Results for 'Sanford H. Kadish'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  6
    Discretion to Disobey: A Study of Lawful Departures from Legal Rules.Mortimer Raymond Kadish & Sanford H. Kadish - 1973
  2.  11
    Respect for Life in Medicine, Philosophy, and the Law.Owsei Temkin, William K. Frankena & Sanford H. Kadish - 1977
    Lectures delivered at the Johns Hopkins University in 1975. Includes bibliographical references and index.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  17
    Discretion to Disobey: A Study of Lawful Departures from Legal Rules. By Mortimer R. Kadish & Sanford H. Kadish. Stanford University Press, Stanford, California. 1973. Pp. x, 241. $8.95. [REVIEW]R. J. Rowan - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (3):534-538.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Meir Dan-Cohen.Sanford Kadish, Andrei Marmor, Robert Posi, Eric Rakowski & Jan Vetter Jeremy Waldron - 1995 - In Andrei Marmor (ed.), Law and interpretation: essays in legal philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  37
    Fusion confusion.D. H. Sanford - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):1-4.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  6.  30
    Distinctness and non-identity.D. H. Sanford - 2005 - Analysis 65 (4):269-274.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7.  44
    Review of R eal Time.David H. Sanford - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):289.
  8.  3
    6. Self-Deception as Rationalization.David H. Sanford - 1988 - In Brian P. McLaughlin & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception. University of California Press. pp. 157-169.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  20
    From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief.David H. Sanford - 1986 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (1):149-154.
  10.  52
    If P, Then Q: Conditionals and the Foundations of Reasoning.David H. Sanford - 1989 - New York, NY, USA: Routledge.
    This new edition includes three new chapters, updating the book to take into account developments in the field over the past fifteen years.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  11.  21
    Reply to Mr. Aranyosi.D. H. Sanford - 2003 - Analysis 63 (4):305-309.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  20
    Begging the question.David H. Sanford - 1972 - Analysis 32 (6):197-199.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  13.  13
    Truth, Love and Immortality: An Introduction to McTaggart's Philosophy.David H. Sanford - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (3):445.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  55
    The Direction of Causation and the Direction of Time.David H. Sanford - 1984 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1):53-75.
    I revise J L Mackie's first account of casual direction by replacing his notion of "fixity" by a newly defined notion of "sufficing" that is designed to accommodate indeterminism. Keeping Mackie's distinction between casual order and casual direction, I then consider another revision that replaces "fixity" with "one-way conditionship". In response to the charge that all such accounts of casual priority beg the question by making an unjustified appeal to temporal priority, i maintain that one-way conditionship explains rather that assumes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  31
    Hume and the Problem of Causation.David H. Sanford - 1983 - Noûs 17 (3):502-508.
  16. Les activités du Centre National de Recherches de Logique en 1971.David H. Sanford - 1970 - Logique Et Analyse 13 (52):(1970:déc.).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  52
    Causation and Intelligibility.David H. Sanford - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (267):55 - 67.
    Hume, in "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", holds (1) that all causal reasoning is based on experience and (2) that causal reasoning is based on nothing but experience. (1) does not imply (2), and Hume's good reasons for (1) are not good reasons for (2). This essay accepts (1) and argues against (2). A priori reasoning plays a role in causal inference. Familiar examples from Hume and from classroom examples of sudden disappearances and radical changes do not show otherwise. A (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  32
    Causal Dependence and Multiplicity.David H. Sanford - 1985 - Philosophy 60 (232):215-230.
    In "Causes and "If P, Even If X, still Q," Philosophy 57 (July 1982), Ted Honderich cites my "The Direction of Causation and the Direction of Conditionship," journal of Philosophy 73 (April 22, 1976) as an example of an account of causal priority that lacks the proper character. After emending Honderich's description of the proper character, I argue that my attempt to account for one-way causation in terms of one-way causal conditionship does not totally lack it. Rather than emphasize the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  58
    McTaggart on Time.David H. Sanford - 1968 - Philosophy 43 (166):371 - 378.
    McTaggart argues that the A series, which orders events with reference to past, present, and future, involves an inescapable contradiction. The significant difference between the earlier version of his argument (Mind, 1908) and the version in The Nature of Existence, Volume II, Chapter 33 (1927), has often gone unnoticed. His arguments are all invalid; the conclusion can be rejected without rejecting any premiss. It is therefore unnecessary to adopt any philosophical thesis about time (e.g., that some token-reflexive analysis of tensed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  12
    Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes's Meditations.David H. Sanford - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (1):120.
  21.  17
    Difficulties for the Reconciling and Estranging Projects: Some Symmetries.David H. Sanford - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):240-244.
    Suppose that Susan did not go to the movies. The reconciling project attempts to show that this plus Determinism does not imply that Susan could not have gone to the movies. The estranging project attempts to show the opposite. A counter‐entailment argument is of the form A is consistent with C, and C entails not‐B, therefore A does not entail B. An instance of the counter‐entailment arguments undermines a central argument for the reconciling project. Another instance undermines a central argument (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  12
    Perception, Common Sense, and Science.David H. Sanford - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (1):163-165.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Begging the Question.David H. Sanford - 1972 - Analysis 32 (6):197-199.
    A primary purpose of argument is to increase the degree of reasonable confidence that one has in the truth of the conclusion. A question begging argument fails this purpose because it violates what W. E. Johnson called an epistemic condition of inference. Although an argument of the sort characterized by Robert Hoffman in his response (Analysis 32.2, Dec 71) to Richard Robinson (Analysis 31.4, March 71) begs the question in all circumstances, we usually understand the charge that an argument is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  24.  18
    Causal Asymmetries. [REVIEW]David H. Sanford - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1):243-246.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  25.  30
    Begging the question as involving actual belief and inconceivable without it.David H. Sanford - 1988 - Metaphilosophy 19 (1):32–37.
    This article answers John Biro's "Knowability, Believability, and Begging the Question: a Reply to Sanford" in "Metaphilosophy" 15 (1984). Biro and I agree that of two argument instances with the same form and content, one but not the other can beg the question, depending on other factors. These factors include actual beliefs, or so I maintain (against Biro) with the help of some analysed examples. Brief selections from Archbishop Whatley and J S Mill suggest that they also regard reference (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  26.  5
    Pre‐Phenomenal Adjustments and the Müller‐Lyer Illusion.David H. Sanford - 2017 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (2):199-201.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Topological Trees: G H von Wright's Theory of Possible Worlds.David H. Sanford - 1998 - In TImothy Childers (ed.), The Logica Yearbook. Acadamy of Sciences of the Czech Republic.
    In several works on modality, G. H. von Wright presents tree structures to explain possible worlds. Worlds that might have developed from an earlier world are possible relative to it. Actually possible worlds are possible relative to the world as it actually was at some point. Many logically consistent worlds are not actually possible. Transitions from node to node in a tree structure are probabilistic. Probabilities are often more useful than similarities between worlds in treating counterfactual conditionals.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. The problem of the many, many composition questions, and naive mereology.David H. Sanford - 1993 - Noûs 27 (2):219-228.
    Naive mereology studies ordinary, common-sense beliefs about part and whole. Some of the speculations in this article on naive mereology do not bear directly on Peter van Inwagen's "Material Beings". The other topics, (1) and (2), both do. (1) Here is an example of Peter Unger's "Problem of the Many". How can a table be a collection of atoms when many collections of atoms have equally strong claims to be that table? Van Inwagen invokes fuzzy sets to solve this problem. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  29.  32
    Impartial Perception.David H. Sanford - 1983 - Philosophy 58 (225):392 - 395.
    Wittgenstein remarks in the "Tractatus" that the eye is not in the visual field. I question the claim of Michael Dummett and P T Geach that reflection on this remark helps one conceive of an observer perceiving objects in space without having any location in that space. The literal meaning of "point of view" is illustrated by the visual field. Reflection on the fact that the point of view is not itself normally an object of sight is no help in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Disjunctive Predicates.David H. Sanford - 1970 - American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (2):162-170.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31. Determinates vs. determinables.David H. Sanford - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Everything red is colored, and all squares are polygons. A square is distinguished from other polygons by being four-sided, equilateral, and equiangular. What distinguishes red things from other colored things? This has been understood as a conceptual rather than scientific question. Theories of wavelengths and reflectance and sensory processing are not considered. Given just our ordinary understanding of color, it seems that what differentiates red from other colors is only redness itself. The Cambridge logician W. E. Johnson introduced the terms (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  32.  34
    Causal Dependence and Multiplicity.David H. Sanford - 1985 - Philosophy 60 (232):215-230.
    Ted Honderich's ‘Causes and If p, even if x, still q ’ contains many good points I shall not discuss. My discussion is restricted to some of the points Honderich makes about causal priority in the final two sections of his paper. He considers several proposals, new and old, for accounting for causal priority before he presents a tentativeproposal of his own. He thinks that some of these proposals, besides having difficulties peculiar to themselves, share the deficiency of lacking the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  13
    Experience and the Objects of Perception.David H. Sanford - 1987 - Noûs 21 (3):435-438.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  19
    Reinforcement aftereffects and intertrial interval.Sanford Katz, George T. Woods & Judith H. Carrithers - 1966 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 72 (4):624.
  35.  21
    Causation and Intelligibility.David H. Sanford - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (267):55-67.
    I shall venture to affirm, as a general proposition which admits of no exception, that the knowledge of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori, but arises entirely from experience, when we find that any particular objects are constantly conjoined with each other.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. The direction of causation and the direction of conditionship.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (8):193-207.
    I criticize and emend J L Mackie's account of causal priority by replacing ‘fixity’ in its central clause by 'x is a causal condition of y, but y is not a causal condition of x'. This replacement works only if 'is a causal condition of' is not a symmetric relation. Even apart from our desire to account for causal priority, it is desirable to have an account of nonsymmetric conditionship. Truth, for example, is a condition of knowledge, but knowledge is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  37.  12
    Causal Necessity and Logical Necessity.David H. Sanford - 1978 - Philosophical Studies 33 (2):185-194.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38. Infinity and vagueness.David H. Sanford - 1975 - Philosophical Review 84 (4):520-535.
    Many philosophic arguments concerned with infinite series depend on the mutual inconsistency of statements of the following five forms: (1) something exists which has R to something; (2) R is asymmetric; (3) R is transitive; (4) for any x which has R to something, there is something which has R to x; (5) only finitely many things are related by R. Such arguments are suspect if the two-place relation R in question involves any conceptual vagueness or inexactness. Traditional sorites arguments (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  39.  48
    Borderline Logic.David H. Sanford - 1975 - American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1):29-39.
    To accommodate vague statements and predicates, I propose an infinite-valued, non-truth-functional interpretation of logic on which the tautologies are exactly the tautologies of classical two-valued logic. iI introduce a determinacy operator, analogous to the necessity operator in alethic modal logic, to allow the definition of first-order and higher-order borderline cases. On the interpretation proposed for determinacy, every statement corresponding to a theorem of modal system T is a logical truth, and I conjecture that every logical truth on the interpretation corresponds (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  40. How Plausible is the Principle of Plenitude?David H. Sanford - 1978 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 59 (2):149.
    The cardinality of incompatible possibilities whose actuality requires at least N seconds exceeds the cardinality of disjoint intervals at least N seconds long. Therefore, not all logical possibilities can be actual in the long run, even if the long run is infinite.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Fusion confusion.David H. Sanford - 2003 - Analysis 63 (1):1–4.
    Two fusions can be in the same place at the same time. So long as a house made of Tinkertoys is intact, the fusion of all its Tinkertoys parts coincides with the fusion of it walls and its roof. If none of the Tinkertoys is destroyed, their fusion persists through the complete disassembly of the house. (So the house is not a fusion of its Tinkertoy parts.) The fusion of the walls and roof does not persist through the complete disassembly (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  42. Locke, Leibniz, and Wiggins on being in the same place at the same time.David H. Sanford - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (1):75-82.
    Locke thought it was a necessary truth that no two material bodies could be in the same place at the same time. Leibniz wasn't so sure. This paper sides with Leibniz. I examine the arguments of David Wiggins in defense of Locke on this point (Philosophical Review, January 1968). Wiggins’ arguments are ineffective.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43.  9
    Illusions and Sense-Data.David H. Sanford - 1981 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1):371-385.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  63
    The possibility of transparent white.David H. Sanford - 1986 - Analysis 46 (4):212.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  1
    Downing on positive and negative terms.David H. Sanford - 1970 - Analysis 30 (5):167-172.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Time may have a stop.David H. Sanford - 1969 - Analysis 29 (6):206-206.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  24
    Vague numbers.David H. Sanford - 2002 - Acta Analytica 17 (2):63-73.
    If there are vague numbers, it would be easier to use numbers as semantic values in a treatment of vagueness while avoiding precise cut-off points. When we assign a particular statement a range of values (less than 1 and greater than 0) there is no precise sharp cut-off point that locates the greatest lower bound or the least upper bound of the interval, I should like to say. Is this possible? “Vague Numbers” stands for awareness of the problem. I do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Contraries and subcontraries.David H. Sanford - 1968 - Noûs 2 (1):95-96.
    If two statements are contraries if and only if they cannot both be true, but can both be false, then some corresponding A and E categorical statements are not contraries, even on the presupposition that something exists which satisfies the subject term. For some such statements are necessarily true and thus cannot be false. There is a similar problem with subcontraries.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49. Causal necessity and logical necessity.David H. Sanford - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 28 (2):185 - 194.
    Myles Brand and Marshall Swain advocate the principle that if A is the set of conditions individually necessary and jointly sufficient for the occurrence of B, then if C is a set of conditions individually necessary for the occurrence of B, every member of C is a member of A. I agree with John Barker and Risto Hilpinen who each argue that this principle is not true for causal necessity and sufficiency, but I disagree with their claim that it is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50. The primary objects of perception.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Mind 85 (April):189-208.
    The primary objects of hearing are sounds: everything we hear we hear by hearing a sound. (This claim differs from Berkeley’s that we hear only sounds and from Aristotle’s that we only hear sounds.) Colored regions are primary objects of sight, and pressure resistant regions are primary objects of perception by touch. By definition, the primary objects of perception are physical. The properties of the primary objects of perception are exactly the properties sense-datum theories attribute to sense-data. Indirect Realism holds (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000