Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Behavior and fitness.Douglass H. Morse - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):141-141.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hominids, coalitions, and weapons: Not vehicles.Jim Moore - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):632-632.
  • Gricean Communication, Joint Action, and the Evolution of Cooperation.Richard Moore - 2018 - Topoi 37 (2):329-341.
    It is sometimes claimed that Gricean communication is necessarily a form of cooperative or ‘joint’ action. A consequence of this Cooperative Communication View is that Gricean communication could not itself contribute to an explanation of the possibility of joint action. I argue that even though Gricean communication is often a form of joint action, it is not necessarily so—since it does not always require intentional action on the part of a hearer. Rejecting the Cooperative Communication View has attractive consequences for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Evolution and impulsiveness.Jay Moore - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):691-691.
  • The comparative approach to understanding central pattern generators.Stacia Moffett - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):558-559.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Identity and the Evolution of Societies.Mark W. Moffett - 2013 - Human Nature 24 (3):219-267.
    Human societies are examined as distinct and coherent groups. This trait is most parsimoniously considered a deeply rooted part of our ancestry rather than a recent cultural invention. Our species is the only vertebrate with society memberships of significantly more than 200. We accomplish this by using society-specific labels to identify members, in what I call an anonymous society. I propose that the human brain has evolved to permit not only the close relationships described by the social brain hypothesis, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Wright and Taylor: Empiricist teleology.Arthur J. Minton - 1975 - Philosophy of Science 42 (3):299-306.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Expectancy bias as sole or partial account of selective associations?Susan Mineka & Michael Cook - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):307-309.
    Davey reviews evidence purporting to distinguish between two accounts of selective associations – expectancy bias and evolved predispositions, although these hypotheses largely apply to different levels of causal analysis. Criticisms of primate studies in which subjects lack prior exposure to stimuli seem uncompelling. Expectancies may sometimes serve as proximal mediators in selective associations, but other factors, both proximate and ultimate, are clearly also involved.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Teleosemantics and the frogs.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 2024 - Mind and Language 39 (1):52-60.
    Some have thought that the plausibility of teleosemantics requires that it yield a determinate answer to the question of what the semantic “content” is of the “representation” triggered in the optic nerve of a frog that spots a fly. An outsize literature has resulted in which, unfortunately, a number of serious confusions and omissions that concern the way teleosemantics would have to work have appeared and been passed on uncorrected leaving a distorted and simplistic picture of the teleosemantic position. I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sex and sensibility: The role of social selection: Roughgarden, Joan: The genial gene: Deconstructing Darwinian selfishness. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2009, ix+261pp, $40.00 HB, $18.95 PB.Erika L. Milam, Roberta L. Millstein, Angela Potochnik & Joan E. Roughgarden - 2010 - Metascience 20 (2):253-277.
    Sex and sensibility: The role of social selection Content Type Journal Article DOI 10.1007/s11016-010-9464-6 Authors Erika L. Milam, Department of History, University of Maryland, 2115 Francis Scott Key Hall, College Park, MD 20742, USA Roberta L. Millstein, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Davis, One Shields Avenue, Davis, CA 95616, USA Angela Potochnik, Department of Philosophy, University of Cincinnati, P.O. Box 210374, Cincinnati, OH 45221, USA Joan E. Roughgarden, Department of Biology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305-5020, USA Journal Metascience Online (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Purpose and conditioning: A reply to Waller.John A. Mills - 1984 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 14 (3):363–367.
  • Nonlinear experiential influences on the development of fear reactions.David B. Miller - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):306-307.
    Failure to find an obvious or linear relationship between a developmental experiential factor and a developmental outcome often leads investigators to posit concepts such as “biological preparedness” and “evolved predispositions” that allude to hypothetical geneticmechanisms that may not exist. However, experiential nonlinearities alone may explain the development of certain instinctive behaviors, as shown by studies on alarm call responsivity in mallard ducklings.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Liberty, the higher pleasures, and mill's missing science of ethnic jokes.Elijah Millgram - 2009 - Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1):326-353.
    Aggregation-friendly moral theories such as classical utilitarianism are forced to invest a great deal of ingenuity in damping out and modulating the effects of welfare aggregation. In Mill's treatment, the problem famously appears as the puzzle of how the Principle of Liberty is meant to be compatible with the Principle of Utility, and there have been a great many attempted interpretations of his solution, all, in my view, unsatisfactory. I will first reconstruct Mill's generally unnoticed account of the psychological implementation (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond shared fate: Group-selected mechanisms for cooperation and competition in fuzzy, fluid vehicles.Geoffrey F. Miller - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):630-631.
  • Beyond interactionism: A transactional approach to behavioral development.David B. Miller - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):641-642.
  • A small fly in some beneficial ointment.P. M. Milner - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):632-633.
  • An assessment of Skinner's theory of animal behavior.John A. Mills - 1988 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 18 (2):197–218.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What are the chemical characteristics of brain mechanisms for aggression?Klaus A. Miczek - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):224-225.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simple or complex systems?R. Christopher Miall - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):734-734.
  • Single-cell versus network properties and the use of models.Michael Merickel - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):557-557.
  • Enhanced processing of threatening stimuli: The case of face recognition.Linda Mealey - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):304-305.
    Because of their evolutionary importance, threat-detection mechanisms are likely to exist at a variety of levels. A recent study of face recognition suggests that novel stimuli receive enhanced processing when presented as fear-related. This suggests the existence of a complex, context-dependent threat-detection mechanism that can adaptively respond to spatiotemporally varying and unique environmental features.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are monkeys nomothetic or idiographic?Linda Mealey - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):161-161.
  • On the functions relating delay, reinforcer value, and behavior.James E. Mazur & R. J. Herrnstein - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):690-691.
  • Are we asking too much of the stretch reflex?Peter B. C. Matthews - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):614-615.
  • Time-based objective coding and human nonverbal behavior.Roger D. Masters - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):284-285.
  • Avoidance behavior: Assumptions, theory, and metatheory.Fred A. Masterson & Mary Crawford - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):685-696.
  • The ethology of neuroethology.Hubert Markl - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):396-397.
  • Semiotic modeling of mimicry with reference to brood parasitism.Timo Maran - 2010 - Sign Systems Studies 38 (1/4):349-376.
    Biological mimicry can be considered as having a double-layered structure: there is a layer of ecological relations between species and there is a layer of semiotic relations of the sign. The present article demonstrates the limitations of triadic models and typologies of mimicry, as well as their lack of correspondence to mimicry as it actually occurs in nature. It is argued that more dynamical semiotic tools are needed to describe mimicry in a theoretically coherent way that would at the same (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philosophy as an open meta‐science of interdisciplinary cross‐induction.Magoroh Maruyama - 1962 - Dialectica 16 (4):361-384.
  • Neuroethology: Not losing sight of behaviour.Aubrey Manning - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):395-396.
  • Dynamic theories of behavior.Marc Mangel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):139-141.
  • Innateness and the sciences.Matteo Mameli & Patrick Bateson - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (2):155-188.
    The concept of innateness is a part of folk wisdom but is also used by biologists and cognitive scientists. This concept has a legitimate role to play in science only if the colloquial usage relates to a coherent body of evidence. We examine many different candidates for the post of scientific successor of the folk concept of innateness. We argue that none of these candidates is entirely satisfactory. Some of the candidates are more interesting and useful than others, but the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Needed: More data on the reticular information.Robert B. Malmo & Helen P. Malmo - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):485-486.
  • A fourth approach to the study of learning: Are “processes” really necessary?John C. Malone - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):151-152.
  • Where's the action?N. J. Mackintosh - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):631-631.
  • We are making good progress in the neural analysis of behaviour.David L. Macmillan - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (3):395-395.
  • Propulsive Torques and Adaptive Reflexes.William A. MacKay - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):614-614.
  • Joint torque precedes the kinematic end result.William A. MacKay - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):283-284.
  • Group evolutionary strategies: Dimensions and mechanisms.Kevin MacDonald - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):629-630.
  • Effortful control, explicit processing, and the regulation of human evolved predispositions.Kevin B. MacDonald - 2008 - Psychological Review 115 (4):1012-1031.
  • Behavioral plasticity, serial order, and the motor program.Donald G. MacKay - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):630-631.
  • Somewhere in time – temporal factors in vertebrate movement analysis.Melvin Lyon - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):282-283.
  • Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology—II. The return to representation.William Lyons - 1991 - Philosophical Psychology 4 (1):83-102.
    Abstract In rounded terms and modern dress a theory of intentionality is a theory about how humans take in information via the senses and in the very process of taking it in understand it and, most often, make subsequent use of it in guiding human behaviour. The problem of intentionality in this century has been the problem of providing an adequate explanation of how a purely physical causal system, the brain, can both receive information and at the same time understand (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The awakened brain: From Wright's psychozoology to Barkow's selfless persons.David Paul Lumsden - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):311-312.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Darwin’s Other Dilemmas and the Theoretical Roots of Emotional Connection.Robert J. Ludwig & Martha G. Welch - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Modern scientific theories of emotional behavior, almost without exception, trace their origin to Charles Darwin, and his publications On the Origin of Species (1859) and The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (1872). The most famous evolutionary dilemma Darwin acknowledged as a challenge to his theory of natural selection was the incomplete sub Cambrian fossil record. However, Darwin struggled with two other rarely referenced theoretical and scientific dilemmas that confounded his theories about emotional behavior. These included (1) the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Central pattern generators and sensory input.J. V. Luco - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):557-557.
  • On the origins of selves and self-control.C. Fergus Lowe & Pauline J. Home - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):689-690.
  • Why are phobias irrational?Peter F. Lovibond, David A. T. Siddle & Nigel W. Bond - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):303-303.
    We endorse Davey's view that expectancy processes are intimately involved in fear reactions, but question his model on three grounds. First, the mechanism for generating expectancy bias to both ontogenetic and phylogenetic stimuli is not spelled out. Second, the selective association component is unnecessary. Third, the model fails to provide a clear explanation for the irrationality of phobic reactions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Working toward the big reinforcer: Integration.A. W. Logue - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):697-709.
  • Research on self-control: An integrating framework.A. W. Logue - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):665-679.