Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Platon, critique du matérialisme: le cas de l' Hippias majeur.Raphaël Arteau McNeil - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (3):435-458.
    ABSTRACTThe aim of this article is twofold: first, to show that, in Plato'sHippias Major,Hippias is the mouthpiece of a materialist ontology; second, to discuss the critique of this ontology. My argument is based on an interpretation ofHippias Major300b4–301e3. I begin by revealing the shortcomings of P. Woodruff's and I. Ludlam's interpretations. Next, I define the concept of materialism as it was understood in ancient Greece in order to outline the specificity of Hippias' materialism. Finally, I argue that the opposition between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dummett on abstract objects.George Duke - 2012 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    This book offers an historically-informed critical assessment of Dummett's account of abstract objects, examining in detail some of the Fregean presuppositions whilst also engaging with recent work on the problem of abstract entities.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematics and Its Applications, A Transcendental-Idealist Perspective.Jairo José da Silva - 2017 - Cham: Springer.
    This monograph offers a fresh perspective on the applicability of mathematics in science. It explores what mathematics must be so that its applications to the empirical world do not constitute a mystery. In the process, readers are presented with a new version of mathematical structuralism. The author details a philosophy of mathematics in which the problem of its applicability, particularly in physics, in all its forms can be explained and justified. Chapters cover: mathematics as a formal science, mathematical ontology: what (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Merleau-Ponty and the transcendental problem of bodily agency.Rasmus Thybo Jensen - 2013 - In Rasmus Thybo Jensen & Dermot Moran (eds.), The Phenomenology of Embodied Subjectivity, Contributions to Phenomenology 71. Springer. pp. 43-61.
    I argue that we find the articulation of a problem concerning bodily agency in the early works of the Merleau-Ponty which he explicates as analogous to what he explicitly calls the problem of perception. The problem of perception is the problem of seeing how we can have the object given in person through it perspectival appearances. The problem concerning bodily agency is the problem of seeing how our bodily movements can be the direct manifestation of a person’s intentions in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Crisis of the Form. The Paradox of Modern Logic and its Meaning for Phenomenology.Gabriele Baratelli - 2023 - Husserl Studies 40 (1):25-44.
    The goal of this paper is to provide an account of the role played by logic in the context of what Husserl names the “crisis of European sciences.” Presupposing the analyses offered in the Krisis, I look at Formale und Transzendentale Logik to demonstrate that the crisis of logic stems from the deviation of its original meaning as a “theory of science” and from its restriction to a mere “theoretical technique.” Through a comparison between Aristotelian syllogistic and modern logic, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locke's Aristotelian theory of quantity.Anat Schechtman - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 107 (2):337-356.
    John Locke’s treatment of quantity in the Essay Concerning Human Understanding is not nearly as extensive or as well-known as his treatment of quality and his distinction between primary and secondary qualities. Yet I contend that a close examination of Locke’s comments on quantity in the Essay reveals that he endorses a general theory of quantity that not only distinguishes quantities from qualities, but also plays several other important roles in his overall philosophy—particularly in his treatments of infinity and demonstrative (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemology Versus Ontology: Essays on the Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics in Honour of Per Martin-Löf.Peter Dybjer, Sten Lindström, Erik Palmgren & Göran Sundholm (eds.) - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book brings together philosophers, mathematicians and logicians to penetrate important problems in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. In philosophy, one has been concerned with the opposition between constructivism and classical mathematics and the different ontological and epistemological views that are reflected in this opposition. The dominant foundational framework for current mathematics is classical logic and set theory with the axiom of choice. This framework is, however, laden with philosophical difficulties. One important alternative foundational programme that is actively pursued (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy, Vintage Enthusiasms: Essays in Honour of John L. Bell.David DeVidi, Michael Hallett & Peter Clark (eds.) - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The volume includes twenty-five research papers presented as gifts to John L. Bell to celebrate his 60th birthday by colleagues, former students, friends and admirers. Like Bell’s own work, the contributions cross boundaries into several inter-related fields. The contributions are new work by highly respected figures, several of whom are among the key figures in their fields. Some examples: in foundations of maths and logic ; analytical philosophy, philosophy of science, philosophy of mathematics and decision theory and foundations of economics. (...)
    No categories
  • Technology, knowledge, governance: The political relevance of Husserl’s critique of the epistemic effects of formalization.Peter Woelert - 2013 - Continental Philosophy Review 46 (4):487-507.
    This paper explores the political import of Husserl’s critical discussion of the epistemic effects of the formalization of rational thinking. More specifically, it argues that this discussion is of direct relevance to make sense of the pervasive processes of ‘technization’, that is, of a mechanistic and superficial generation and use of knowledge, to be observed in current contexts of governance. Building upon Husserl’s understanding of formalization as a symbolic technique for abstraction in the thinking with and about numbers, I argue (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Husserl on symbolic technologies and meaning-constitution: A critical inquiry.Peter Woelert - 2017 - Continental Philosophy Review 50 (3):289-310.
    This paper reconstructs and critically analyzes Husserl’s philosophical engagement with symbolic technologies—those material artifacts and cultural devices that serve to aid, structure and guide processes of thinking. Identifying and exploring a range of tensions in Husserl’s conception of symbolic technologies, I argue that this conception is limited in several ways, and particularly with regard to the task of accounting for the more constructive role these technologies play in processes of meaning-constitution. At the same time, this paper shows that a critical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Idealization and external symbolic storage: the epistemic and technical dimensions of theoretic cognition.Peter Woelert - 2012 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 11 (3):335-366.
    This paper explores some of the constructive dimensions and specifics of human theoretic cognition, combining perspectives from (Husserlian) genetic phenomenology and distributed cognition approaches. I further consult recent psychological research concerning spatial and numerical cognition. The focus is on the nexus between the theoretic development of abstract, idealized geometrical and mathematical notions of space and the development and effective use of environmental cognitive support systems. In my discussion, I show that the evolution of the theoretic cognition of space apparently follows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Governing Knowledge: The Formalization Dilemma in the Governance of the Public Sciences.Peter Woelert - 2015 - Minerva 53 (1):1-19.
    This paper offers a conceptually novel contribution to the understanding of the distinctive governance challenges arising from the increasing reliance on formalized knowledge in the governance of research activities. It uses the current Australian research governance system as an example – a system which exhibits a comparatively strong degree of formalization as to its knowledge mechanisms. Combining theoretical reflections on the political-administrative and epistemic dimensions of processes of formalization with analyses of interview data gathered at Australian universities, it is suggested (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Mimetic Style in Plato's Republic.Russell Winslow - 2012 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 45 (1):46-64.
    In book 3 of his Republic, Plato has Socrates undertake an assessment of the educational curriculum that the city (which is being constructed by him in speech) will implement for its youth. Consequently we see that Socrates assigns to poetry a crucial importance; by their imitation of it, poetry shapes the citizens with an initial formation, casts them within a certain orientation, and places them on a path leading in an already conceived direction, toward some unarticulated good. Thus, in forming (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tom Rockmore. German Idealism as Constructivism. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2016. ISBN 978-0-22-634990-9 (hbk). Pp. x + 203. £30.00. [REVIEW]Paul T. Wilford - 2020 - Hegel Bulletin 41 (1):141-146.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant and real numbers.Mark van Atten - unknown
    Kant held that under the concept of √2 falls a geometrical magnitude, but not a number. In particular, he explicitly distinguished this root from potentially infinite converging sequences of rationals. Like Kant, Brouwer based his foundations of mathematics on the a priori intuition of time, but unlike Kant, Brouwer did identify this root with a potentially infinite sequence. In this paper I discuss the systematical reasons why in Kant's philosophy this identification is impossible.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Problem of University Courses on Infinitesimal Calculus and Their Demarcation from Infinitesimal Calculus in High Schools.Otto Toeplitz - 2015 - Science in Context 28 (2):297-310.
    When the Association of German Scientists and Physicians last met in Düsseldorf exactly twenty-eight years ago on September 24, a debate took place following lectures by Felix Klein and Alfred Pringsheim on roughly the same topic to which I would like to direct your attention today. The printed report of the Düsseldorf debate only remarked that, “It is not possible to go into details here,” so one can only guess how two of the most powerful teacher personalities among German mathematicians (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Framework for Defining the Generality of Diophantos' Methods in "Arithmetica".Yannis Thomaidis - 2005 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 59 (6):591-640.
    Diophantos' solutions to the problems of Arithmetica have been the object of extensive reading and interpretation in modern times, especially from the point of view of identifying ``hidden steps'' or ``general methods''. In this paper, after examining the relevance of various interpretations given for the famous problem II 8 in the context of modern algebra or geometry, we focus on a close reading of the ancient text of some problems of Arithmetica in order to investigate Diophantos' solving practices. This inquiry (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein and Stenlund on Mathematical Symbolism.Martin Gullvåg Sætre - 2023 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 12.
    In recent work, Sören Stenlund (2015) contextualizes Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics as aligned with the tradition of symbolic mathematics. In the early modern era, mathematicians began using purely formal methods disconnected from any obvious empirical applications, transforming their subject into a symbolic discipline. With this, Stenlund argues, they were freeing themselves of ancient ontological presuppositions and discovering the ultimately autonomous nature of mathematical symbolism, which eventually formed the basis for Wittgenstein’s thinking. A crucial premise of Wittgenstein’s philosophy of mathematics, on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Μονάς and ψυχή in the Phaedo.Sophia Stone - 2018 - Plato Journal 18:55-69.
    The paper analyzes the final proof with Greek mathematics and the possibility of intermediates in the Phaedo. The final proof in Plato’s Phaedo depends on a claim at 105c6, that μονάς, ‘unit’, generates περιττός ‘odd’ in number. So, ψυχή ‘soul’ generates ζωή ‘life’ in a body, at 105c10-11. Yet commentators disagree how to understand these mathematical terms and their relation to the soul in Plato’s arguments. The Greek mathematicians understood odd numbers in one of two ways: either that which is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Origin of Symbolic Mathematics and Its Significance for Wittgenstein’s Thought.Sören Stenlund - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (1):7-92.
    The main topic of this essay is symbolic mathematics or the method of symbolic construction, which I trace to the end of the sixteenth century when Franciscus Vieta invented the algebraic symbolism and started to use the word ‘symbolic’ in the relevant, non-ontological sense. This approach has played an important role for many of the great inventions in modern mathematics such as the introduction of the decimal place-value system of numeration, Descartes’ analytic geometry, and Leibniz’s infinitesimal calculus. It was also (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • La filosofía de las matemáticas de Aristóteles.Miguel Martí Sánchez - 2016 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 52:43-66.
    La filosofía de las matemáticas de Aristóteles es una investigación acerca de tres asuntos diferentes pero complementarios: el lugar epistemológico de las matemáticas en el organigrama de las ciencias teoréticas o especulativas; el estudio del método usado por el matemático para elaborar sus doctrinas, sobre todo la geometría y la aritmética; y la averiguación del estatuto ontológico de las entidades matemáticas. Para comprender lo peculiar de la doctrina aristotélica es necesario tener en cuenta que su principal interés está en poner (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situating the Debate on “Geometrical Algebra” within the Framework of Premodern Algebra.Michalis Sialaros & Jean Christianidis - 2016 - Science in Context 29 (2):129-150.
    ArgumentThe aim of this paper is to employ the newly contextualized historiographical category of “premodern algebra” in order to revisit the arguably most controversial topic of the last decades in the field of Greek mathematics, namely the debate on “geometrical algebra.” Within this framework, we shift focus from the discrepancy among the views expressed in the debate to some of the historiographical assumptions and methodological approaches that the opposing sides shared. Moreover, by using a series of propositions related toElem.II.5 as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Identity, indiscernibility, and Ante Rem structuralism: The tale of I and –I.Stewart Shapiro - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):285-309.
    Some authors have claimed that ante rem structuralism has problems with structures that have indiscernible places. In response, I argue that there is no requirement that mathematical objects be individuated in a non-trivial way. Metaphysical principles and intuitions to the contrary do not stand up to ordinary mathematical practice, which presupposes an identity relation that, in a sense, cannot be defined. In complex analysis, the two square roots of –1 are indiscernible: anything true of one of them is true of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Strategies for conceptual change: Ratio and proportion in classical Greek mathematics.Paul Rusnock & Paul Thagard - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (1):107-131.
    …all men begin… by wondering that things are as they are…as they do about…the incommensurability of the diagonal of the square with the side; for it seems wonderful to all who have not yet seen the reason, that there is a thing which cannot be measured even by the smallest unit. But we must end in the contrary and, according to the proverb, the better state, as is the case in these instances too when men learn the cause; for there (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Introduction: The Idiosyncratic Nature of Renaissance Mathematics.Paolo Rossini - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (3):353-357.
    Ever since its foundation in 1540, the Society of Jesus had had one mission—to restore order where Luther, Calvin and the other instigators of the Reformation had brought chaos. To stop the hemorrhage of believers, the Jesuits needed to form a united front. No signs of internal disagreement could to be shown to the outside world, lest the congregation lose its credibility. But in 1570s two prominent Jesuits, Cristophorus Clavius and Benito Perera, had engaged in a bitter controversy. The issue (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical naturalism: An anthropological perspective.Stephen Pollard & Robert Bates Graber - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (3):427-441.
  • Mathematical Naturalism: An Anthropological Perspective.Stephen Pollard & Robert Bates Graber - 1989 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 27 (3):427-441.
  • Irrational “Coefficients” in Renaissance Algebra.Jeffrey A. Oaks - 2017 - Science in Context 30 (2):141-172.
    ArgumentFrom the time of al-Khwārizmī in the ninth century to the beginning of the sixteenth century algebraists did not allow irrational numbers to serve as coefficients. To multiply$\sqrt {18} $byx, for instance, the result was expressed as the rhetorical equivalent of$\sqrt {18{x^2}} $. The reason for this practice has to do with the premodern concept of a monomial. The coefficient, or “number,” of a term was thought of as how many of that term are present, and not as the scalar (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • François Viète’s revolution in algebra.Jeffrey A. Oaks - 2018 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 (3):245-302.
    Françios Viète was a geometer in search of better techniques for astronomical calculation. Through his theorem on angular sections he found a use for higher-dimensional geometric magnitudes which allowed him to create an algebra for geometry. We show that unlike traditional numerical algebra, the knowns and unknowns in Viète’s logistice speciosa are the relative sizes of non-arithmetized magnitudes in which the “calculations” must respect dimension. Along with this foundational shift Viète adopted a radically new notation based in Greek geometric equalities. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein, formalism, and symbolic mathematics.Anderson Luis Nakano - 2020 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 61 (145):31-53.
    ABSTRACT In a recent essay, Sören Stenlund tries to align Wittgenstein’s approach to the foundations and nature of mathematics with the tradition of symbolic mathematics. The characterization of symbolic mathematics made by Stenlund, according to which mathematics is logically separated from its external applications, brings it closer to the formalist position. This raises naturally the question whether Wittgenstein holds a formalist position in philosophy of mathematics. The aim of this paper is to give a negative answer to this question, defending (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How to Define a Number? A General Epistemological Account of Simon Stevin’s Art of Defining.Jurgen Naets - 2010 - Topoi 29 (1):77-86.
    This paper explores Simon Stevin’s l’Arithmétique of 1585, where we find a novel understanding of the concept of number. I will discuss the dynamics between his practice and philosophy of mathematics, and put it in the context of his general epistemological attitude. Subsequently, I will take a close look at his justificational concerns, and at how these are reflected in his inductive, a postiori and structuralist approach to investigating the numerical field. I will argue that Stevin’s renewed conceptualisation of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On some academic theories of mathematical objects.Ian Mueller - 1986 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 106:111-120.
    In his critical study of Speusippus Leonardo Tarán (T.) expounds an interpretation of a considerable part of the controversial books M and N of Aristotle's Metaphysics. In this essay I want to consider three aspects of the interpretation, the account of Plato's ‘ideal numbers’ (section I), the account of Speusippus’ mathematical ontology (section II), and the account of the principles of that ontology (section III). T. builds his interpretation squarely on the work of Harold Cherniss (C.), to whom I will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Syrianus on the Platonic Tradition of the Separate Existence of Numbers.Melina G. Mouzala - 2015 - Peitho 6 (1):167-194.
    This paper analyzes and explains certain parts of Syrianus’s Commentary on book M of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, which details Syrianus’s response to Aristotle’s attack against the Platonic position of the separate existence of numbers. Syrianus defends the separate existence not only of eidetic but also of mathematical numbers, following a line of argumentation which involves a hylomorphic approach to the latter. He proceeds with an analysis of the mathematical number into matter and form, but his interpretation entails that form is the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conjecture.B. Mazur - 1997 - Synthese 111 (2):197-210.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A new begriffsschrift (II).John P. Mayberry - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4):329-358.
  • A Trivial Source of Wonder : Some Mathematical Examples in Plato’s Dialogues.Laura Marongiu - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    The purpose of this paper is to reassess some mathematical examples in Plato’s dialogues which at a first glance may appear to be nothing more than trivial puzzles. In order to provide the necessary background for this analysis, I shall begin by sketching a brief overview of Plato’s mathematical passages and discuss the criteria for aptly selecting them. Second, I shall explain what I mean by ‘mathematical examples,’ and reflect on their function in light of the discussion on παραδείγματα outlined (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Re‐Examining Descartes’ Algebra and Geometry: An Account Based on the Reguale.Cathay Liu - 2017 - Analytic Philosophy 58 (1):29-57.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem: Mathematization as Exploration.Johannes Lenhard & Michael Otte - 2018 - Foundations of Science 23 (4):719-737.
    This paper discerns two types of mathematization, a foundational and an explorative one. The foundational perspective is well-established, but we argue that the explorative type is essential when approaching the problem of applicability and how it influences our conception of mathematics. The first part of the paper argues that a philosophical transformation made explorative mathematization possible. This transformation took place in early modernity when sense acquired partial independence from reference. The second part of the paper discusses a series of examples (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The history of algebra and the development of the form of its language.Ladislav Kvasz - 2006 - Philosophia Mathematica 14 (3):287-317.
    This paper offers an epistemological reconstruction of the historical development of algebra from al-Khwrizm, Cardano, and Descartes to Euler, Lagrange, and Galois. In the reconstruction it interprets the algebraic formulas as a symbolic language and analyzes the changes of this language in the course of history. It turns out that the most fundamental epistemological changes in the development of algebra can be interpreted as changes of the pictorial form of the symbolic language of algebra. Thus the paper develops further the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Descartes' psychology of vision and cognitive science: The optics (1637) in the light of Marr's (1982) vision.Geir kirkebøen - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (2):161 – 182.
    In this paper I consider the relation between Descartes' psychology of vision and the cognitive science approach to psychology (henceforth CS). In particular, I examine Descartes' the Optics (1637) in the light of David Marr's (1982) position in CS. My general claim is that CS can be seen as a rediscovery of Descartes' psychology of vision. In the first section, I point to a parallel between Descartes' epistemological revolution, which created the modem version of the problem of perception, and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does Frege Have Aristotle's Number?Emily Katz - 2023 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 9 (1):135-153.
    Frege argues that number is so unlike the things we accept as properties of external objects that it cannot be such a property. In particular, (1) number is arbitrary in a way that qualities are not, and (2) number is not predicated of its subjects in the way that qualities are. Most Aristotle scholars suppose either that Frege has refuted Aristotle's number theory or that Aristotle avoids Frege's objections by not making numbers properties of external objects. This has led some (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Positional value and linguistic recursion.John Kadvany - 2007 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 35 (5-6):487-520.
  • Phenomenology as a critique of politics.Hwa Yol Jung - 1982 - Human Studies 5 (1):161 - 181.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A hermeneutical accent on the conduct of political inquiry.Hwa Yol Jung - 1978 - Human Studies 1 (1):48 - 82.
  • Hobbes and Mathematical Method.Douglas M. Jesseph - 1993 - Perspectives on Science 1 (1993):306-341.
    This article examines Hobbes’s conception of mathematical method, situating his methodological writings in the context of disputed mathematical issues of the seventeenth century. After a brief exposition of the Hobbesian philosophy of mathematics, it investigates Hobbes’s attempts to resolve three important mathematical controversies of the seventeenth century: the debates over the status of analytic geometry, disputes over the nature of ratios, and the problem of the “angle of contact” between a curve and tangent. In the course of these investigations, Hobbes’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristotle on Time, Plurality and Continuity.Jean-Louis Hudry - 2009 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 12 (1):190-205.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Post-Husserl Husserlian Phenomenological Epistemology: Seebohm on History as a Science and the System of Sciences.Burt C. Hopkins - 2021 - Husserl Studies 38 (1):67-85.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Klein and Derrida on the Historicity of Meaning and the Meaning of Historicity in Husserl's Crisis-Texts.Burt C. Hopkins - 2005 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 36 (2):179-187.
  • Dallas Willard’s Contribution to Phenomenology.Burt C. Hopkins - 2019 - Husserl Studies 35 (2):117-130.
    Dallas Willard’s contribution to phenomenology is presented in terms of his articles on, and translations into English of, Edmund Husserl’s early philosophical writings, which single-handedly prevented them from falling into oblivion, both literally and philosophically. Willard’s account of Husserl’s “negative critique” of formalized logic in those writings, and argument for its contemporary relevance, is presented and largely endorsed.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dallas Willard’s Contribution to Phenomenology.Burt C. Hopkins - 2019 - Husserl Studies 35 (2):117-130.
    Dallas Willard’s contribution to phenomenology is presented in terms of his articles on, and translations into English of, Edmund Husserl’s early philosophical writings, which single-handedly prevented them from falling into oblivion, both literally and philosophically. Willard’s account of Husserl’s “negative critique” of formalized logic in those writings, and argument for its contemporary relevance, is presented and largely endorsed.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark