Results for 'Turing definable'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Computability and λ-definability.A. M. Turing - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):153-163.
  2.  61
    Computability and $lambda$-Definability.A. M. Turing - 1937 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):153-163.
  3.  19
    Definability by turing machines.R. M. Baer - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (20‐22):325-332.
  4.  23
    Definability by turing machines.R. M. Baer - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (20-22):325-332.
  5.  16
    Turing A. M.. Computability and λ-definability.Rózsa Péter - 1938 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):89-89.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  4
    REVIEWS-Defining the Turing jump.R. Shore, T. Slaman & Carl G. Jockusch Jr - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):73-74.
  7.  38
    On homogeneity and definability in the first-order theory of the Turing degrees.Richard A. Shore - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):8-16.
  8.  13
    The Inversion of Functions Defined by Turing Machines.John Mccarthy - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):481-481.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  5
    A hierarchy of Turing degrees: a transfinite hierarchy of lowness notions in the computably enumerable degrees, unifying classes, and natural definability.R. G. Downey - 2020 - Princeton: Princeton University Press. Edited by Noam Greenberg.
    This book presents new results in computability theory, a branch of mathematical logic and computer science that has become increasingly relevant in recent years. The field's connections with disparate areas of mathematical logic and mathematics more generally have grown deeper, and now have a variety of applications in topology, group theory, and other subfields. This monograph establishes new directions in the field, blending classic results with modern research areas such as algorithmic randomness. The significance of the book lies not only (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  24
    Turing–Taylor Expansions for Arithmetic Theories.Joost J. Joosten - 2016 - Studia Logica 104 (6):1225-1243.
    Turing progressions have been often used to measure the proof-theoretic strength of mathematical theories: iterate adding consistency of some weak base theory until you “hit” the target theory. Turing progressions based on n-consistency give rise to a \ proof-theoretic ordinal \ also denoted \. As such, to each theory U we can assign the sequence of corresponding \ ordinals \. We call this sequence a Turing-Taylor expansion or spectrum of a theory. In this paper, we relate (...)-Taylor expansions of sub-theories of Peano Arithmetic to Ignatiev’s universal model for the closed fragment of the polymodal provability logic \. In particular, we observe that each point in the Ignatiev model can be seen as Turing-Taylor expansions of formal mathematical theories. Moreover, each sub-theory of Peano Arithmetic that allows for a Turing-Taylor expansion will define a unique point in Ignatiev’s model. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  84
    The Constructibility of Artificial Intelligence (as Defined by the Turing Test).Bruce Edmonds - 2000 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 9 (4):419-424.
    The Turing Test (TT), as originally specified, centres on theability to perform a social role. The TT can be seen as a test of anability to enter into normal human social dynamics. In this light itseems unlikely that such an entity can be wholly designed in an off-line mode; rather a considerable period of training insitu would be required. The argument that since we can pass the TT,and our cognitive processes might be implemented as a Turing Machine(TM), that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Turing computations on ordinals.Peter Koepke - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):377-397.
    We define the notion of ordinal computability by generalizing standard Turing computability on tapes of length ω to computations on tapes of arbitrary ordinal length. We show that a set of ordinals is ordinal computable from a finite set of ordinal parameters if and only if it is an element of Gödel's constructible universe L. This characterization can be used to prove the generalized continuum hypothesis in L.
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13.  13
    A. M. Turing. Computability and λ-definability. The journal of symbolic logic, Bd. 2 , S. 153–163. [REVIEW]Rózsa Péter - 1938 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 3 (2):89-89.
  14.  20
    Turing computable embeddings.F. Knight Julia, Miller Sara & M. Vanden Boom - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3):901-918.
    In [3], two different effective versions of Borel embedding are defined. The first, called computable embedding, is based on uniform enumeration reducibility, while the second, called Turing computable embedding, is based on uniform Turing reducibility. While [3] focused mainly on computable embeddings, the present paper considers Turing computable embeddings. Although the two notions are not equivalent, we can show that they behave alike on the mathematically interesting classes chosen for investigation in [3]. We give a “Pull-back Theorem”, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  23
    On Turing degrees of points in computable topology.Iraj Kalantari & Larry Welch - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (5):470-482.
    This paper continues our study of computable point-free topological spaces and the metamathematical points in them. For us, a point is the intersection of a sequence of basic open sets with compact and nested closures. We call such a sequence a sharp filter. A function fF from points to points is generated by a function F from basic open sets to basic open sets such that sharp filters map to sharp filters. We restrict our study to functions that have at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  47
    Turing degrees of certain isomorphic images of computable relations.Valentina S. Harizanov - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 93 (1-3):103-113.
    A model is computable if its domain is a computable set and its relations and functions are uniformly computable. Let be a computable model and let R be an extra relation on the domain of . That is, R is not named in the language of . We define to be the set of Turing degrees of the images f under all isomorphisms f from to computable models. We investigate conditions on and R which are sufficient and necessary for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17.  41
    Beyond Turing equivalence.Aaron Sloman - 1996 - In Peter Millican Andy Clark (ed.), Machines and Thought The Legacy of Alan Turing. Oxford University Press. pp. 1--179.
    What is the relation between intelligence and computation? Although the difficulty of defining `intelligence' is widely recognized, many are unaware that it is hard to give a satisfactory definition of `computational' if computation is supposed to provide a non-circular explanation for intelligent abilities. The only well-defined notion of `computation' is what can be generated by a Turing machine or a formally equivalent mechanism. This is not adequate for the key role in explaining the nature of mental processes, because it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  18. Beyond the universal Turing machine.Jack Copeland - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (1):46-67.
    We describe an emerging field, that of nonclassical computability and nonclassical computing machinery. According to the nonclassicist, the set of well-defined computations is not exhausted by the computations that can be carried out by a Turing machine. We provide an overview of the field and a philosophical defence of its foundations.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  19. Hypercomputation and the Physical Church‐Turing Thesis.Paolo Cotogno - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2):181-223.
    A version of the Church-Turing Thesis states that every effectively realizable physical system can be simulated by Turing Machines (‘Thesis P’). In this formulation the Thesis appears to be an empirical hypothesis, subject to physical falsification. We review the main approaches to computation beyond Turing definability (‘hypercomputation’): supertask, non-well-founded, analog, quantum, and retrocausal computation. The conclusions are that these models reduce to supertasks, i.e. infinite computation, and that even supertasks are no solution for recursive incomputability. This yields (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  20.  26
    Turing degrees of hypersimple relations on computable structures.Valentina S. Harizanov - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (2-3):209-226.
    Let be an infinite computable structure, and let R be an additional computable relation on its domain A. The syntactic notion of formal hypersimplicity of R on , first introduced and studied by Hird, is analogous to the computability-theoretic notion of hypersimplicity of R on A, given the definability of certain effective sequences of relations on A. Assuming that R is formally hypersimple on , we give general sufficient conditions for the existence of a computable isomorphic copy of on whose (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Beyond the Turing test.Jose Hernandez-Orallo - 2000 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 9 (4):447-466.
    The main factor of intelligence is defined as the ability tocomprehend, formalising this ability with the help of new constructsbased on descriptional complexity. The result is a comprehension test,or C- test, which is exclusively defined in computational terms. Due toits absolute and non-anthropomorphic character, it is equally applicableto both humans and non-humans. Moreover, it correlates with classicalpsychometric tests, thus establishing the first firm connection betweeninformation theoretical notions and traditional IQ tests. The TuringTest is compared with the C- test and the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  22.  14
    A Bounded Jump for the Bounded Turing Degrees.Bernard Anderson & Barbara Csima - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (2):245-264.
    We define the bounded jump of $A$ by $A^{b}=\{x\in \omega \mid \exists i\leq x[\varphi_{i}\downarrow \wedge\Phi_{x}^{A\upharpoonright \!\!\!\upharpoonright \varphi_{i}}\downarrow ]\}$ and let $A^{nb}$ denote the $n$th bounded jump. We demonstrate several properties of the bounded jump, including the fact that it is strictly increasing and order-preserving on the bounded Turing degrees. We show that the bounded jump is related to the Ershov hierarchy. Indeed, for $n\geq2$ we have $X\leq_{bT}\emptyset ^{nb}\iff X$ is $\omega^{n}$-c.e. $\iff X\leq_{1}\emptyset ^{nb}$, extending the classical result that $X\leq_{bT}\emptyset (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  6
    Coarse computability, the density metric, Hausdorff distances between Turing degrees, perfect trees, and reverse mathematics.Denis R. Hirschfeldt, Carl G. Jockusch & Paul E. Schupp - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 24 (2).
    For [Formula: see text], the coarse similarity class of A, denoted by [Formula: see text], is the set of all [Formula: see text] such that the symmetric difference of A and B has asymptotic density 0. There is a natural metric [Formula: see text] on the space [Formula: see text] of coarse similarity classes defined by letting [Formula: see text] be the upper density of the symmetric difference of A and B. We study the metric space of coarse similarity classes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  18
    Mind who’s testing: Turing tests and the post-colonial imposition of their implicit conceptions of intelligence.Fabian Fischbach, Tijs Vandemeulebroucke & Aimee van Wynsberghe - forthcoming - AI and Society:1-12.
    This paper aims to show that dominant conceptions of intelligence used in artificial intelligence (AI) are biased by normative assumptions that originate from the Global North, making it questionable if AI can be uncritically applied elsewhere without risking serious harm to vulnerable people. After the introduction in Sect. 1 we shortly present the history of IQ testing in Sect. 2, focusing on its multiple discriminatory biases. To determine how these biases came into existence, we define intelligence ontologically and underline its (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  19
    Richard A. Shore and Theodore A. Slaman. Defining the Turing jump. Mathematical research letters, vol. 6 , pp. 711–722. [REVIEW]Carl G. Jockusch - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):73-75.
  26.  28
    Richard A. Shore. Determining automorphisms of the recursively enumerable sets. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 65 , pp. 318– 325. - Richard A. Shore. The homogeneity conjecture. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 76 , pp. 4218– 4219. - Richard A. Shore. On homogeneity and definability in the first-order theory of the Turing degrees. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 47 , pp. 8– 16. - Richard A. Shore. The arithmetic and Turing degrees are not elementarily equivalent. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, vol. 24 , pp. 137– 139. - Richard A. Shore. The structure of the degrees of unsolvabitity. Recursion theory, edited by Anil Nerode and Richard A. Shore, Proceedings of symposia in pure mathematics, vol. 42, American Mathematical Society, Providence1985, pp. 33– 51. - Theodore A. Slaman and W. Hugh Woodin. Definability in the Turing degrees. Illinois journal of mathematics, vol. 30 , pp. 320–. [REVIEW]Carl Jockusch - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):358-360.
  27. Computing machinery and intelligence.Alan M. Turing - 1950 - Mind 59 (October):433-60.
    I propose to consider the question, "Can machines think?" This should begin with definitions of the meaning of the terms "machine" and "think." The definitions might be framed so as to reflect so far as possible the normal use of the words, but this attitude is dangerous, If the meaning of the words "machine" and "think" are to be found by examining how they are commonly used it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the meaning and the answer to (...)
    Direct download (19 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1023 citations  
  28.  15
    Review: John McCarthy, The Inversion of Functions Defined by Turing Machines. [REVIEW]Patrick C. Fischer - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):481-481.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  65
    Weaker variants of infinite time Turing machines.Matteo Bianchetti - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (3-4):335-365.
    Infinite time Turing machines represent a model of computability that extends the operations of Turing machines to transfinite ordinal time by defining the content of each cell at limit steps to be the lim sup of the sequences of previous contents of that cell. In this paper, we study a computational model obtained by replacing the lim sup rule with an ‘eventually constant’ rule: at each limit step, the value of each cell is defined if and only if (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  34
    Automorphisms in the PTIME-Turing degrees of recursive sets.Christine Ann Haught & Theodore A. Slaman - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 84 (1):139-152.
    We consider questions related to the rigidity of the structure R, the PTIME-Turing degrees of recursive sets of strings together with PTIME-Turing reducibility, pT, and related structures; do these structures have nontrivial automorphisms? We prove that there is a nontrivial automorphism of an ideal of R. This can be rephrased in terms of partial relativizations. We consider the sets which are PTIME-Turing computable from a set A, and call this class PTIMEA. Our result can be stated as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  58
    Passing loebner's Turing test: A case of conflicting discourse functions. [REVIEW]Sean Zdenek - 2001 - Minds and Machines 11 (1):53-76.
    This paper argues that the Turing test is based on a fixed and de-contextualized view of communicative competence. According to this view, a machine that passes the test will be able to communicate effectively in a variety of other situations. But the de-contextualized view ignores the relationship between language and social context, or, to put it another way, the extent to which speakers respond dynamically to variations in discourse function, formality level, social distance/solidarity among participants, and participants' relative degrees (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  34
    Implicit Definability in Arithmetic.Stephen G. Simpson - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (3):329-339.
    We consider implicit definability over the natural number system $\mathbb{N},+,\times,=$. We present a new proof of two theorems of Leo Harrington. The first theorem says that there exist implicitly definable subsets of $\mathbb{N}$ which are not explicitly definable from each other. The second theorem says that there exists a subset of $\mathbb{N}$ which is not implicitly definable but belongs to a countable, explicitly definable set of subsets of $\mathbb{N}$. Previous proofs of these theorems have used finite- (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Definability, automorphisms, and dynamic properties of computably enumerable sets.Leo Harrington & Robert I. Soare - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):199-213.
    We announce and explain recent results on the computably enumerable (c.e.) sets, especially their definability properties (as sets in the spirit of Cantor), their automorphisms (in the spirit of Felix Klein's Erlanger Programm), their dynamic properties, expressed in terms of how quickly elements enter them relative to elements entering other sets, and the Martin Invariance Conjecture on their Turing degrees, i.e., their information content with respect to relative computability (Turing reducibility).
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34.  34
    Direct and local definitions of the Turing jump.Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 7 (2):229-262.
    We show that there are Π5 formulas in the language of the Turing degrees, [Formula: see text], with ≤, ∨ and ∧, that define the relations x″ ≤ y″, x″ = y″ and so {x ∈ L2 = x ≥ y|x″ = y″} in any jump ideal containing 0. There are also Σ6&Π6 and Π8 formulas that define the relations w = x″ and w = x', respectively, in any such ideal [Formula: see text]. In the language with just (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35. Ascribing Moral Value and the Embodied Turing Test.Anthony Chemero - unknown
    What would it take for an artificial agent to be treated as having moral value? As a first step toward answering this question, we ask what it would take for an artificial agent to be capable of the sort of autonomous, adaptive social behavior that is characteristic of the animals that humans interact with. We propose that this sort of capacity is best measured by what we call the Embodied Turing Test. The Embodied Turing test is a test (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  11
    Exact pairs for the ideal of the k-trivial sequences in the Turing degrees.George Barmpalias & Rod G. Downey - 2014 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 79 (3):676-692.
    TheK-trivial sets form an ideal in the Turing degrees, which is generated by its computably enumerable members and has an exact pair below the degree of the halting problem. The question of whether it has an exact pair in the c.e. degrees was first raised in [22, Question 4.2] and later in [25, Problem 5.5.8].We give a negative answer to this question. In fact, we show the following stronger statement in the c.e. degrees. There exists aK-trivial degreedsuch that for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  31
    Spaces of orders and their Turing degree spectra.Malgorzata A. Dabkowska, Mieczyslaw K. Dabkowski, Valentina S. Harizanov & Amir A. Togha - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (9):1134-1143.
    We investigate computability theoretic and topological properties of spaces of orders on computable orderable groups. A left order on a group G is a linear order of the domain of G, which is left-invariant under the group operation. Right orders and bi-orders are defined similarly. In particular, we study groups for which the spaces of left orders are homeomorphic to the Cantor set, and their Turing degree spectra contain certain upper cones of degrees. Our approach unifies and extends Sikora’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  18
    The computational strengths of α-tape infinite time Turing machines.Benjamin Rin - 2014 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (9):1501-1511.
    In [7], open questions are raised regarding the computational strengths of so-called ∞-α -Turing machines, a family of models of computation resembling the infinite-time Turing machine model of [2], except with α -length tape . Let TαTα denote the machine model of tape length α . Define that TαTα is computationally stronger than TβTβ precisely when TαTα can compute all TβTβ-computable functions ƒ: min2→min2 plus more. The following results are found: Tω1≻TωTω1≻Tω. There are countable ordinals α such that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  50
    The machine as data: a computational view of emergence and definability.S. Barry Cooper - 2015 - Synthese 192 (7):1955-1988.
    Turing’s paper on computable numbers has played its role in underpinning different perspectives on the world of information. On the one hand, it encourages a digital ontology, with a perceived flatness of computational structure comprehensively hosting causality at the physical level and beyond. On the other, it can give an insight into the way in which higher order information arises and leads to loss of computational control—while demonstrating how the control can be re-established, in special circumstances, via suitable type (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  42
    A note on definability in fragments of arithmetic with free unary predicates.Stanislav O. Speranski - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (5-6):507-516.
    We carry out a study of definability issues in the standard models of Presburger and Skolem arithmetics (henceforth referred to simply as Presburger and Skolem arithmetics, for short, because we only deal with these models, not the theories, thus there is no risk of confusion) supplied with free unary predicates—which are strongly related to definability in the monadic SOA (second-order arithmetic) without × or + , respectively. As a consequence, we obtain a very direct proof for ${\Pi^1_1}$ -completeness of Presburger, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. Definability in the recursively enumerable degrees.André Nies, Richard A. Shore & Theodore A. Slaman - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):392-404.
    §1. Introduction. Natural sets that can be enumerated by a computable function always seem to be either actually computable or of the same complexity as the Halting Problem, the complete r.e. set K. The obvious question, first posed in Post [1944] and since then called Post's Problem is then just whether there are r.e. sets which are neither computable nor complete, i.e., neither recursive nor of the same Turing degree as K?Let be the r.e. degrees, i.e., the r.e. sets (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42. Kripke’s paradox and the Church–Turing thesis.Mark D. Sprevak - 2008 - Synthese 160 (2):285-295.
    Kripke (1982, Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) presents a rule-following paradox in terms of what we meant by our past use of “plus”, but the same paradox can be applied to any other term in natural language. Many responses to the paradox concentrate on fixing determinate meaning for “plus”, or for a small class of other natural language terms. This raises a problem: how can these particular responses be generalised to the whole of natural language? (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  55
    On the definability of the double jump in the computably enumerable sets.Peter A. Cholak & Leo A. Harrington - 2002 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 2 (02):261-296.
    We show that the double jump is definable in the computably enumerable sets. Our main result is as follows: let [Formula: see text] is the Turing degree of a [Formula: see text] set J ≥T0″}. Let [Formula: see text] such that [Formula: see text] is upward closed in [Formula: see text]. Then there is an ℒ property [Formula: see text] such that [Formula: see text] if and only if there is an A where A ≡T F and [Formula: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  44. Jumping through the transfinite: The master code hierarchy of Turing degrees.Harold T. Hodes - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):204-220.
    Where $\underline{a}$ is a Turing degree and ξ is an ordinal $ , the result of performing ξ jumps on $\underline{a},\underline{a}^{(\xi)}$ , is defined set-theoretically, using Jensen's fine-structure results. This operation appears to be the natural extension through $(\aleph_1)^{L^\underline{a}}$ of the ordinary jump operations. We describe this operation in more degree-theoretic terms, examine how much of it could be defined in degree-theoretic terms and compare it to the single jump operation.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem.Alan Turing - 1936 - Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 42 (1):230-265.
  46.  21
    Embedding finite lattices into the ideals of computably enumerable Turing degrees.William C. Calhoun & Manuel Lerman - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1791-1802.
    We show that the lattice L 20 is not embeddable into the lattice of ideals of computably enumerable Turing degrees (J). We define a structure called a pseudolattice that generalizes the notion of a lattice, and show that there is a Π 2 necessary and sufficient condition for embedding a finite pseudolattice into J.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Computing Machinery and Intelligence.Alan M. Turing - 2003 - In John Heil (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology. Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   596 citations  
  48.  15
    Alan Turing's systems of logic: the Princeton thesis.Alan Turing - 2012 - Woodstock, England: Princeton University Press. Edited by Andrew W. Appel & Solomon Feferman.
    Though less well known than his other work, Turings 1938 Princeton Thesis, this title which includes his notion of an oracle machine, has had a lasting influence on computer science and mathematics. It presents a facsimile of the original typescript of the thesis along with essays by Appel and Feferman that explain its still-unfolding significance.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  42
    Hobson’s Conception of Definable Numbers.Zhao Fan - 2020 - History and Philosophy of Logic 41 (2):128-139.
    In this paper, I explore an intriguing view of definable numbers proposed by a Cambridge mathematician Ernest Hobson, and his solution to the paradoxes of definability. Reflecting on König’s paradox and Richard’s paradox, Hobson argues that an unacceptable consequence of the paradoxes of definability is that there are numbers that are inherently incapable of finite definition. Contrast to other interpreters, Hobson analyses the problem of the paradoxes of definability lies in a dichotomy between finitely definable numbers and not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  59
    Systems of logic based on ordinals..Alan Turing - 1939 - London,: Printed by C.F. Hodgson & son.
1 — 50 / 1000