Results for 'Isomorphism Theorem'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  11
    The isomorphism theorem for linear fragments of continuous logic.Seyed-Mohammad Bagheri - 2021 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 67 (2):193-205.
    The ultraproduct construction is generalized to p‐ultramean constructions () by replacing ultrafilters with finitely additive measures. These constructions correspond to the linear fragments of continuous logic and are very close to the constructions in real analysis. A powermean variant of the Keisler‐Shelah isomorphism theorem is proved for. It is then proved that ‐sentences (and their approximations) are exactly those sentences of continuous logic which are preserved by such constructions. Some other applications are also given.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  8
    An isomorphism theorem for partial numberings.Dieter Spreen - 2014 - In Dieter Spreen, Hannes Diener & Vasco Brattka (eds.), Logic, Computation, Hierarchies. De Gruyter. pp. 341-382.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  42
    The semantic isomorphism theorem in abstract algebraic logic.Tommaso Moraschini - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (12):1298-1331.
  4.  18
    On Shavrukov’s Non-Isomorphism Theorem for Diagonalizable Algebras.Evgeny A. Kolmakov - 2024 - Review of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):206-243.
    We prove a strengthened version of Shavrukov’s result on the non-isomorphism of diagonalizable algebras of two $\Sigma _1$ -sound theories, based on the improvements previously found by Adamsson. We then obtain several corollaries to the strengthened result by applying it to various pairs of theories and obtain new non-isomorphism examples. In particular, we show that there are no surjective homomorphisms from the algebra $(\mathfrak {L}_T, \Box _T\Box _T)$ onto the algebra $(\mathfrak {L}_T, \Box _T)$. The case of bimodal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Isomorphism between the Peres and Penrose Proofs of the BKS Theorem in Three Dimensions.Elizabeth Gould & P. K. Aravind - 2010 - Foundations of Physics 40 (8):1096-1101.
    It is shown that the 33 complex rays in three dimensions used by Penrose to prove the Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem have the same orthogonality relations as the 33 real rays of Peres, and therefore provide an isomorphic proof of the theorem. It is further shown that the Peres and Penrose rays are just two members of a continuous three-parameter family of unitarily inequivalent rays that prove the theorem.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  80
    A theorem on the isomorphism property.Renling Jin - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1011-1017.
    An L-structure is called internally presented in a nonstandard universe if its base set and interpretation of every symbol in L are internal. A nonstandard universe is said to satisfy the κ-isomorphism property if for any two internally presented L-structures U and B, where L has less than κ many symbols, U is elementarily equivalent to B implies that U is isomorphic to B. In this paper we prove that the ℵ1-isomorphism property is equivalent to the ℵ0-isomorphism (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  18
    Partial isomorphism extension method and a represntation theorem for post‐language.Antonio Mario Sette - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19‐24):289-293.
  8.  30
    Partial Isomorphism Extension Method and a Represntation Theorem for Post‐Language.Antonio Mario Sette - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19-24):289-293.
  9.  20
    Some dichotomy theorems for isomorphism relations of countable models.Su Gao - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (2):902-922.
    Strengthening known instances of Vaught Conjecture, we prove the Glimm-Effros dichotomy theorems for countable linear orderings and for simple trees. Corollaries of the theorems answer some open questions of Friedman and Stanley in an L ω 1ω -interpretability theory. We also give a survey of this theory.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  22
    The isomorphism problem for classes of computable fields.Wesley Calvert - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (3):327-336.
    Theories of classification distinguish classes with some good structure theorem from those for which none is possible. Some classes (dense linear orders, for instance) are non-classifiable in general, but are classifiable when we consider only countable members. This paper explores such a notion for classes of computable structures by working out several examples. One motivation is to see whether some classes whose set of countable members is very complex become classifiable when we consider only computable members. We follow recent (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  11.  24
    The Isomorphism Problem for Computable Abelian p-Groups of Bounded Length.Wesley Calvert - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (1):331 - 345.
    Theories of classification distinguish classes with some good structure theorem from those for which none is possible. Some classes (dense linear orders, for instance) are non-classifiable in general, but are classifiable when we consider only countable members. This paper explores such a notion for classes of computable structures by working out a sequence of examples. We follow recent work by Goncharov and Knight in using the degree of the isomorphism problem for a class to distinguish classifiable classes from (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  12. The isomorphism of Minkowski space and the separable complex Hilbert space and its physical interpretation.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Philosophy of Science eJournal (Elsevier:SSRN) 13 (31):1-3.
    An isomorphism is built between the separable complex Hilbert space (quantum mechanics) and Minkowski space (special relativity) by meditation of quantum information (i.e. qubit by qubit). That isomorphism can be interpreted physically as the invariance between a reference frame within a system and its unambiguous counterpart out of the system. The same idea can be applied to Poincaré’s conjecture (proved by G. Perelman) hinting another way for proving it, more concise and meaningful physically. Mathematically, the isomorphism means (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  34
    An isomorphism between monoids of external embeddings: About definability in arithmetic.Mihai Prunescu - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (2):598-620.
    We use a new version of the Definability Theorem of Beth in order to unify classical theorems of Yuri Matiyasevich and Jan Denef in one structural statement. We give similar forms for other important definability results from Arithmetic and Number Theory.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  31
    The isomorphism problem for ω-automatic trees.Dietrich Kuske, Jiamou Liu & Markus Lohrey - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (1):30-48.
    The main result of this paper states that the isomorphism problem for ω-automatic trees of finite height is at least has hard as second-order arithmetic and therefore not analytical. This strengthens a recent result by Hjorth, Khoussainov, Montalbán, and Nies showing that the isomorphism problem for ω-automatic structures is not in . Moreover, assuming the continuum hypothesis CH, we can show that the isomorphism problem for ω-automatic trees of finite height is recursively equivalent with second-order arithmetic. On (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  17
    Representation Theorems for Quantales.Silvio Valentini - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (2):182-190.
    In this paper we prove that any quantale Q is a quantale of suitable relations on Q. As a consequence two isomorphism theorems are also shown with suitable sets of functions of Q into Q. These theorems are the mathematical background one needs in order to give natural and complete semantics for Linear Logic using relations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  11
    On potential isomorphism and non-structure.Taneli Huuskonen, Tapani Hyttinen & Mika Rautila - 2004 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 43 (1):85-120.
    We show in the paper that for any non-classifiable countable theory T there are non-isomorphic models and that can be forced to be isomorphic without adding subsets of small cardinality. By making suitable cardinal arithmetic assumptions we can often preserve stationary sets as well. We also study non-structure theorems relative to the Ehrenfeucht-Fraïssé game.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  27
    The Keisler–Shelah theorem for $\mathsf{QmbC}$ through semantical atomization.Thomas Macaulay Ferguson - 2020 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 28 (5):912-935.
    In this paper, we consider some contributions to the model theory of the logic of formal inconsistency $\mathsf{QmbC}$ as a reply to Walter Carnielli, Marcelo Coniglio, Rodrigo Podiacki and Tarcísio Rodrigues’ call for a ‘wider model theory.’ This call demands that we align the practices and techniques of model theory for logics of formal inconsistency as closely as possible with those employed in classical model theory. The key result is a proof that the Keisler–Shelah isomorphism theorem holds for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  9
    Keisler’s Theorem and Cardinal Invariants.Tatsuya Goto - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (2):905-917.
    We consider several variants of Keisler’s isomorphism theorem. We separate these variants by showing implications between them and cardinal invariants hypotheses. We characterize saturation hypotheses that are stronger than Keisler’s theorem with respect to models of size $\aleph _1$ and $\aleph _0$ by $\mathrm {CH}$ and $\operatorname {cov}(\mathsf {meager}) = \mathfrak {c} \land 2^{<\mathfrak {c}} = \mathfrak {c}$ respectively. We prove that Keisler’s theorem for models of size $\aleph _1$ and $\aleph _0$ implies $\mathfrak {b} = (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  31
    Boolean sentence algebras: Isomorphism constructions.William P. Hanf & Dale Myers - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):329-338.
    Associated with each first-order theory is a Boolean algebra of sentences and a Boolean space of models. Homomorphisms between the sentence algebras correspond to continuous maps between the model spaces. To what do recursive homomorphisms correspond? We introduce axiomatizable maps as the appropriate dual. For these maps we prove a Cantor-Bernstein theorem. Duality and the Cantor-Bernstein theorem are used to show that the Boolean sentence algebras of any two undecidable languages or of any two functional languages are recursively (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  13
    Elementary equivalence theorem for Pac structures.Jan Dobrowolski, Daniel Max Hoffmann & Junguk Lee - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (4):1467-1498.
    We generalize a well-known theorem binding the elementary equivalence relation on the level of PAC fields and the isomorphism type of their absolute Galois groups. Our results concern two cases: saturated PAC structures and nonsaturated PAC structures.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  31
    An extension of a theorem of zermelo.Jouko Väänänen - 2019 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 25 (2):208-212.
    We show that if $$ satisfies the first-order Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms of set theory when the membership relation is ${ \in _1}$ and also when the membership relation is ${ \in _2}$, and in both cases the formulas are allowed to contain both ${ \in _1}$ and ${ \in _2}$, then $\left \cong \left$, and the isomorphism is definable in $$. This extends Zermelo’s 1930 theorem in [6].
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  20
    A descriptive Main Gap Theorem.Francesco Mangraviti & Luca Motto Ros - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (1):2050025.
    Answering one of the main questions of [S.-D. Friedman, T. Hyttinen and V. Kulikov, Generalized descriptive set theory and classification theory, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 230 80, Chap. 7], we show that there is a tight connection between the depth of a classifiable shallow theory [Formula: see text] and the Borel rank of the isomorphism relation [Formula: see text] on its models of size [Formula: see text], for [Formula: see text] any cardinal satisfying [Formula: see text]. This is achieved (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. The Hole Argument without the notion of isomorphism.Joanna Luc - 2024 - Synthese 203 (3):1-28.
    In this paper, I argue that the Hole Argument can be formulated without using the notion of isomorphism, and for this reason it is not threatened by the criticism of Halvorson and Manchak (Br J Philos Sci, 2022. https://doi.org/10.1086/719193). Following Earman and Norton (Br J Philos Sci 38, pp. 515–525, 1987), I divide the Hole Argument into two steps: the proof of the Gauge Theorem and the transition from the Gauge Theorem to the conclusion of radical indeterminism. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  62
    Structuralism and representation theorems.George Weaver - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3):257-271.
    Much of the inspiration for structuralist approaches to mathematics can be found in the late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century program of characterizing various mathematical systems upto isomorphism. From the perspective of this program, differences between isomorphic systems are irrelevant. It is argued that a different view of the import of the differences between isomorphic systems can be obtained from the perspective of contemporary discussions of representation theorems and that from this perspective both the identification of isomorphic systems and the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  27
    Upward Morley's theorem downward.Gábor Sági & Zalán Gyenis - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (4-5):303-331.
    By a celebrated theorem of Morley, a theory T is ℵ1‐categorical if and only if it is κ‐categorical for all uncountable κ. In this paper we are taking the first steps towards extending Morley's categoricity theorem “to the finite”. In more detail, we are presenting conditions, implying that certain finite subsets of certain ℵ1‐categorical T have at most one n‐element model for each natural number (counting up to isomorphism, of course).
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  14
    A Completeness Theorem for Certain Classes of Recursive Infinitary Formulas.Christopher J. Ash & Julia F. Knight - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (2):173-181.
    We consider the following generalization of the notion of a structure recursive relative to a set X. A relational structure A is said to be a Γ-structure if for each relation symbol R, the interpretation of R in A is ∑math image relative to X, where β = Γ. We show that a certain, fairly obvious, description of classes ∑math image of recursive infinitary formulas has the property that if A is a Γ-structure and S is a further relation on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  33
    Completeness and Herbrand Theorems for Nominal Logic.James Cheney - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1):299 - 320.
    Nominal logic is a variant of first-order logic in which abstract syntax with names and binding is formalized in terms of two basic operations: name-swapping and freshness. It relies on two important principles: equivariance (validity is preserved by name-swapping), and fresh name generation ("new" or fresh names can always be chosen). It is inspired by a particular class of models for abstract syntax trees involving names and binding, drawing on ideas from Fraenkel-Mostowski set theory: finite-support models in which each value (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  40
    On the Consistency of Some Partition Theorems for Continuous Colorings, and the Structure of ℵ 1 -Dense Real Order Types.J. Steprans, Uri Abraham, Matatyahu Rubin & Saharon Shelah - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):303.
    We present some techniques in c.c.c. forcing, and apply them to prove consistency results concerning the isomorphism and embeddability relations on the family of ℵ 1 -dense sets of real numbers. In this direction we continue the work of Baumgartner [2] who proved the axiom BA stating that every two ℵ 1 -dense subsets of R are isomorphic, is consistent. We e.g. prove Con). Let K H , be the set of order types of ℵ 1 -dense homogeneous subsets (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  29.  21
    A Model Theoretical Generalization of Steinitz’s Theorem.Alexandre Martins Rodrigues & Edelcio De Souza - 2011 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 15 (1):107-110.
    Infinitary languages are used to prove that any strong isomorphism of substructures of isomorphic structures can be extended to an isomorphism of the structures. If the structures are models of a theory that has quantifier elimination, any isomorphism of substructures is strong. This theorem is a partial generalization of Steinitz’s theorem for algebraically closed fields and has as special case the analogous theorem for differentially closed fields. In this note, we announce results which will (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  34
    Topological Ramsey spaces from Fraïssé classes, Ramsey-classification theorems, and initial structures in the Tukey types of p-points.Natasha Dobrinen, José G. Mijares & Timothy Trujillo - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (7-8):733-782.
    A general method for constructing a new class of topological Ramsey spaces is presented. Members of such spaces are infinite sequences of products of Fraïssé classes of finite relational structures satisfying the Ramsey property. The Product Ramsey Theorem of Sokič is extended to equivalence relations for finite products of structures from Fraïssé classes of finite relational structures satisfying the Ramsey property and the Order-Prescribed Free Amalgamation Property. This is essential to proving Ramsey-classification theorems for equivalence relations on fronts, generalizing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31.  34
    Some results on permutation group isomorphism and categoricity.Anand Pillay & Mark D. Schlatter - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):910-914.
    We extend Morley's Theorem to show that if a theory is κ-p-categorical for some uncountable cardinal κ, it is uncountably categorical. We then discuss ω-p-categoricity and provide examples to show that similar extensions for the Baldwin-Lachlan and Lachlan Theorems are not possible.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  10
    Towards a Ryll‐Nardzewski‐type theorem for weakly oligomorphic structures.Christian Pech & Maja Pech - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (1-2):25-34.
    A structure is called weakly oligomorphic if its endomorphism monoid has only finitely many invariant relations of every arity. The goal of this paper is to show that the notions of homomorphism‐homogeneity, and weak oligomorphy are not only completely analogous to the classical notions of homogeneity and oligomorphy, but are actually closely related. We first prove a Fraïssé‐type theorem for homomorphism‐homogeneous relational structures. We then show that the countable models of the theories of countable weakly oligomorphic structures are mutually (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  9
    A Model Theoretical Generalization of Steinitz’s Theorem.Alexandre Martins Rodrigues & Edelcio de Souza - 2011 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 15 (1):107-110.
    Infinitary languages are used to prove that any strong isomorphism of substructures of isomorphic structures can be extended to an isomorphism of the structures. If the structures are models of a theory that has quantifier elimination, any isomorphism of substructures is strong. This theorem is a partial generalization of Steinitz’s theorem for algebraically closed fields and has as special case the analogous theorem for differentially closed fields. In this note, we announce results which will (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  21
    A generalized Borel-reducibility counterpart of Shelah’s main gap theorem.Tapani Hyttinen, Vadim Kulikov & Miguel Moreno - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (3-4):175-185.
    We study the κ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\kappa $$\end{document}-Borel-reducibility of isomorphism relations of complete first order theories in a countable language and show the consistency of the following: For all such theories T and T′\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$T^{\prime }$$\end{document}, if T is classifiable and T′\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$T^{\prime }$$\end{document} is not, then the isomorphism of models of T′\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  35
    An example related to Gregory’s Theorem.J. Johnson, J. F. Knight, V. Ocasio & S. VanDenDriessche - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (3-4):419-434.
    In this paper, we give an example of a complete computable infinitary theory T with countable models ${\mathcal{M}}$ and ${\mathcal{N}}$ , where ${\mathcal{N}}$ is a proper computable infinitary extension of ${\mathcal{M}}$ and T has no uncountable model. In fact, ${\mathcal{M}}$ and ${\mathcal{N}}$ are (up to isomorphism) the only models of T. Moreover, for all computable ordinals α, the computable ${\Sigma_\alpha}$ part of T is hyperarithmetical. It follows from a theorem of Gregory (JSL 38:460–470, 1972; Not Am Math Soc (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  52
    A lambda proof of the p-w theorem.Sachio Hirokawa, Yuichi Komori & Misao Nagayama - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (4):1841-1849.
    The logical system P-W is an implicational non-commutative intuitionistic logic defined by axiom schemes B = (b → c) → (a → b) → a → c, B' = (a → b) → (b → c) → a → c, I = a → a with the rules of modus ponens and substitution. The P-W problem is a problem asking whether α = β holds if α → β and β → α are both provable in P-W. The answer is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  8
    Elementary Equivalence in Positive Logic Via Prime Products.Tommaso Moraschini, Johann J. Wannenburg & Kentaro Yamamoto - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-18.
    We introduce prime products as a generalization of ultraproducts for positive logic. Prime products are shown to satisfy a version of Łoś’s Theorem restricted to positive formulas, as well as the following variant of the Keisler Isomorphism Theorem: under the generalized continuum hypothesis, two models have the same positive theory if and only if they have isomorphic prime powers of ultrapowers.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  72
    Infinitary propositional relevant languages with absurdity.Guillermo Badia - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):663-681.
    Analogues of Scott's isomorphism theorem, Karp's theorem as well as results on lack of compactness and strong completeness are established for infinitary propositional relevant logics. An "interpolation theorem" for the infinitary quantificational boolean logic L-infinity omega. holds. This yields a preservation result characterizing the expressive power of infinitary relevant languages with absurdity using the model-theoretic relation of relevant directed bisimulation as well as a Beth definability property.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  15
    Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unstable theories.Tapani Hyttinen & Heikki Tuuri - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 52 (3):203-248.
    If T is an unstable theory of cardinality <λ or countable stable theory with OTOP or countable superstable theory with DOP, λω λω1 in the superstable with DOP case) is regular and λ<λ=λ, then we construct for T strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models of cardinality λ. This can be viewed as a strong nonstructure theorem for such theories. We also consider the case when T is unsuperstable and develop further a result of Shelah about the existence of L∞,λ-equivalent nonisomorphic models (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  40. Stratified languages.A. Pétry - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (4):1366-1376.
    We consider arbitrary stratified languages. We study structures which satisfy the same stratified sentences and we obtain an extension of Keisler's Isomorphism Theorem to this situation. Then we consider operations which are definable by a stratified formula and modify the `type' of their argument by one; we prove that for such an operation F the sentence c = F(c) and the scheme $\varphi(c) \leftrightarrow \varphi(F(c))$ , where φ(x) varies among all the stratified formulas with no variable other than (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  39
    An Algebraic Characterization of Equivalent Preferential Models.Zhaohui Zhu & Rong Zhang - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3):803 - 833.
    Preferential model is one of the important semantical structures in nonmonotonic logic. This paper aims to establish an isomorphism theorem for preferential models, which gives us a purely algebraic characterization of the equivalence of preferential models. To this end, we present the notions of local similarity and local simulation. Based on these notions, two operators Δ(·) and μ(·) over preferential models are introduced and explored respectively. Together with other two existent operators ρ(·) and ΠD(·), we introduce an operator (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  24
    Language-Theoretic and Finite Relation Models for the (Full) Lambek Calculus.Christian Wurm - 2017 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 26 (2):179-214.
    We prove completeness for some language-theoretic models of the full Lambek calculus and its various fragments. First we consider syntactic concepts and syntactic concepts over regular languages, which provide a complete semantics for the full Lambek calculus \. We present a new semantics we call automata-theoretic, which combines languages and relations via closure operators which are based on automaton transitions. We establish the completeness of this semantics for the full Lambek calculus via an isomorphism theorem for the syntactic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  22
    Maximality of Logic Without Identity.Guillermo Badia, Xavier Caicedo & Carles Noguera - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):147-162.
    Lindström’s theorem obviously fails as a characterization of first-order logic without identity ( $\mathcal {L}_{\omega \omega }^{-} $ ). In this note, we provide a fix: we show that $\mathcal {L}_{\omega \omega }^{-} $ is a maximal abstract logic satisfying a weak form of the isomorphism property (suitable for identity-free languages and studied in [11]), the Löwenheim–Skolem property, and compactness. Furthermore, we show that compactness can be replaced by being recursively enumerable for validity under certain conditions. In the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  81
    Saturated models in institutions.Răzvan Diaconescu & Marius Petria - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (6):693-723.
    Saturated models constitute one of the powerful methods of conventional model theory, with many applications. Here we develop a categorical abstract model theoretic approach to saturated models within the theory of institutions. The most important consequence is that the method of saturated models becomes thus available to a multitude of logical systems from logic or from computing science. In this paper we define the concept of saturated model at an abstract institution-independent level and develop the fundamental existence and uniqueness theorems. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  49
    Quasi-subtractive varieties.Tomasz Kowalski, Francesco Paoli & Matthew Spinks - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (4):1261-1286.
    Varieties like groups, rings, or Boolean algebras have the property that, in any of their members, the lattice of congruences is isomorphic to a lattice of more manageable objects, for example normal subgroups of groups, two-sided ideals of rings, filters (or ideals) of Boolean algebras.algebraic logic can explain these phenomena at a rather satisfactory level of generality: in every member A of a τ-regular variety ������ the lattice of congruences of A is isomorphic to the lattice of deductive filters on (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46. Algebraic structures of neutrosophic triplets, neutrosophic duplets, or neutrosophic multisets. Volume I.Florentin Smarandache, Xiaohong Zhang & Mumtaz Ali - 2018 - Basel, Switzerland: MDPI. Edited by Florentin Smarandache, Xiaohong Zhang & Mumtaz Ali.
    The topics approached in the 52 papers included in this book are: neutrosophic sets; neutrosophic logic; generalized neutrosophic set; neutrosophic rough set; multigranulation neutrosophic rough set (MNRS); neutrosophic cubic sets; triangular fuzzy neutrosophic sets (TFNSs); probabilistic single-valued (interval) neutrosophic hesitant fuzzy set; neutro-homomorphism; neutrosophic computation; quantum computation; neutrosophic association rule; data mining; big data; oracle Turing machines; recursive enumerability; oracle computation; interval number; dependent degree; possibility degree; power aggregation operators; multi-criteria group decision-making (MCGDM); expert set; soft sets; LA-semihypergroups; single valued (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Algebraic structures of neutrosophic triplets, neutrosophic duplets, or neutrosophic multisets. Volume II.Florentin Smarandache, Xiaohong Zhang & Mumtaz Ali - 2019 - Basel, Switzerland: MDPI.
    The topics approached in this collection of papers are: neutrosophic sets; neutrosophic logic; generalized neutrosophic set; neutrosophic rough set; multigranulation neutrosophic rough set (MNRS); neutrosophic cubic sets; triangular fuzzy neutrosophic sets (TFNSs); probabilistic single-valued (interval) neutrosophic hesitant fuzzy set; neutro-homomorphism; neutrosophic computation; quantum computation; neutrosophic association rule; data mining; big data; oracle Turing machines; recursive enumerability; oracle computation; interval number; dependent degree; possibility degree; power aggregation operators; multi-criteria group decision-making (MCGDM); expert set; soft sets; LA-semihypergroups; single valued trapezoidal neutrosophic number; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  9
    Multi‐term π‐institutions and their equivalence.José Gil-Férez - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (5):505-526.
    The notion of a multi-term π-institution is introduced and a criterion for the equivalence of two multi-term π-institutions in terms of their categories of theories is proved. Moreover, a counterexample that shows that this criterion is false for arbitrary π-institutions is given.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Set-theoretical Invariance Criteria for Logicality.Solomon Feferman - 2010 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 51 (1):3-20.
    This is a survey of work on set-theoretical invariance criteria for logicality. It begins with a review of the Tarski-Sher thesis in terms, first, of permutation invariance over a given domain and then of isomorphism invariance across domains, both characterized by McGee in terms of definability in the language L∞,∞. It continues with a review of critiques of the Tarski-Sher thesis, and a proposal in response to one of those critiques via homomorphism invariance. That has quite divergent characterization results (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  50.  16
    Every recursive boolean algebra is isomorphic to one with incomplete atoms.Rod Downey - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 60 (3):193-206.
    The theorem of the title is proven, solving an old question of Remmel. The method of proof uses an algebraic technique of Remmel-Vaught combined with a complex tree of strategies argument where the true path is needed to figure out the final isomorphism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000