Results for 'J. Lenman'

961 found
Order:
  1.  19
    Preferences in their Place.J. Lenman - 2000 - Environmental Values 9 (4):431-451.
    In at least some of their forms, Cost-Benefit techniques for the evaluation of environmental projects and policies treat the preferences of citizens as the sole determinants of the value of outcomes. There are two salient ways in which this supposition might be defended. The first is metaethical and appeals to considerations about how we must understand talk of environmental and other values. The second is political and appeals to considerations about democratic legitimacy and the proper aims of public policy. Metaethical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2. Baier, K.-The Rational and the Moral Order.J. Lenman - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38:268-268.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. HOOKER, B.-Ideal Code, Real World.J. Lenman - 2003 - Philosophical Books 44 (2):181-182.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Schneewind, JB (ed.)-Reason, Ethics and Society.J. Lenman - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38:268-271.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  88
    Review: Reasons and Purposes: Human Rationality and the Teleological Explanation of Action. [REVIEW]J. Lenman - 2007 - Mind 116 (463):776-778.
  6. Utilitarianism and obviousness.James Lenman - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (3):322-325.
    This article seeks to diagnose a serious defect in a highly influential supposed counterexample to utilitarianism: Bernard Williams's case of Jim and the Indians. Discussing this, Williams argues that, according to utilitarianism, it is obviously right to say that Jim should kill an Indian. But as this is not obviously right, Williams takes the example to furnish a forceful counterexample to utilitarianism. I note here that the force of the supposed counterexample is in fact very doubtful as the utilitarian can (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  26
    Intuition, Theory and Anti‐Theory in Ethics Sophie Grace Chappell , 2015 Oxford, Oxford University Press ix + 230 pp, £40.00. [REVIEW]A. J. Walsh - 2016 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 33 (4):467-469.
    Since the publication of Jonathan Dancy's 'Moral Reasons' in 1991, many English speaking ethicists have been especially interested in the role of abstract theory in moral life and the extent to which principles analogous to those employed in the hard sciences like physics are central to the development of ethical knowledge. Unlike earlier generations of philosophers who had, on the whole, accepted that principles had an integral role in the life of a morally serious person, contemporary ethicists are largely divided (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  88
    Review of J. Lenman & Y. Shemmer's (eds.) Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. [REVIEW]Jussi Suikkanen - 2013 - Ethics 123 (4):763-768.
    This is a short review of James Lenman and Yonatan Shemmer's (eds.) collection of articles Constructivism in Practical Philosophy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Self and Future Generations. An Intercultural Conversation (J. Lenman).T. -C. Kim & R. Harrison - 2002 - Philosophical Books 43 (1):62-63.
  10.  40
    Christine M. Korsgaard: Creating the Kingdom of Ends.James Lenman - 1998 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (4):487-488.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   165 citations  
  11.  62
    I—James Lenman: What is Moral Inquiry?James Lenman - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):63-81.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12.  77
    I—James Lenman: What is Moral Inquiry?James Lenman - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):63-81.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13.  30
    Disciplined Syntacticism and Moral Expressivism.James Lenman - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):32-57.
    Moral Expressivists typically concede that, in someminimalsense, moral sentences are truth‐apt but claim that in some morerobustsense they are not. TheImmodest Disciplined Syntacticist, a species of minimalist about truth, raises a doubt as to whether this contrast can be made out. I here address this challenge by motivating and describing a distinction betweenreduciblyandirreduciblytruth‐apt sentences. In the light of this distinction the Disciplined Syntacticist must either adopt a moremodestversion of his theory, friendlier to Expressivism, or substantially modify it, abandoning one of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  14. Consequentialism and Cluelessness.James Lenman - 2000 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (4):342-370.
  15.  54
    Michael Smith: The Moral Problem. [REVIEW]James Lenman - 1994 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1):125-126.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   497 citations  
  16.  98
    Expressivism and epistemology: What is moral inquiry?James Lenman - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):63–81.
  17.  40
    Immortality.James Lenman - 1995 - Cogito 9 (2):164-169.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Contractualism and risk imposition.James Lenman - 2008 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 7 (1):99-122.
    The article investigates the resources of contractualist moral theory to make sense of the ethics of risk imposition. In some ways, contractualism seems well placed to explain how it can be reasonable to accept exposure to risk of harms whose direct imposition would not be acceptable. However, there are difficulties getting clear about what directness comes to here, especially given the difficulty of adequately motivating traditional views that assign ethical significance to what the agent intends as opposed to merely foreseeing. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  19. Publicity and Common Commitment to Believe.J. R. G. Williams - 2021 - Erkenntnis 88 (3):1059-1080.
    Information can be public among a group. Whether or not information is public matters, for example, for accounts of interdependent rational choice, of communication, and of joint intention. A standard analysis of public information identifies it with (some variant of) common belief. The latter notion is stipulatively defined as an infinite conjunction: for p to be commonly believed is for it to believed by all members of a group, for all members to believe that all members believe it, and so (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Compatibilism and contractualism: The possibility of moral responsibility.James Lenman - 2006 - Ethics 117 (1):7-31.
  21. Objectual understanding, factivity and belief.J. Adam Carter & Emma C. Gordon - 2016 - In Martin Grajner & Pedro Schmechtig (eds.), Epistemic Reasons, Norms and Goals. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 423-442.
    Should we regard Jennifer Lackey’s ‘Creationist Teacher’ as understanding evolution, even though she does not, given her religious convictions, believe its central claims? We think this question raises a range of important and unexplored questions about the relationship between understanding, factivity and belief. Our aim will be to diagnose this case in a principled way, and in doing so, to make some progress toward appreciating what objectual understanding—i.e., understanding a subject matter or body of information—demands of us. Here is the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22. Disciplined syntacticism and moral expressivism.James Lenman - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (1):32–57.
    Moral Expressivists typically concede that, in some minimal sense, moral sentences are truth-apt but claim that in some more robust sense they are not. The Immodest Disciplined Syntacticist, a species of minimalist about truth, raises a doubt as to whether this contrast can be made out. I here address this challenge by motivating and describing a distinction between reducibly and irreducibly truth-apt sentences. In the light of this distinction the Disciplined Syntacticist must either adopt a more modest version of his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  23. Moral naturalism.Jimmy Lenman - manuscript
    While "moral naturalism" is sometimes used to refer to any approach to metaethics intended to cohere with naturalism in metaphysics more generally, the label is more usually reserved for naturalistic forms of moral realism according to which there are objective moral facts and properties and these moral facts and properties are natural facts and properties. Views of this kind appeal to many as combining the advantages of naturalism and realism but have seemed to many others to do inadequate justice to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  24. Michael Smith and the Daleks: Reason, Morality, and Contingency.James Lenman - 1999 - Utilitas 11 (2):164-177.
    Smith has defended the rationalist's conceptual claim that moral requirements are categorical requirements of reason, arguing that no status short of this would make sense of our taking these requirements as seriously as we do. Against this I argue that Smith has failed to show either that our moral commitments would be undermined by possessing only an internal, contextual justification or that they need presuppose any expectation that rational agents must converge on their acceptance. His claim that this rationalistic understanding (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25. Against moral fictionalism.James Lenman - 2008 - Philosophical Books 49 (1):23-32.
  26.  98
    Ethics Without Errors.James Lenman - 2013 - Ratio 26 (4):391-409.
    I argue against the claim that we should adopt a moral error theory. The intelligibility of our moral practice need offer no questionable metaphysical hostages to fortune. The two most credible policy recommendations that might follow from moral error theory, abolitionism and prescriptive fictionalism, are not very credible.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  27. The externalist and the amoralist.James Lenman - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (3-4):441-457.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  28.  43
    Functions of Thought and the Synthesis of Intuitions.J. Michael Young - 1992 - In Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Kant. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 3--101.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  29. Humean Constructivism in Moral Theory.James Lenman - 2010 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume 5. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  30. Humean Constructivism in Moral Theory.James Lenman - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 5.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  31.  81
    Gibbardian Humility: Moral Fallibility and Moral Smugness.James Lenman - 2014 - Journal of Value Inquiry 48 (2):235-245.
    Those whose Way is not the same cannot take counsel together.Confucius, Analects XV, 40Quasi-Realism and Fundamental Disagreement: Egan’s ProblemI believe that it is wrong to open your boiled egg at the big end. You believe that it is not wrong to open your egg at the big end. We are at an impasse. The impasse might not be deep. One of us might just be wrong on some matter of prosaic nonnormative fact. But perhaps that is not the case. Even (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  12
    Naturalism Without Tears.James Lenman - 2009 - Ratio (Misc.) 22 (1):1-18.
    Parfit argues that naturalistic theories that seek to understand normative concepts either as simply descriptive of certain natural facts about our desires or as expressive of our desires commit us to a bleak normative nihilism whereby nothing matters. I here defend such naturalism, in particular its expressivist variety, against this charge. It is true that such views commit us to there being no reasons as Parfit understands them. But for Parfit to suppose that equivalent to there being no reasons leaves (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. Constructivism in Practical Philosophy.James Lenman & Yonatan Shemmer (eds.) - 2012 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    This volume presents twelve original papers on the idea that moral objectivity is to be understood in terms of a suitably constructed social point of view that all can accept.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34. Expressivism and constructivism.James Lenman - 2012 - In James Lenman & Yonatan Shemmer (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  35. On becoming extinct.James Lenman - 2002 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (3):253–269.
    From an impersonal, timeless perspective it is hard to identify good reasons why it should matter that human extinction comes later rather than sooner, particularly if we accept that it does not matter how many human beings there are. We cannot appeal to the natural narrative shape of human history for there is no such thing. We have more local and particular concerns to which we can better appeal but only if an impersonal, timeless perspective is abandoned: only from a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  36. Belief, Desire and Motivation: An Essay in Quasi-Hydraulics.James Lenman - 1996 - American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (3):291-301.
    My concern here is with the Humean claim that no purely cognitive state could, in combination with appropriate other beliefs, but with nothing else, originate a process of rational motivation. The starting point of such motivation must always include some other element: a desire. Let's call this claim, following David McNaughton the belief-desire theory, or BDT for short. The theory is widely believed but intensely controversial. I argue here that it is true.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  37. The Saucer of mud, The Kudzu vine and the uxorious cheetah: Against neo-Aristotelian naturalism in metaethics.James Lenman - 2005 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 1 (2):37-50.
    Let me say something, to begin with, about wanting weird stuff. Stuff like saucers of mud. The example, famously, is from Anscombe’s Intention (Anscombe Anscombe 957)) where she is, in effect, defending a version of the old scholastic maxim, Omne appetitum appetitur sub specie boni. If your Latin is rusty like mine, what that says is just that every appetite – for better congruence with modern discussions, let’s say every desire – desires under the aspect of the good, or in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38.  64
    Jeanette Kennett, Agency and Responsibility: A Common-sense Moral Psychology, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2001, pp. viii + 229. [REVIEW]James Lenman - 2003 - Utilitas 15 (3):380.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  33
    An Ecumenical Matter?James Lenman - 2019 - Philosophical Quarterly 69 (274):175-186.
    Ridge defends a form of hybrid expressivism where normative judgements are constituted by two elements, normative perspectives and representational beliefs that invoke standards our normative perspectives determine. He thinks this view will enable him to ‘offload logical complexity’ onto the latter, representational components of our judgements, thereby taming the Frege-Geach Problem and conferring a dialectical advantage over non-hybrid, ‘pure’ forms of expressivism. But this will only work if our normative perspectives are themselves consistent in ways that are resistant to such (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  49
    The Place of Protagoras in Athenian Public Life (460–415 B.C.).J. S. Morrison - 1941 - Classical Quarterly 35 (1-2):1-.
    Protagoras, of all the ancient philosophers, has perhaps attracted the most interest in modern times. His saying ‘Man is the measure of all things’ caused Schiller to adopt him as the patron of the Oxford pragmatists, and has generally earned him the title of the first humanist. Yet the exact delineation of his philosophcal position remains a baffling task. Neumann, writing on Die Problematik des ‘Homo-mensura’ Satzes in 1938,2 concludes that no certainty whatever can be reached on the meaning of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Reasons for action: Justification vs. explanation.James Lenman - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Modern philosophical literature distinguishes between explanatory reasons and justifying reasons. The former are reasons we appeal to in attempting to explain actions and attitudes. The latter are reasons we appeal to in attempting to justify them.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  42. Noncognitivism and wishfulness.James Lenman - 2003 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6 (3):265-274.
    It has recently been argued by Cian Dorr that if noncognitivism is true, inferences to factual conclusions from premises at least one of which is moral must be condemned as irrational. For, given a noncognitivist understanding of what it is to accept such premises, such reasoning would be wishful thinking: irrationally revising our views about the world to make them cohere with our desires and feelings. This he takes to be a reductio of noncognitivism. I argue that no compelling case (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  43. Naturalism without tears.James Lenman - 2009 - Ratio 22 (1):1-18.
    Parfit argues that naturalistic theories that seek to understand normative concepts either as simply descriptive of certain natural facts about our desires or as expressive of our desires commit us to a bleak normative nihilism whereby nothing matters. I here defend such naturalism, in particular its expressivist variety, against this charge. It is true that such views commit us to there being no reasons as Parfit understands them. But for Parfit to suppose that equivalent to there being no reasons leaves (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44. Introduction.James Lenman & Yonatan Shemmer - 1977 - In James Lenman & Yonatan Shemmer (eds.), Constructivism in Practical Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  3
    Ethics without errors.James Lenman - 2014 - In Bart Streumer (ed.), Irrealism in Ethics. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 41–59.
    I argue against the claim that we should adopt a moral error theory. The intelligibility of our moral practice need offer no questionable metaphysical hostages to fortune. The two most credible policy recommendations that might follow from moral error theory, abolitionism and prescriptive fictionalism, are not very credible.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  96
    Moral Deviants and Amoral Saints: A Dilemma for Moral Externalism.James Lenman - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (2):223-240.
  47.  4
    Soft-Finished Textiles In Roman Britain.J. P. Wild - 1967 - Classical Quarterly 17 (1):133-135.
    The achievements of the textile industry in Roman Britain are often underestimated as a result of the meagreness of our available evidence. The Edict on maximum prices issued by Diocletian in A.D. 301 shows that British capes commanded high prices on the markets of the Empire, and that in the late third century A.D. British rugs were the best in the world. In view of the competition from the traditional centres of rug manufacture in the East, this is an astonishing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  2
    The Textile Term Scutulatus.J. P. Wild - 1964 - Classical Quarterly 14 (2):263-266.
    The received translation and interpretation of many of the technical terms current in the textile industry of the Roman Empire are inaccurate, because lexicographers have either fought shy of being precise, or have thought that they recognized in the ancient world technical processes which originated at a much later date. The evidence is often equivocal or insufficient, but may still yield details that have been overlooked. The textile expression scutulatus, to take an example, deserves more attention than Blümner has devoted (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  57
    Achieving objectivity.James Lenman - 2009 - Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1):293-304.
  50.  48
    Finding beauty.James Lenman - 1994 - Journal of Value Inquiry 28 (2):245-256.
1 — 50 / 961