Results for 'David Zachariah Flanagin'

967 found
Order:
  1.  3
    Seek and Ye Shall Find: The Assumptions of Biblical Exegesis.David Zachariah Flanagin - 2019 - Listening 54 (1):5-17.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Tyrannicide and the question of (il)licit violence in the fifteenth century.David Zachariah Flanagin - 2019 - In Gerald Christianson & Thomas M. Izbicki (eds.), Nicholas of Cusa and times of transition: essays in honor of Gerald Christianson. Boston: Brill.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  51
    Nemesius: On the Nature of Man. Translated with introduction and notes by R. W. Sharples and P. J. van der Eijk and The Life of Severus by Zachariah of Mutilene. Translated with Introduction by Lena Ambjörn. [REVIEW]David Meconi - 2011 - Heythrop Journal 52 (3):462-462.
  4.  11
    Interdisciplinary Lessons Learned While Researching Fake News.Char Sample, Michael J. Jensen, Keith Scott, John McAlaney, Steve Fitchpatrick, Amanda Brockinton, David Ormrod & Amy Ormrod - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11:537612.
    The misleading and propagandistic tendencies in American news reporting have been a part of public discussion from its earliest days as a republic (Innis, 2007;Sheppard, 2007). “Fake news” is hardly new (McKernon, 1925), and the term has been applied to a variety of distinct phenomenon ranging from satire to news, which one may find disagreeable (Jankowski, 2018;Tandoc et al., 2018). However, this problem has become increasingly acute in recent years with the Macquarie Dictionary declaring “fake news” the word of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Elusive knowledge.David Lewis - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):549 – 567.
    David Lewis (1941-2001) was Class of 1943 University Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. His contributions spanned philosophical logic, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, metaphysics, and epistemology. In On the Plurality of Worlds, he defended his challenging metaphysical position, "modal realism." He was also the author of the books Convention, Counterfactuals, Parts of Classes, and several volumes of collected papers.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1040 citations  
  6. Causation.David Lewis - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (17):556-567.
  7. Scorekeeping in a language game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):339--359.
  8. Attitudes de dicto and de se.David Lewis - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (4):513-543.
    I hear the patter of little feet around the house, I expect Bruce. What I expect is a cat, a particular cat. If I heard such a patter in another house, I might expect a cat but no particular cat. What I expect then seems to be a Meinongian incomplete cat. I expect winter, expect stormy weather, expect to shovel snow, expect fatigue---a season, a phenomenon, an activity, a state. I expect that someday mankind will inhabit at least five planets. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   845 citations  
  9. Counterfactual Dependence and Time’s Arrow.David Lewis - 1979 - Noûs 13 (4):455-476.
  10. How to define theoretical terms.David Lewis - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (13):427-446.
  11. Causation as influence.David Lewis - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (4):182-197.
  12. Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic.David Lewis - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (5):113-126.
  13. Putnam’s paradox.David Lewis - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):221 – 236.
  14. Finkish dispositions.David Kellogg Lewis - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):143-158.
    Many years ago, C.B. Martin drew our attention to the possibility of ‘finkish’ dispositions: dispositions which, if put to the test would not be manifested, but rather would disappear. Thus if x if finkishly disposed to give response r to stimulus s, it is not so that if x were subjected to stimulus r, x would give response z; so finkish dispositions afford a counter‐example to the simplest conditional analysis of dispositions. Martin went on to suggest that finkish dispositions required (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   420 citations  
  15.  20
    Direct Reference for the Narrow Minded.David Shier - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (3):225-248.
    This paper develops a theory of belief and belief ascription which retains the core of the received Propositionalist theory but which, unlike the Propositionalist theory, is compatible with both Direct Reference and Individualism about belief. The focus is on developing an alternative analysis of belief ascriptions, drawing out its implications, and applying it to some standard problems. On that analysis, ascriptions involving directly referential embedded terms are seen as roughly characterizing, but not specifying, the contents of beliefs. This feature is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  16. Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities.David Lewis - 1976 - Philosophical Review 85 (3):297-315.
  17.  62
    Thermoscopes, thermometers, and the foundations of measurement.David Sherry - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (4):509-524.
    Psychologists debate whether mental attributes can be quantified or whether they admit only qualitative comparisons of more and less. Their disagreement is not merely terminological, for it bears upon the permissibility of various statistical techniques. This article contributes to the discussion in two stages. First it explains how temperature, which was originally a qualitative concept, came to occupy its position as an unquestionably quantitative concept (§§1–4). Specifically, it lays out the circumstances in which thermometers, which register quantitative (or cardinal) differences, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  18. Causal decision theory.David Lewis - 1981 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (1):5 – 30.
    Newcomb's problem and similar cases show the need to incorporate causal distinctions into the theory of rational decision; the usual noncausal decision theory, though simpler, does not always give the right answers. I give my own version of causal decision theory, compare it with versions offered by several other authors, and suggest that the versions have more in common than meets the eye.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  19.  6
    Nociones generales y contexto histórico del derecho penal colombiano. Estudio de las codificaciones penales de 1890 hasta el 2000.Cristian David Ibarra Sánchez & Ángel Emiro Páez Moreno - 2023 - Res Pública. Revista de Historia de Las Ideas Políticas 26 (3):205-215.
    El presente trabajo de investigación tiene como objeto el estudio de la legislación penal en la República de Colombia desde 1890 hasta la actualidad con la ley 599 de 2000, este último conocido como el vigente Código Penal. Lo anterior, conforme a la siguiente pregunta problémica ¿se ha dado un desarrollo oportuno de la legislación penal colombiana que otorgue soluciones fehacientes a las necesidades de una política criminal sólida desde sus inicios hasta la actualidad? Con ello, se pretende analizar las (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. On being in the same place at the same time.David Wiggins - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (1):90-95.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  21. Logic for equivocators.David Lewis - 1982 - Noûs 16 (3):431-441.
  22. On the logic of demonstratives.David Kaplan - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):81 - 98.
  23. Counterparts of persons and their bodies.David Lewis - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (7):203-211.
  24. Empty names, fictional names, mythical names.David Braun - 2005 - Noûs 39 (4):596–631.
    John Stuart Mill (1843) thought that proper names denote individuals and do not connote attributes. Contemporary Millians agree, in spirit. We hold that the semantic content of a proper name is simply its referent. We also think that the semantic content of a declarative sentence is a Russellian structured proposition whose constituents are the semantic contents of the sentence’s constituents. This proposition is what the sentence semantically expresses. Therefore, we think that sentences containing proper names semantically express singular propositions, which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  25. Against structural universals.David K. Lewis - 1986 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1):25 – 46.
  26. Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude.David Miller - 1974 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25 (2):166-177.
  27. Anselm and actuality.David K. Lewis - 1970 - Noûs 4 (2):175-188.
  28. Holes.David K. Lewis & Stephanie Lewis - 1970 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):206 – 212.
  29.  34
    Who’s afraid of nutritionism?Jonathan Sholl & David Raubenheimer - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    Various scientists and philosophers have heavily criticized what they see as problematic forms of ‘nutritional reductionism’ or ‘nutritionism’ whereby studying food–health interactions at the level of isolated food components produces largely misguided science and misleading interpretations. However, the exact target of these diverse criticisms remains elusive, and its implications are overstated, which may hinder scientific understanding. To better identify the types of flaws supposedly hindering reductionist research, we disentangle three types of reductionist claims to better determine what the debate is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Distributing responsibilities.David Miller - 2001 - Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (4):453–471.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  31.  11
    What Efficacious Divine Action Need Not Be.David A. Vander Laan - 2023 - Philosophia Christi 25 (2):231-237.
    Arguments concerning divine conservation and concurrence often assume that actions of certain descriptions would be superfluous if God were to perform them, and it is then concluded that God does not perform such actions. In particular, it often seems that atomic actions cannot be the result of cooperative activity between God and creatures since there is no apparent way to divide the labor between the two. However, the actions that are atomic in one model of divine action may not be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Full information accounts of well-being.David Sobel - 1994 - Ethics 104 (4):784-810.
  33.  27
    Contest, Competition, and Metaphor.David Shields & Brenda Bredemeier - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (1):27-38.
  34. Causal theories of time and the conventionality of simultaneity.David Malament - 1977 - Noûs 11 (3):293-300.
  35. Caring, identification, and agency.David W. Shoemaker - 2003 - Ethics 114 (1):88-118.
    This paper articulates and defends a noncognitive, care-based view of identification, of what privileged psychic subset provides the source of self-determination in actions and attitudes. The author provides an extended analysis of "caring," and then applies it to debates between Frankfurtians, on the one hand, and Watsonians, on the other, about the nature of identification, then defends the view against objections.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  36. Ordering semantics and premise semantics for counterfactuals.David K. Lewis - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2):217-234.
  37. The impotence of the demandingness objection.David Sobel - 2007 - Philosophers' Imprint 7:1-17.
    Consequentialism, many philosophers have claimed, asks too much of us to be a plausible ethical theory. Indeed, the theory's severe demandingness is often claimed to be its chief flaw. My thesis is that as we come to better understand this objection, we see that, even if it signals or tracks the existence of a real problem for Consequentialism, it cannot itself be a fundamental problem with the view. The objection cannot itself provide good reason to break with Consequentialism, because it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  38. Noneism or allism?David K. Lewis - 1990 - Mind 99 (393):23-31.
  39. Mathematics is megethology.David K. Lewis - 1993 - Philosophia Mathematica 1 (1):3-23.
    is the second-order theory of the part-whole relation. It can express such hypotheses about the size of Reality as that there are inaccessibly many atoms. Take a non-empty class to have exactly its non-empty subclasses as parts; hence, its singleton subclasses as atomic parts. Then standard set theory becomes the theory of the member-singleton function—better, the theory of all singleton functions—within the framework of megethology. Given inaccessibly many atoms and a specification of which atoms are urelements, a singleton function exists, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  40. Individuation by acquaintance and by stipulation.David Lewis - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (1):3-32.
  41. Secession and the Principle of Nationality.David Miller - 1998 - In Margaret Moore (ed.), National Self-Determination and Secession. Oxford University Press.
    This chapter argues that the principle of nationality offers a perspective on the secession issue that avoids condoning a secessionist free‐for‐all without forcing us to defend existing state boundaries regardless. It suggests the need for a contextual approach to secession, examining the extent to which different groups have or have not evolved separate national identities, how minorities are likely to fare under various possible regimes, and whether partial autonomy regimes might be more justified than secession.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42. Sider on existence.David Liebesman & Matti Eklund - 2007 - Noûs 41 (3):519–528.
    In (2001), (2003), and elsewhere, Ted Sider presents two arguments concerning the existential quantifier which are justly central to the recent discussion of metaontology. What we will call Sider's indeterminacy argument is an attempted reductio of the suggestion that the existential quantifier might be semantically indeterminate. What we will call Sider's naturalness argument is an argument for the claim that the semantic value of the existential quantifier is the most eligible existence-like meaning there is, à la David Lewis' eligibility (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  43. The St. Petersburg two-envelope paradox.David J. Chalmers - 2002 - Analysis 62 (2):155–157.
    I reason: (1) For any x, if I knew that A contained x, then the odds are even that B contains either 2x or x/2, so the expected amount in B would be 5x/4. So (2) for all x, if I knew that A contained x, I would have an expected gain in switching to B. So (3) I should switch to B. But this seems clearly wrong, as my information about A and B is symmetrical.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  44. The Lord of the Rings as Philosophy: Environmental Enchantment and Resistance in Peter Jackson and J.R.R. Tolkien.John F. Whitmire & David G. Henderson - 2022 - In David Kyle Johnson (ed.), The Palgrave Handbook of Popular Culture as Philosophy. Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 827-854.
    A key philosophical feature of Peter Jackson’s film interpretation of J.R.R. Tolkien’s The Lord of the Rings is its use of fantasy to inspire a “recovery” of the actual or, in other words, a reawakening to the beauty of nature and the many possible ways of living in healthier ecological relation to the world. Though none of these ways is perfectly achieved, this pluralistic view is demonstrated in the various lifeways of Hobbits, Elves, Men, and Ents. All of the positive (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Consciousness and its function.David Rosenthal - 2008
    MS, under submission, derived from a Powerpoint presentation at a Conference on Consciousness, Memory, and Perception, in honor of Larry Weiskrantz, City University, London, September 15, 2006.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  46. Input/output logics.David Makinson & Leendert van der Torre - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):383-408.
    In a range of contexts, one comes across processes resembling inference, but where input propositions are not in general included among outputs, and the operation is not in any way reversible. Examples arise in contexts of conditional obligations, goals, ideals, preferences, actions, and beliefs. Our purpose is to develop a theory of such input/output operations. Four are singled out: simple-minded, basic (making intelligent use of disjunctive inputs), simple-minded reusable (in which outputs may be recycled as inputs), and basic reusable. They (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  47. Coercive wage offers.David Zimmerman - 1981 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (2):121-145.
  48. Immodest inductive methods.David Lewis - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (1):54-63.
    Inductive methods can be used to estimate the accuracies of inductive methods. Call a method immodest if it estimates that it is at least as accurate as any of its rivals. It would be unreasonable to adopt any but an immodest method. Under certain assumptions, exactly one of Carnap's lambda-methods is immodest. This may seem to solve the problem of choosing among the lambda-methods; but sometimes the immodest lambda-method is λ =0, which it would not be reasonable to adopt. We (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  49. Just war and human rights.David Luban - 1980 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (2):160-181.
  50. On a moral right to civil disobedience.David Lefkowitz - 2007 - Ethics 117 (2):202-233.
1 — 50 / 967