Results for 'British mathematics'

999 found
Order:
  1. The Future Of British Mathematics Teacher Education.Paul Ernest - 1992 - Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal 4.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  13
    Biobibliography of British Mathematics and Its Applications. Part II: 1701-1760. R. V. Wallis, P. J. Wallis.D. T. Whiteside - 1988 - Isis 79 (2):305-307.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  24
    Mathematics Sent Across the Channel and the Atlantic: British Mathematical Contributions to European and American Scientific Journals, 1835–1900.Sloan Evans Despeaux - 2008 - Annals of Science 65 (1):73-99.
    Summary This paper will consider the range of British participation in mathematics internationally during the nineteenth century through an analysis of British mathematical contributions to scientific journals outside of Britain. Viewing scientific papers contained in journals as significant indicators of research, we consider scientists who authored or read and responded in print to papers in a given area within a given group of journals to constitute a publication community. The extent of publication by British mathematicians in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  6
    Biobibliography of British Mathematics and Its Applications. Part II: 1701-1760 by R. V. Wallis; P. J. Wallis. [REVIEW]D. Whiteside - 1988 - Isis 79:305-307.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  11
    The Influence of Fourier on British Mathematics.John Herivel - 1973 - Centaurus 17 (1):40-57.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6.  15
    Duncan F. Gregory and Robert Leslie Ellis: second-generation reformers of British mathematics.Lukas M. Verburgt - 2018 - Intellectual History Review 28 (3):369-397.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  7
    R.V. & P.J. Wallis. Biobibliography of British Mathematics and its Applications, Part II, 1701–1760. Newcastle upon Tyne: Project for Historical Biobibliography, 1986, Pp. xxiii + 502. ISBN 1-85027-003-1. £48. [REVIEW]John Fauvel - 1989 - British Journal for the History of Science 22 (1):118-119.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  16
    Alex D. D. Craik. Mr. Hopkins' Men: Cambridge Reform and British Mathematics in the Nineteenth Century. xiv + 405 pp., illus., table, apps., bibl., indexes. New York: Springer, 2008. $49.95. [REVIEW]Karen Hunger Parshall - 2009 - Isis 100 (3):669-670.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Reviews: Mathematics and Logic-Symbols, Impossible Numbers, and Geometric Entanglements: British Algebra through the Commentaries on Newton's Universal Arithmetick. [REVIEW]Helena M. Pycior & M. Seltman - 1998 - Annals of Science 55 (4):438-439.
  10. Material mathematics : British algebra as algorithmic mathematics.Kevin Lambert - 2022 - In Morgan G. Ames & Massimo Mazzotti (eds.), Algorithmic modernity: mechanizing thought and action, 1500-2000. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Material mathematics : British algebra as algorithmic mathematics.Kevin Lambert - 2022 - In Morgan G. Ames & Massimo Mazzotti (eds.), Algorithmic modernity: mechanizing thought and action, 1500-2000. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  14
    Early Mathematical Economics: William Whewell and the British Case by James P. Henderson. [REVIEW]Margaret Schabas - 1998 - Isis 89 (1):141-142.
  13.  7
    The mathematical philosophy of Bertrand Russell: origins and development.Francisco A. Rodríguez-Consuegra - 1991 - Boston: Birkhäuser Verlag.
    Traces the development of British philosopher Russell's (1872-1970) ideas on mathematics from the 1890s to the publication of his Principles of mathematics in 1903. Draws from Russell's unpublished manuscripts, correspondence, and published works to point out the influence of Hegel, Cantor, Whitehead, Peano, and others. No index. Annotation copyrighted by Book News, Inc., Portland, OR.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  14.  20
    Robert Arthur Fairthorne. The mathematics of classification. Discussion by Agard A. B. Evans, T. H. O'Beirne, E. M. R. Ditmas, and the author. The proceedings of the British Society for International Bibliography, vol. 9 part 4 , pp. 35–42. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):158-159.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  26
    Robert Arthur Fairthorne. The mathematics of classification. Discussion by Agard A. B. Evans, T. H. O'Beirne, E. M. R. Ditmas, and the author. The proceedings of the British Society for International Bibliography, vol. 9 part 4 , pp. 35–42. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):158-159.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  21
    J. H. Woodger. From biology to mathematics. The British journal for the philosophy of science, vol. 3 , pp. 1–21.Edward E. Dawson - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):353-354.
  17. Mathematical Explanation by Law.Sam Baron - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (3):683-717.
    Call an explanation in which a non-mathematical fact is explained—in part or in whole—by mathematical facts: an extra-mathematical explanation. Such explanations have attracted a great deal of interest recently in arguments over mathematical realism. In this article, a theory of extra-mathematical explanation is developed. The theory is modelled on a deductive-nomological theory of scientific explanation. A basic DN account of extra-mathematical explanation is proposed and then redeveloped in the light of two difficulties that the basic theory faces. The final view (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  18.  7
    Metz Rudolf. Mathematical logic. A hundred years of British philosophy, by Metz Rudolf, New York and London 1938, pp. 705–726. Translation of IV 136. [REVIEW]C. H. Langford - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (4):168-168.
  19. Mathematical Explanation in Science.Alan Baker - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3):611-633.
    Does mathematics ever play an explanatory role in science? If so then this opens the way for scientific realists to argue for the existence of mathematical entities using inference to the best explanation. Elsewhere I have argued, using a case study involving the prime-numbered life cycles of periodical cicadas, that there are examples of indispensable mathematical explanations of purely physical phenomena. In this paper I respond to objections to this claim that have been made by various philosophers, and I (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  20. Mathematical Explanation beyond Explanatory Proof.William D’Alessandro - 2017 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 71 (2):581-603.
    Much recent work on mathematical explanation has presupposed that the phenomenon involves explanatory proofs in an essential way. I argue that this view, ‘proof chauvinism’, is false. I then look in some detail at the explanation of the solvability of polynomial equations provided by Galois theory, which has often been thought to revolve around an explanatory proof. The article concludes with some general worries about the effects of chauvinism on the theory of mathematical explanation. 1Introduction 2Why I Am Not a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  13
    Cottage industry or ghetto? The British Society for the History of Mathematics, 1971–1992.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1993 - Annals of Science 50 (5):483-490.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Mathematical models: Questions of trustworthiness.Adam Morton - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (4):659-674.
    I argue that the contrast between models and theories is important for public policy issues. I focus especially on the way a mathematical model explains just one aspect of the data.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  23.  92
    Is mathematical rigor necessary in physics?Kevin Davey - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):439-463.
    Many arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts that are not well-defined by the usual standards of mathematics. I argue that physicists are entitled to employ such concepts without rigorously defining them so long as they restrict the sorts of mathematical arguments in which these concepts are involved. Restrictions of this sort allow the physicist to ignore calculations involving these concepts that might lead to contradictory results. I argue that such restrictions need not be ad hoc, but can (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24.  54
    Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy (review).Daniel Sutherland - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):426-427.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 426-427 [Access article in PDF] Timothy Smiley, editor. Mathematics and Necessity: Essays in the History of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. ix + 166. Cloth, $35.00.Mathematics and Necessity contains essays by M. F. Burnyeat, Ian Hacking, and Jonathan Bennett based on lectures given to the British Academy in 1998. All concern the history of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Comparing Mathematical Explanations.Isaac Wilhelm - 2023 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (1):269-290.
    Philosophers have developed several detailed accounts of what makes some mathematical proofs explanatory. Significantly less attention has been paid, however, to what makes some proofs more explanatory than other proofs. That is problematic, since the reasons for thinking that some proofs explain are also reasons for thinking that some proofs are more explanatory than others. So in this paper, I develop an account of comparative explanation in mathematics. I propose a theory of the `at least as explanatory as' relation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Plato's philosophy of mathematics.Paul Pritchard - 1995 - Sankt Augustin: Academia Verlag.
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. ;Plato's philosophy of mathematics must be a philosophy of 4th century B.C. Greek mathematics, and cannot be understood if one is not aware that the notions involved in this mathematics differ radically from our own notions; particularly, the notion of arithmos is quite different from our notion of number. The development of the post-Renaissance notion of number brought with it a different conception of what mathematics is, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  27.  42
    A Mathematical Theory of Evidence.Glenn Shafer - 1976 - Princeton University Press.
    Degrees of belief; Dempster's rule of combination; Simple and separable support functions; The weights of evidence; Compatible frames of discernment; Support functions; The discernment of evidence; Quasi support functions; Consonance; Statistical evidence; The dual nature of probable reasoning.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   250 citations  
  28. Can Mathematics Explain Physical Phenomena?Otávio Bueno & Steven French - 2012 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (1):85-113.
    Batterman raises a number of concerns for the inferential conception of the applicability of mathematics advocated by Bueno and Colyvan. Here, we distinguish the various concerns, and indicate how they can be assuaged by paying attention to the nature of the mappings involved and emphasizing the significance of interpretation in this context. We also indicate how this conception can accommodate the examples that Batterman draws upon in his critique. Our conclusion is that ‘asymptotic reasoning’ can be straightforwardly accommodated within (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  29.  41
    The mathematical origins of nineteenth-century algebra of logic.Volker Peckhaus - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 159.
    This chapter discusses the complex conditions for the emergence of 19th-century symbolic logic. The main scope will be on the mathematical motives leading to the interest in logic; the philosophical context will be dealt with only in passing. The main object of study will be the algebra of logic in its British and German versions. Special emphasis will be laid on the systems of George Boole and above all of his German follower Ernst Schröder.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  30.  9
    Berkeley's Philosophy of Mathematics.Douglas M. Jesseph - 2010 - University of Chicago Press.
    In this first modern, critical assessment of the place of mathematics in Berkeley's philosophy and Berkeley's place in the history of mathematics, Douglas M. Jesseph provides a bold reinterpretation of Berkeley's work. Jesseph challenges the prevailing view that Berkeley's mathematical writings are peripheral to his philosophy and argues that mathematics is in fact central to his thought, developing out of his critique of abstraction. Jesseph's argument situates Berkeley's ideas within the larger historical and intellectual context of the (...)
    No categories
  31.  69
    Mathematics and the mind.Michael Redhead - 2004 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (4):731-737.
    Granted that truth is valuable we must recognize that certifiable truth is hard to come by, for example in the natural and social sciences. This paper examines the case of mathematics. As a result of the work of Gödel and Tarski we know that truth does not equate with proof. This has been used by Lucas and Penrose to argue that human minds can do things which digital computers can't, viz to know the truth of unprovable arithmetical statements. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. Mathematical Explanation: A Pythagorean Proposal.Samuel Baron - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    Mathematics appears to play an explanatory role in science. This, in turn, is thought to pave a way toward mathematical Platonism. A central challenge for mathematical Platonists, however, is to provide an account of how mathematical explanations work. I propose a property-based account: physical systems possess mathematical properties, which either guarantee the presence of other mathematical properties and, by extension, the physical states that possess them; or rule out other mathematical properties, and their associated physical states. I explain why (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  15
    Do Mathematicians Agree about Mathematical Beauty?Rentuya Sa, Lara Alcock, Matthew Inglis & Fenner Stanley Tanswell - 2024 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 15 (1):299-325.
    Mathematicians often conduct aesthetic judgements to evaluate mathematical objects such as equations or proofs. But is there a consensus about which mathematical objects are beautiful? We used a comparative judgement technique to measure aesthetic intuitions among British mathematicians, Chinese mathematicians, and British mathematics undergraduates, with the aim of assessing whether judgements of mathematical beauty are influenced by cultural differences or levels of expertise. We found aesthetic agreement both within and across these demographic groups. We conclude that judgements (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Mathematical explanation and the theory of why-questions.David Sandborg - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4):603-624.
    Van Fraassen and others have urged that judgements of explanations are relative to why-questions; explanations should be considered good in so far as they effectively answer why-questions. In this paper, I evaluate van Fraassen's theory with respect to mathematical explanation. I show that his theory cannot recognize any proofs as explanatory. I also present an example that contradicts the main thesis of the why-question approach—an explanation that appears explanatory despite its inability to answer the why-question that motivated it. This example (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  35.  47
    Mathematical Structure and Empirical Content.Michael E. Miller - unknown - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (2):511-532.
    Approaches to the interpretation of physical theories provide accounts of how physical meaning accrues to the mathematical structure of a theory. According to many standard approaches to interpretation, meaning relations are captured by maps from the mathematical structure of the theory to statements expressing its empirical content. In this article I argue that while such accounts adequately address meaning relations when exact models are available or perturbation theory converges, they do not fare as well for models that give rise to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36. Aristotle on Mathematical Truth.Phil Corkum - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (6):1057-1076.
    Both literalism, the view that mathematical objects simply exist in the empirical world, and fictionalism, the view that mathematical objects do not exist but are rather harmless fictions, have been both ascribed to Aristotle. The ascription of literalism to Aristotle, however, commits Aristotle to the unattractive view that mathematics studies but a small fragment of the physical world; and there is evidence that Aristotle would deny the literalist position that mathematical objects are perceivable. The ascription of fictionalism also faces (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  37. Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's Elements.Ian Mueller - 1981 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    A survey of Euclid's Elements, this text provides an understanding of the classical Greek conception of mathematics and its similarities to modern views as well as its differences. It focuses on philosophical, foundational, and logical questions — rather than strictly historical and mathematical issues — and features several helpful appendixes.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  38. From Mathematics to Philosophy.Hao Wang - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (2):170-174.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  39.  15
    British Acoustics and its Transformation from the 1860s to the 1910s.Ja Hyon Ku - 2006 - Annals of Science 63 (4):395-423.
    Summary Between the 1860s and the 1910s, British acoustics was transformed from an area of empirical research into a mathematically organized field. Musical motives—improving musical scales and temperaments, making better musical instruments, and understanding the nature of musical tones—were among the major driving forces of acoustical researchers in nineteenth-century Britain. The German acoustician, Helmholtz, had a major impact on British acousticians who also had extensive interactions with American and French acousticians. Rayleigh's acoustics, reflecting all these features, bore remarkable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times.M. Kline - 1978 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1):68-87.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  41. Mathematics as a Science of Patterns.Michael D. Resnik & Stewart Shapiro - 1998 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4):652-656.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  42.  2
    Oxford mathematics at a low ebb? An 1855 dispute over examination results.Christopher D. Hollings - forthcoming - Annals of Science.
    Between December 1855 and March 1856, a public dispute raged, in British national newspapers and locally published pamphlets, between two teachers at the University of Oxford: the mathematical lecturer Francis Ashpitel and Bartholomew Price, the professor of natural philosophy. The starting point for these exchanges was the particularly poor results that had come out of the final mathematics examinations in Oxford that December. Ashpitel, as one of the examiners, stood accused of setting questions that were too difficult for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  7
    Review of Address to the Mathematical and Physical Section of the British Association for the Advancement of Science at the Dover Meeting, September, 1899. [REVIEW]James McKeen Cattell - 1900 - Psychological Review 7 (1):100-101.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  8
    Menger Karl. On variables in mathematics and in natural science. The British journal for the philosophy of science, vol. 5 , pp. 134–142.Menger Karl. Variables, de diverses natures. Bulletin des sciences mathématiques, ser. 2 vol. 78 , pp. 229–234.Menger Karl. What are variables and constants? Science, vol. 123 , pp. 547–548. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (3):300-301.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  8
    Mathematical logic with special reference to the natural numbers.S. W. P. Steen - 1972 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    This book presents a comprehensive treatment of basic mathematical logic. The author's aim is to make exact the vague, intuitive notions of natural number, preciseness, and correctness, and to invent a method whereby these notions can be communicated to others and stored in the memory. He adopts a symbolic language in which ideas about natural numbers can be stated precisely and meaningfully, and then investigates the properties and limitations of this language. The treatment of mathematical concepts in the main body (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra.Jacob Klein, Eva Brann & J. Winfree Smith - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (4):374-375.
  47. The Narrow Ontic Counterfactual Account of Distinctively Mathematical Explanation.Mark Povich - 2021 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 72 (2):511-543.
    An account of distinctively mathematical explanation (DME) should satisfy three desiderata: it should account for the modal import of some DMEs; it should distinguish uses of mathematics in explanation that are distinctively mathematical from those that are not (Baron [2016]); and it should also account for the directionality of DMEs (Craver and Povich [2017]). Baron’s (forthcoming) deductive-mathematical account, because it is modelled on the deductive-nomological account, is unlikely to satisfy these desiderata. I provide a counterfactual account of DME, the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  48. Mind, Mathematics and the I gnorabimusstreit.Neil Tennant - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (4):745 – 773.
    1Certain developments in recent philosophy of mind that contemporary philosophers would regard as both novel and important were fully anticipated by writers in (or reacting to) the tradition of Nat...
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49.  36
    The Philosophy of Mathematics Education.Paul Ernest - 1991 - Falmer Press.
    Although many agree that all teaching rests on a theory of knowledge, this is an in-depth exploration of the philosophy of mathematics for education, building on the work of Lakatos and Wittgenstein.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  50.  44
    Zucker J. I.. The adequacy problem for classical logic. Journal of philosophical logic, vol. 7 , pp. 517–535.Zucker J. I. and Tragesser R. S.. The adequacy problem for inferential logic. Journal of philosophical logic, pp. 501–516.Prawitz Dag. Proofs and the meaning and completeness of the logical constants. Essays on mathematical and philosophical logic, Proceedings of the Fourth Scandinavian Logic Symposium and of the First Soviet-Finnish Logic Conference, Jyväskyla, Finland, June 29-July 6,1976, edited by Hintikka Jaakko, Niiniluoto Ilkka, and Saarinen Esa, Synthese library, vol. 122, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, and London, 1979, pp. 25–40.Prawitz Dag. Meaning and proofs: on the conflict between classical and intuitionistic logic. Theoria, vol. 43 , pp. 2–40.Dummett M. A. E.. The justification of deduction. Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. 59 , pp. 201–232.Dummett Michael. The philosophical basis of intuitionistic logic. Logic Colloquium '73, Proceedings. [REVIEW]Richard E. Grandy - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (3):689-694.
1 — 50 / 999