Results for 'set-theoretic definability'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Set-theoretical Invariance Criteria for Logicality.Solomon Feferman - 2010 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (1):3-20.
    This is a survey of work on set-theoretical invariance criteria for logicality. It begins with a review of the Tarski-Sher thesis in terms, first, of permutation invariance over a given domain and then of isomorphism invariance across domains, both characterized by McGee in terms of definability in the language L∞,∞. It continues with a review of critiques of the Tarski-Sher thesis, and a proposal in response to one of those critiques via homomorphism invariance. That has quite divergent characterization results (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  2.  47
    Set-theoretic mereology.Joel David Hamkins & Makoto Kikuchi - 2016 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 25 (3):285-308.
    We consider a set-theoretic version of mereology based on the inclusion relation ⊆ and analyze how well it might serve as a foundation of mathematics. After establishing the non-definability of ∈ from ⊆, we identify the natural axioms for ⊆-based mereology, which constitute a finitely axiomatizable, complete, decidable theory. Ultimately, for these reasons, we conclude that this form of set-theoretic mereology cannot by itself serve as a foundation of mathematics. Meanwhile, augmented forms of set-theoretic mereology, such (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  69
    The Set Theoretic Ambit Of Arrow's Theorem.Louis M. Guenin - 2001 - Synthese 126 (3):443-472.
    Set theoretic formulation of Arrow's theorem, viewedin light of a taxonomy of transitive relations,serves to unmask the theorem's understatedgenerality. Under the impress of the independenceof irrelevant alternatives, the antipode of ceteris paribus reasoning, a purported compilerfunction either breaches some other rationalitypremise or produces the effet Condorcet. Types of cycles, each the seeming handiwork of avirtual voter disdaining transitivity, arerigorously defined. Arrow's theorem erects adilemma between cyclic indecision anddictatorship. Maneuvers responsive theretoare explicable in set theoretic terms. None ofthese gambits (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  78
    Set theoretic properties of Loeb measure.Arnold W. Miller - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):1022-1036.
    In this paper we ask the question: to what extent do basic set theoretic properties of Loeb measure depend on the nonstandard universe and on properties of the model of set theory in which it lies? We show that, assuming Martin's axiom and κ-saturation, the smallest cover by Loeb measure zero sets must have cardinality less than κ. In contrast to this we show that the additivity of Loeb measure cannot be greater than ω 1 . Define $\operatorname{cof}(H)$ as (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  36
    Choiceless large cardinals and set‐theoretic potentialism.Raffaella Cutolo & Joel David Hamkins - 2022 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 68 (4):409-415.
    We define a potentialist system of ‐structures, i.e., a collection of possible worlds in the language of connected by a binary accessibility relation, achieving a potentialist account of the full background set‐theoretic universe V. The definition involves Berkeley cardinals, the strongest known large cardinal axioms, inconsistent with the Axiom of Choice. In fact, as background theory we assume just. It turns out that the propositional modal assertions which are valid at every world of our system are exactly those in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Combinatorial set theoretic principles of great logical strength.Harvey Friedman - manuscript
    Let j:β → β, where β is an ordinal. Let R ⊆ α x α, where β ≤ α. We define j[R] = {(j(c),j(d)): R(c,d)}. We say that j is a nonidentity function if and only if j is not the..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  91
    Model theory: Geometrical and set-theoretic aspects and prospects.Angus Macintyre - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):197-212.
    I see model theory as becoming increasingly detached from set theory, and the Tarskian notion of set-theoretic model being no longer central to model theory. In much of modern mathematics, the set-theoretic component is of minor interest, and basic notions are geometric or category-theoretic. In algebraic geometry, schemes or algebraic spaces are the basic notions, with the older “sets of points in affine or projective space” no more than restrictive special cases. The basic notions may be given (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  44
    Taxonomies of model-theoretically defined topological properties.Paul Bankston - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):589-603.
    A topological classification scheme consists of two ingredients: (1) an abstract class K of topological spaces; and (2) a "taxonomy", i.e. a list of first order sentences, together with a way of assigning an abstract class of spaces to each sentence of the list so that logically equivalent sentences are assigned the same class. K is then endowed with an equivalence relation, two spaces belonging to the same equivalence class if and only if they lie in the same classes prescribed (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  49
    Neither categorical nor set-theoretic foundations.Geoffrey Hellman - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):16-23.
    First we review highlights of the ongoing debate about foundations of category theory, beginning with Fefermantop-down” approach, where particular categories and functors need not be explicitly defined. Possible reasons for resisting the proposal are offered and countered. The upshot is to sustain a pluralism of foundations along lines actually foreseen by Feferman (1977), something that should be welcomed as a way of resolving this long-standing debate.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  18
    Kolmogorov complexity and set theoretical representations of integers.Marie Ferbus-Zanda & Serge Grigorieff - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (4):375-403.
    We reconsider some classical natural semantics of integers in the perspective of Kolmogorov complexity. To each such semantics one can attach a simple representation of integers that we suitably effectivize in order to develop an associated Kolmogorov theory. Such effectivizations are particular instances of a general notion of “self-enumerated system” that we introduce in this paper. Our main result asserts that, with such effectivizations, Kolmogorov theory allows to quantitatively distinguish the underlying semantics. We characterize the families obtained by such effectivizations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  40
    Definability of R. E. sets in a class of recursion theoretic structures.Robert E. Byerly - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):662-669.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. On Evans's Vague Object from Set Theoretic Viewpoint.Shunsuke Yatabe & Hiroyuki Inaoka - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (4):423-434.
    Gareth Evans proved that if two objects are indeterminately equal then they are different in reality. He insisted that this contradicts the assumption that there can be vague objects. However we show the consistency between Evans's proof and the existence of vague objects within classical logic. We formalize Evans's proof in a set theory without the axiom of extensionality, and we define a set to be vague if it violates extensionality with respect to some other set. There exist models of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  44
    Algebraicity and Implicit Definability in Set Theory.Joel David Hamkins & Cole Leahy - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (3):431-439.
    We analyze the effect of replacing several natural uses of definability in set theory by the weaker model-theoretic notion of algebraicity. We find, for example, that the class of hereditarily ordinal algebraic sets is the same as the class of hereditarily ordinal definable sets; that is, $\mathrm{HOA}=\mathrm{HOD}$. Moreover, we show that every algebraic model of $\mathrm{ZF}$ is actually pointwise definable. Finally, we consider the implicitly constructible universe Imp—an algebraic analogue of the constructible universe—which is obtained by iteratively adding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  14.  40
    Sets and Functions in Theoretical Physics.Adonai S. Sant’Anna & Otávio Bueno - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (2):257-281.
    It is easy to show that in many natural axiomatic formulations of physical and even mathematical theories, there are many superfluous concepts usually assumed as primitive. This happens mainly when these theories are formulated in the language of standard set theories, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel’s. In 1925, John von Neumann created a set theory where sets are definable by means of functions. We provide a reformulation of von Neumann’s set theory and show that it can be used to formulate physical and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  8
    Families of sets with nonmeasurable unions with respect to ideals defined by trees.Robert Rałowski - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):649-658.
    In this note we consider subfamilies of the ideal s0 introduced by Marczewski-Szpilrajn and ideals sp0, l0 analogously defined using complete Laver trees and Laver trees respectively. We show that under some set-theoretical assumptions =c\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${cov=\mathfrak{c}}$$\end{document} for example) in every uncountable Polish space X every family A⊆s0\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal{A}\subseteq s_0}$$\end{document} covering X has a subfamily with s-nonmeasurable union. We show the consistency of cov=ω1 (...))
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  29
    Some theoretical and practical implications of defining aptitude and reasoning in terms of each other.Adam S. Goodie & Cristina C. Williams - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5):675-676.
    Stanovich & West continue a history of norm-setting that began with deference to reasonable people's opinions, followed by adherence to probability theorems. They return to deference to reasonable people, with aptitude test performance substituting for reasonableness. This allows them to select independently among competing theories, but defines reasoning circularly in terms of aptitude, while aptitude is measured using reasoning.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. A proof-theoretic characterization of the primitive recursive set functions.Michael Rathjen - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):954-969.
    Let KP- be the theory resulting from Kripke-Platek set theory by restricting Foundation to Set Foundation. Let G: V → V (V:= universe of sets) be a ▵0-definable set function, i.e. there is a ▵0-formula φ(x, y) such that φ(x, G(x)) is true for all sets x, and $V \models \forall x \exists!y\varphi (x, y)$ . In this paper we shall verify (by elementary proof-theoretic methods) that the collection of set functions primitive recursive in G coincides with the collection (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18. A Graph-theoretic Method to Define any Boolean Operation on Partitions.David Ellerman - 2019 - The Art of Discrete and Applied Mathematics 2 (2):1-9.
    The lattice operations of join and meet were defined for set partitions in the nineteenth century, but no new logical operations on partitions were defined and studied during the twentieth century. Yet there is a simple and natural graph-theoretic method presented here to define any n-ary Boolean operation on partitions. An equivalent closure-theoretic method is also defined. In closing, the question is addressed of why it took so long for all Boolean operations to be defined for partitions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Free Set Algebras Satisfying Systems of Equations.G. Antonelli - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1656-1674.
    In this paper we introduce the notion of a set algebra $\mathscr{S}$ satisfying a system $\mathscr{E}$ equations. After defining a notion of freeness for such algebras, we show that, for any system $\mathscr{E}$ of equations, set algebras that are free in the class of structures satisfying $\mathscr{E}$ exist and are unique up to a bisimulation. Along the way, analogues of classical set-theoretic and algebraic properties are investigated.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Librationist cum classical theories of sets.Frode Bjørdal - manuscript
    The focus in this essay will be upon the paradoxes, and foremostly in set theory. A central result is that the librationist set theory £ extension \Pfund $\mathscr{HR}(\mathbf{D})$ of \pounds \ accounts for \textbf{Neumann-Bernays-Gödel} set theory with the \textbf{Axiom of Choice} and \textbf{Tarski's Axiom}. Moreover, \Pfund \ succeeds with defining an impredicative manifestation set $\mathbf{W}$, \emph{die Welt}, so that \Pfund$\mathscr{H}(\mathbf{W})$ %is a model accounts for Quine's \textbf{New Foundations}. Nevertheless, the points of view developed support the view that the truth-paradoxes and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  10
    x1. Introduction. In 1938, K. Gödel defined the model L of set theory to show the relative consistency of Cantor's Continuum Hypothesis. L is defined as a union L=. [REVIEW]Sy D. Friedman & Peter Koepke - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):453-468.
    We present here an approach to the fine structure of L based solely on elementary model theoretic ideas, and illustrate its use in a proof of Global Square in L. We thereby avoid the Lévy hierarchy of formulas and the subtleties of master codes and projecta, introduced by Jensen [3] in the original form of the theory. Our theory could appropriately be called ”Hyperfine Structure Theory”, as we make use of a hierarchy of structures and hull operations which refines (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  10
    The Combinatorics and Absoluteness of Definable Sets of Real Numbers.Zach Norwood - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (2):263-264.
    This thesis divides naturally into two parts, each concerned with the extent to which the theory of $L$ can be changed by forcing.The first part focuses primarily on applying generic-absoluteness principles to how that definable sets of reals enjoy regularity properties. The work in Part I is joint with Itay Neeman and is adapted from our paper Happy and mad families in $L$, JSL, 2018. The project was motivated by questions about mad families, maximal families of infinite subsets of $\omega (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Definability and the Structure of Logical Paradoxes.Haixia Zhong - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):779 - 788.
    Graham Priest 2002 argues that all logical paradoxes that include set-theoretic paradoxes and semantic paradoxes share a common structure, the Inclosure Schema, so they should be treated as one family. Through a discussion of Berry's Paradox and the semantic notion ?definable?, I argue that (i) the Inclosure Schema is not fine-grained enough to capture the essential features of semantic paradoxes, and (ii) the traditional separation of the two groups of logical paradoxes should be retained.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Decision-theoretic paradoxes as voting paradoxes.Rachael Briggs - 2010 - Philosophical Review 119 (1):1-30.
    It is a platitude among decision theorists that agents should choose their actions so as to maximize expected value. But exactly how to define expected value is contentious. Evidential decision theory (henceforth EDT), causal decision theory (henceforth CDT), and a theory proposed by Ralph Wedgwood that this essay will call benchmark theory (BT) all advise agents to maximize different types of expected value. Consequently, their verdicts sometimes conflict. In certain famous cases of conflict—medical Newcomb problems—CDT and BT seem to get (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  25.  76
    A Formalization of Set Theory Without Variables.István Németi - 1988 - American Mathematical Soc..
    Completed in 1983, this work culminates nearly half a century of the late Alfred Tarski's foundational studies in logic, mathematics, and the philosophy of science. Written in collaboration with Steven Givant, the book appeals to a very broad audience, and requires only a familiarity with first-order logic. It is of great interest to logicians and mathematicians interested in the foundations of mathematics, but also to philosophers interested in logic, semantics, algebraic logic, or the methodology of the deductive sciences, and to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  26.  28
    Quantum set theory: Transfer Principle and De Morgan's Laws.Masanao Ozawa - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (4):102938.
    In quantum logic, introduced by Birkhoff and von Neumann, De Morgan's Laws play an important role in the projection-valued truth value assignment of observational propositions in quantum mechanics. Takeuti's quantum set theory extends this assignment to all the set-theoretical statements on the universe of quantum sets. However, Takeuti's quantum set theory has a problem in that De Morgan's Laws do not hold between universal and existential bounded quantifiers. Here, we solve this problem by introducing a new truth value assignment for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  15
    A Theoretical Framework for How We Learn Aesthetic Values.Hassan Aleem, Ivan Correa-Herran & Norberto M. Grzywacz - 2020 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14:565629.
    How do we come to like the things that we do? Each one of us starts from a relatively similar state at birth, yet we end up with vastly different sets of aesthetic preferences. These preferences go on to define us both as individuals and as members of our cultures. Therefore, it is important to understand how aesthetic preferences form over our lifetimes. This poses a challenging problem: to understand this process, one must account for the many factors at play (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  69
    A system of axiomatic set theory - Part VII.Paul Bernays - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (2):81-96.
    The reader of Part VI will have noticed that among the set-theoretic models considered there some models were missing which were announced in Part II for certain proofs of independence. These models will be supplied now.Mainly two models have to be constructed: one with the property that there exists a set which is its own only element, and another in which the axioms I–III and VII, but not Va, are satisfied. In either case we need not satisfy the axiom (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  29. Mass terms and model-theoretic semantics.Harry C. Bunt - 1985 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    'Mass terms', words like water, rice and traffic, have proved very difficult to accommodate in any theory of meaning since, unlike count nouns such as house or dog, they cannot be viewed as part of a logical set and differ in their grammatical properties. In this study, motivated by the need to design a computer program for understanding natural language utterances incorporating mass terms, Harry Bunt provides a thorough analysis of the problem and offers an original and detailed solution. An (...)
  30.  19
    Defining Collective Identities in Technopolitical Interaction Networks.Xabier E. Barandiaran, Antonio Calleja-López & Emanuele Cozzo - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    We are currently witnessing the emergence of new forms of collective identities and a redefinition of the old ones through networked digital interactions, and these can be explicitly measured and analyzed. We distinguish between three major trends on the development of the concept of identity in the social realm: (1) an essentialist sense (based on conditions and properties shared by members of a group), (2) a representational or ideational sense (based on the application of categories by oneself or others), and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  57
    Set theory: Constructive and intuitionistic ZF.Laura Crosilla - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Constructive and intuitionistic Zermelo-Fraenkel set theories are axiomatic theories of sets in the style of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF) which are based on intuitionistic logic. They were introduced in the 1970's and they represent a formal context within which to codify mathematics based on intuitionistic logic. They are formulated on the basis of the standard first order language of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory and make no direct use of inherently constructive ideas. In working in constructive and intuitionistic ZF we can thus (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  51
    Intuitionistic sets and ordinals.Paul Taylor - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):705-744.
    Transitive extensional well founded relations provide an intuitionistic notion of ordinals which admits transfinite induction. However these ordinals are not directed and their successor operation is poorly behaved, leading to problems of functoriality. We show how to make the successor monotone by introducing plumpness, which strengthens transitivity. This clarifies the traditional development of successors and unions, making it intuitionistic; even the (classical) proof of trichotomy is made simpler. The definition is, however, recursive, and, as their name suggests, the plump ordinals (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33. How set theory impinges on logic.Jesus Mosterin - unknown
    Standard (classical) logic is not independent of set theory. Which formulas are valid in logic depends on which sets we assume to exist in our set-theoretical universe. Second-order logic is just set theory in disguise. The typically logical notions of validity and consequence are not well defined in second-order logic, at least as long as there are open issues in set theory. Such contentious issues in set theory as the axiom of choice, the continuum hypothesis or the existence of inaccessible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  10
    Condensable models of set theory.Ali Enayat - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (3):299-315.
    A model \ of ZF is said to be condensable if \\prec _{\mathbb {L}_{{\mathcal {M}}}} {\mathcal {M}}\) for some “ordinal” \, where \:=,\in )^{{\mathcal {M}}}\) and \ is the set of formulae of the infinitary logic \ that appear in the well-founded part of \. The work of Barwise and Schlipf in the 1970s revealed the fact that every countable recursively saturated model of ZF is cofinally condensable \prec _{\mathbb {L}_{{\mathcal {M}}}}{\mathcal {M}}\) for an unbounded collection of \). Moreover, it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. On arbitrary sets and ZFC.José Ferreirós - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (3):361-393.
    Set theory deals with the most fundamental existence questions in mathematics—questions which affect other areas of mathematics, from the real numbers to structures of all kinds, but which are posed as dealing with the existence of sets. Especially noteworthy are principles establishing the existence of some infinite sets, the so-called “arbitrary sets.” This paper is devoted to an analysis of the motivating goal of studying arbitrary sets, usually referred to under the labels of quasi-combinatorialism or combinatorial maximality. After explaining what (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  18
    The Weak Choice Principle WISC may Fail in the Category of Sets.David Michael Roberts - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (5):1005-1017.
    The set-theoretic axiom WISC states that for every set there is a set of surjections to it cofinal in all such surjections. By constructing an unbounded topos over the category of sets and using an extension of the internal logic of a topos due to Shulman, we show that WISC is independent of the rest of the axioms of the set theory given by a well-pointed topos. This also gives an example of a topos that is not a predicative (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Defining disease beyond conceptual analysis: an analysis of conceptual analysis in philosophy of medicine.Maël Lemoine - 2013 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34 (4):309-325.
    Conceptual analysis of health and disease is portrayed as consisting in the confrontation of a set of criteria—a “definition”—with a set of cases, called instances of either “health” or “ disease.” Apart from logical counter-arguments, there is no other way to refute an opponent’s definition than by providing counter-cases. As resorting to intensional stipulation is not forbidden, several contenders can therefore be deemed to have succeeded. This implies that conceptual analysis alone is not likely to decide between naturalism and normativism. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  38.  13
    Theoretical concepts in flux: Conceptual knowledge and theory change.Hans Rott - 2003 - In Regine Eckardt, Klaus von Heusinger & Christoph Schwarze (eds.), Words in Time: Diachronic Semantics From Different Points of View. Mouton de Gruyter. pp. 143-175.
    A theoretical term gets its meaning from a set of meaning-constitutive or 'analytic' sentences of the relevant theory. The meanings of theoretical terms may change when the theories change. After a discussion of Kant and Frege, I propose a broadly Quinean view of analyticity, without adopting Quine's meaning skepticism. A sentence of a given theory in a certain language is called analytic if revising the theory so that this sentence is lost entails the abandonment of the given linguistic (alternatively, of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Review of: Garciadiego, A., "Emergence of...paradoxes...set theory", Historia Mathematica (1985), in Mathematical Reviews 87j:01035.John Corcoran - 1987 - MATHEMATICAL REVIEWS 87 (J):01035.
    DEFINING OUR TERMS A “paradox" is an argumentation that appears to deduce a conclusion believed to be false from premises believed to be true. An “inconsistency proof for a theory" is an argumentation that actually deduces a negation of a theorem of the theory from premises that are all theorems of the theory. An “indirect proof of the negation of a hypothesis" is an argumentation that actually deduces a conclusion known to be false from the hypothesis alone or, more commonly, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  34
    Construction of tableaux for classical logic: Tableaux as combinations of branches, branches as chains of sets.Tomasz Jarmużek - 2007 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 16 (1):85-101.
    The paper is devoted to an approach to analytic tableaux for propositional logic, but can be successfully extended to other logics. The distinguishing features of the presented approach are:(i) a precise set-theoretical description of tableau method; (ii) a notion of tableau consequence relation is defined without help of a notion of tableau, in our universe of discourse the basic notion is a branch;(iii) we define a tableau as a finite set of some chosen branches which is enough to check; hence, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  41
    Defining Philosophical Counselling: An Overview1.D. Louw - 2013 - South African Journal of Philosophy 32 (1):60-70.
    The practice of ‘Philosophical Counselling’ (henceforth ‘PC’) is growing. But what exactly is PC? The variety of attempts to define PC can be summarised in terms of three overlapping sets of opposites: practical versus theoretical definitions; monistic versus pluralistic definitions; and substantive versus antinomous definitions. ‘Practical’ definitions of PC include descriptive accounts of its actual practice. ‘Theoretical’ definitions exclude such accounts. ‘Monistic definitions’ refers to definitions of PC that define it in terms of the work of one specific philosopher or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  27
    New Theoretical Framework for Approaching Artistic Activity.Dan-Eugen Raţiu - 2012 - Cultura 9 (1):101-122.
    This article explores recent developments in the sociology of the arts, namely the new theoretical framework set up by the French sociologist Pierre-Michel Menger in order to approach the artistic activity. It aims to show how he has shaped new tools of understanding and modelling for exploring the arts, as a particular world of action. Laying down the foundation of a conception of action related to symbolic interactionism and drawing on the economic analysis of risk and uncertainty, Menger move towards (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  14
    New Theoretical Framework for Approaching Artistic Activity.Dan-Eugen Raţiu - 2012 - Cultura 9 (1):101-122.
    This article explores recent developments in the sociology of the arts, namely the new theoretical framework set up by the French sociologist Pierre-Michel Menger in order to approach the artistic activity. It aims to show how he has shaped new tools of understanding and modelling for exploring the arts, as a particular world of action. Laying down the foundation of a conception of action related to symbolic interactionism and drawing on the economic analysis of risk and uncertainty, Menger move towards (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  15
    New Theoretical Framework for Approaching Artistic Activity: the Principle of Uncertainty. Pierre-Michel Menger’s Sociology of Creative Work.Dan-Eugen Raţiu - 2012 - Cultura 9 (1):101-122.
    This article explores recent developments in the sociology of the arts, namely the new theoretical framework set up by the French sociologist Pierre-Michel Menger in order to approach the artistic activity. It aims to show how he has shaped new tools of understanding and modelling for exploring the arts, as a particular world of action. Laying down the foundation of a conception of action related to symbolic interactionism and drawing on the economic analysis of risk and uncertainty, Menger move towards (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  41
    Type-Theoretical Interpretation and Generalization of Phrase Structure Grammar.Aarne Ranta - 1995 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 3 (2-3):319-342.
    In this paper, we shall present a generalization of phrase structure grammar, in which all functional categories have type restrictions, that is, their argument types are specific domains. In ordinary phrase structure grammar, there is just one universal domain of individuals. The grammar does not make a distinction between verbs and adjectives in terms of domains of applicability. Consequently, it fails to distinguish between sentences like every line intersects every line, which is well typed, and every line intersects every point, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Definability in the recursively enumerable degrees.André Nies, Richard A. Shore & Theodore A. Slaman - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):392-404.
    §1. Introduction. Natural sets that can be enumerated by a computable function always seem to be either actually computable or of the same complexity as the Halting Problem, the complete r.e. set K. The obvious question, first posed in Post [1944] and since then called Post's Problem is then just whether there are r.e. sets which are neither computable nor complete, i.e., neither recursive nor of the same Turing degree as K?Let be the r.e. degrees, i.e., the r.e. sets modulo (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  27
    Theoretical and Practical Issues of Consumer's Conception.Lina Novikovienė - 2010 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 122 (4):279-293.
    Protecting consumers' rights set higher standards on the rights of security compared with other participants of civil turnover, so the concept of consumer acquires not only theoretical but also practical significance. Definition of consumer must be sufficiently clear and precise as the proper subject of classification depends on what rules will apply to legal relationships arising. To this purpose, the concept of consumer is formulated as the concept of both the European Union and national legislation. Both presented the concept of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    Existential definability of modal frame classes.Tin Perkov & Luka Mikec - 2020 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 66 (3):316-325.
    We prove an existential analogue of the Goldblatt‐Thomason Theorem which characterizes modal definability of elementary classes of Kripke frames using closure under model theoretic constructions. The less known version of the Goldblatt‐Thomason Theorem gives general conditions, without the assumption of first‐order definability, but uses non‐standard constructions and algebraic semantics. We present a non‐algebraic proof of this result and we prove an analogous characterization for an alternative notion of modal definability, in which a class is defined by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  27
    Defining, Using, and Challenging the Rhetorical Tradition.Alisse Theodore Portnoy - 2003 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 36 (2):103-108.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Rhetoric 36.2 (2003) 103-108 [Access article in PDF] Defining, Using, and Challenging the Rhetorical Tradition Alisse Theodore Portnoy "What counts as 'the tradition'?" was the question that provoked this series of essays. Several of us attended a retreat sponsored by the Rhetoric Society of America, and we had dutifully split into smaller groups in an attempt to define or mark rhetoric as a discipline. Patricia Bizzell and (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  13
    Three Model-Theoretic Constructions for Generalized Epstein Semantics.Krzysztof A. Krawczyk - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (4):1023-1032.
    This paper introduces three model-theoretic constructions for generalized Epstein semantics: reducts, ultramodels and $\textsf {S}$ -sets. We apply these notions to obtain metatheoretical results. We prove connective inexpressibility by means of a reduct, compactness by an ultramodel and definability theorem which states that a set of generalized Epstein models is definable iff it is closed under ultramodels and $\textsf {S}$ -sets. Furthermore, a corollary concerning definability of a set of models by a single formula is given on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 1000