adquirido llevó a rechazar la hipótesis de la herencia de esos caracteres. Se considerará el ejemplo del experimento llevado a cabo por Weismann que fue tomado como un caso paradigmático en los libros de textos y en la bibliografía especializada para refutar esa hipótesis. Ese diseño experimental fue aceptado por la comunidad como una refutación, a pesar de que los caracteres a los que hacía referencia no cumplían (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  42
    The Development of Francis Galton's Ideas on the Mechanism of Heredity.Michael Bulmer - 1999 - Journal of the History of Biology 32 (2):263 - 292.
    Galton greeted Darwin's theory of pangenesis with enthusiasm, and tried to test the assumption that the hereditary particles circulate in the blood by transfusion experiments on rabbits. The failure of these experiments led him to reject this assumption, and in the 1870s he developed an alternative theory of heredity, which incorporated those parts of Darwin's theory that did not involve the transportation of hereditary particles throughout the system. He supposed that the fertilized ovum contains a large number of hereditary elements, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  36. Disentangling life: Darwin, selectionism, and the postgenomic return of the environment.Maurizio Meloni - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 62:10-19.
    In this paper, I analyze the disruptive impact of Darwinian selectionism for the century-long tradition in which the environment had a direct causative role in shaping an organism’s traits. In the case of humans, the surrounding environment often determined not only the physical, but also the mental and moral features of individuals and whole populations. With its apparatus of indirect effects, random variations, and a much less harmonious view of nature and adaptation, Darwinian selectionism severed the deep imbrication of organism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  11
    Soma to germline inheritance of extrachromosomal genetic information via a LINE‐1 reverse transcriptase‐based mechanism.Corrado Spadafora - 2016 - Bioessays 38 (8):726-733.
    Mature spermatozoa are permeable to foreign DNA and RNA molecules. Here I propose a model, whereby extrachromosomal genetic information, mostly encoded in the form of RNA in somatic cells, can cross the Weismann barrier and reach epididymal spermatozoa. LINE‐1 retrotransposon‐derived reverse transcriptase (RT) can play key roles in the process by expanding the RNA‐encoded information. Retrotransposon‐encoded RT is stored in mature gametes, is highly expressed in early embryos and undifferentiated cells, and becomes downregulated in differentiated cells. In turn, RT (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  38. Of Mice and Men: Evolution and the Socialist Utopia. William Morris, H.G. Wells, and George Bernard Shaw. [REVIEW]Piers J. Hale - 2010 - Journal of the History of Biology 43 (1):17 - 66.
    During the British socialist revival of the 1880s competing theories of evolution were central to disagreements about strategy for social change. In News from Nowhere (1891), William Morris had portrayed socialism as the result of Lamarckian processes, and imagined a non-Malthusian future. H.G. Wells, an enthusiastic admirer of Morris in the early days of the movement, became disillusioned as a result of the Malthusianism he learnt from Huxley and his subsequent rejection of Lamarckism in light of Weismann's experiments on (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  36
    Avoiding bad genes: oxidatively damaged DNA in germ line and mate choice.Alberto Velando, Roxana Torres & Carlos Alonso-Alvarez - 2008 - Bioessays 30 (11-12):1212-1219.
    August Weismann proposed that genetic changes in somatic cells cannot pass to germ cells and hence to next generations. Nevertheless, evidence is accumulating that some environmental effects can promote heritable changes in the DNA of germ cells, which implies that some somatic influence on germ line is possible. This influence is mostly detrimental and related to the presence of oxidative stress, which induces mutations and epigenetic changes. This effect should be stronger in males due to the particular characteristics of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  12
    Neither Dogmas nor Barriers are Absolute.Denis Noble - 2022 - Biosemiotics 15 (1):57-60.
    The Weismann Barrier and the Central Dogma do not protect the assumptions of The Modern Synthesis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  16
    Lamarckian-Darwinian reorientation.T. H. Howells - 1947 - Psychological Review 54 (1):24-40.
    Weismann's famous test of inheritance assumes that inherited traits will persist in the absence of the environment that first produced them; while, on the other hand, environmental traits are more transitory. The purpose of this paper is to show that this Weismannian criterion is inconsistent and equivocal, and should, therefore, be recognized as one of the obsolete dogmas of heredity. Equivocal interpretation of relevant experiments is possible. Failure to distinguish active from passive environmental changes has been responsible for much (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  23
    Human progress by human effort: neo-Darwinism, social heredity, and the professionalization of the American social sciences, 1889–1925.Emilie J. Raymer - 2018 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 40 (4):63.
    Prior to August Weismann’s 1889 germ-plasm theory, social reformers believed that humans could inherit the effects of a salubrious environment and, by passing environmentally-induced modifications to their offspring, achieve continuous progress. Weismann’s theory disrupted this logic and caused many to fear that they had little control over human development. As numerous historians have observed, this contributed to the birth of the eugenics movement. However, through an examination of the work of social scientists Lester Frank Ward, Richard T. Ely, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  38
    The Illusions of the Modern Synthesis.Denis Noble - forthcoming - Biosemiotics:1-20.
    The Modern Synthesis has dominated biology for 80 years. It was formulated in 1942, a decade before the major achievements of molecular biology, including the Double Helix and the Central Dogma. When first formulated in the 1950s these discoveries and concepts seemed initially to completely justify the central genetic assumptions of the Modern Synthesis. The Double Helix provided the basis for highly accurate DNA replication, while the Central Dogma was viewed as supporting the Weismann Barrier, so excluding the inheritance (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  44. Epiphenomenalism - the do's and the don 'ts'.Lawrence A. Shapiro & Elliott Sober - 2007 - In G. Wolters & Peter K. Machamer (eds.), Thinking About Causes: From Greek Philosophy to Modern physics. University of Pittsburgh Press. pp. 235-264.
    When philosophers defend epiphenomenalist doctrines, they often do so by way of a priori arguments. Here we suggest an empirical approach that is modeled on August Weismann’s experimental arguments against the inheritance of acquired characters. This conception of how epiphenomenalism ought to be developed helps clarify some mistakes in two recent epiphenomenalist positions – Jaegwon Kim’s (1993) arguments against mental causation, and the arguments developed by Walsh (2000), Walsh, Lewens, and Ariew (2002), and Matthen and Ariew (2002) that natural (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  45. Exceeding our grasp: science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives.P. Kyle Stanford - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The incredible achievements of modern scientific theories lead most of us to embrace scientific realism: the view that our best theories offer us at least roughly accurate descriptions of otherwise inaccessible parts of the world like genes, atoms, and the big bang. In Exceeding Our Grasp, Stanford argues that careful attention to the history of scientific investigation invites a challenge to this view that is not well represented in contemporary debates about the nature of the scientific enterprise. The historical record (...)
  46.  83
    The expanded evolutionary synthesis—a response to Godfrey-Smith, Haig, and west-Eberhard.Eva Jablonka & Marion J. Lamb - 2007 - Biology and Philosophy 22 (3):453-472.
    In responding to three reviews of Evolution in Four Dimensions (Jablonka and Lamb, 2005, MIT Press), we briefly consider the historical background to the present genecentred view of evolution, especially the way in which Weismann’s theories have influenced it, and discuss the origins of the notion of epigenetic inheritance. We reaffirm our belief that all types of hereditary information—genetic, epigenetic, behavioural and cultural—have contributed to evolutionary change, and outline recent evidence, mainly from epigenetic studies, that suggests that non-DNA heritable (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  40
    Mendel and the Path to Genetics: Portraying Science as a Social Process.Kostas Kampourakis - 2013 - Science & Education 22 (2):293-324.
    Textbook descriptions of the foundations of Genetics give the impression that besides Mendel’s no other research on heredity took place during the nineteenth century. However, the publication of the Origin of Species in 1859, and the criticism that it received, placed the study of heredity at the centre of biological thought. Consequently, Herbert Spencer, Charles Darwin himself, Francis Galton, William Keith Brooks, Carl von Nägeli, August Weismann, and Hugo de Vries attempted to develop theories of heredity under an evolutionary (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  48. Whatever Happened to Reversion?Charles H. Pence - 2022 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 92 (C):97-108.
    The idea of ‘reversion’ or ‘atavism’ has a peculiar history. For many authors in the latenineteenth and early-twentieth centuries – including Darwin, Galton, Pearson, Weismann, and Spencer, among others – reversion was one of the central phenomena which a theory of heredity ought to explain. By only a few decades later, however, Fisher and others could look back upon reversion as a historical curiosity, a non-problem, or even an impediment to clear theorizing. I explore various reasons that reversion might (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  22
    Between Social and Biological Heredity: Cope and Baldwin on Evolution, Inheritance, and Mind.David Ceccarelli - 2019 - Journal of the History of Biology 52 (1):161-194.
    In the years of the post-Darwinian debate, many American naturalists invoked the name of Lamarck to signal their belief in a purposive and anti-Darwinian view of evolution. Yet Weismann’s theory of germ-plasm continuity undermined the shared tenet of the neo-Lamarckian theories as well as the idea of the interchangeability between biological and social heredity. Edward Drinker Cope, the leader of the so-called “American School,” defended his neo-Lamarckian philosophy against every attempt to redefine the relationship between behavior, development, and heredity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50. The concept of information in biology.John Maynard Smith - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (2):177-194.
    The use of informational terms is widespread in molecular and developmental biology. The usage dates back to Weismann. In both protein synthesis and in later development, genes are symbols, in that there is no necessary connection between their form (sequence) and their effects. The sequence of a gene has been determined, by past natural selection, because of the effects it produces. In biology, the use of informational terms implies intentionality, in that both the form of the signal, and the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
1 — 50 / 72