Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Working memory and its extensions.K. J. Gilhooly - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):761-762.
  • Creativity theory: Detail and testability.K. J. Gilhooly - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):544-545.
  • Strong AI and the problem of “second-order” algorithms.Gerd Gigerenzer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):663-664.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy as a Private Language.Ben Gibran - 2012 - Essays in Philosophy 13 (1):54-73.
    Philosophy (and its corollaries in the human sciences such as literary, social and political theory) is distinguished from other disciplines by a more thoroughgoing emphasis on the a priori. Philosophy makes no claims to predictive power; nor does it aim to conform to popular opinion (beyond ordinary intuitions as recorded by ‘thought experiments’). Many philosophers view the discipline’s self-exemption from ‘real world’ empirical testing as a non-issue or even an advantage, in allowing philosophy to focus on universal and necessary truths. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are libraries intelligent?Michael T. Ghiselin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):78-78.
  • Minds vs Machines.Karim Gherab - 2022 - Human Review. International Humanities Review / Revista Internacional de Humanidades 11 (2):185-195.
    This paper presents, from a historical and logical-philosophical perspective, the Gödelian arguments of two Oxford scholars, John Lucas and Roger Penrose. Both have been based on Gödel's Theorem to refute mechanism, computationalism and the possibility of creating an AI capable of simulating or duplicating the human mind. In the conclusions, the growing application of empirical methods in mathematics is mentioned and a possible path that would support Lucas and Penrose's arguments is speculated.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Issues in robot ethics seen through the lens of a moral Turing test.Anne Gerdes & Peter Øhrstrøm - 2015 - Journal of Information, Communication and Ethics in Society 13 (2):98-109.
    Purpose – The purpose of this paper is to explore artificial moral agency by reflecting upon the possibility of a Moral Turing Test and whether its lack of focus on interiority, i.e. its behaviouristic foundation, counts as an obstacle to establishing such a test to judge the performance of an Artificial Moral Agent. Subsequently, to investigate whether an MTT could serve as a useful framework for the understanding, designing and engineering of AMAs, we set out to address fundamental challenges within (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • How to be a conformist, part II. simulation and rule following.Philip Gerrans - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (4):566 – 586.
  • Awareness, understanding, and functionalism.N. Georgalis - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (2):225-56.
  • Asymmetry of access to intentional states.Nicholas Georgalis - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (2):185-211.
  • On kicking the behaviorist; or, Pain is distressing.Myles Genest - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):59-60.
  • Does mentality entail consciousness?Rocco J. Gennaro - 1995 - Philosophia 24 (3-4):331-58.
  • From Searle’s Chinese room to the mathematics classroom: technical and cognitive mathematics.Dimitris Gavalas - 2006 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 26 (2):127-146.
    Employing Searle’s views, I begin by arguing that students of Mathematics behave similarly to machines that manage symbols using a set of rules. I then consider two types of Mathematics, which I call Cognitive Mathematics and Technical Mathematics respectively. The former type relates to concepts and meanings, logic and sense, whilst the latter relates to algorithms, heuristics, rules and application of various techniques. I claim that an upgrade in the school teaching of Cognitive Mathematics is necessary. The aim is to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Philosophy of Creativity.Berys Gaut - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (12):1034-1046.
    This paper surveys some of the central issues in the philosophy of creativity and argues that an adequate treatment of them requires attention to the rich psychological literature on creativity. It also shows that the range of interesting philosophical questions to be raised about creativity is much wider than concerns its role in art. Issues covered include the definition of ‘creativity’; the relation of creativity to imagination; whether the creative process is rational; whether it is teleological; the relation of creativity (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • The virtues of chaos.Alan Garfinkel - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):178-179.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Semantic Grounding of Novel Spoken Words in the Primary Visual Cortex.Max Garagnani, Evgeniya Kirilina & Friedemann Pulvermüller - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 15.
    Embodied theories of grounded semantics postulate that, when word meaning is first acquired, a link is established between symbol and corresponding semantic information present in modality-specific—including primary—sensorimotor cortices of the brain. Direct experimental evidence documenting the emergence of such a link, however, is still missing. Here, we present new neuroimaging results that provide such evidence. We taught participants aspects of the referential meaning of previously unknown, senseless novel spoken words by associating them with either a familiar action or a familiar (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mice in mirrored mazes and the mind.James W. Garson - 1993 - Philosophical Psychology 6 (2):123-34.
    The computational theory of cognition (CTC) holds that the mind is akin to computer software. This article aims to show that CTC is incorrect because it is not able to distinguish the ability to solve a maze from the ability to solve its mirror image. CTC cannot do so because it only individuates brain states up to isomorphism. It is shown that a finer individuation that would distinguish left-handed from right-handed abilities is not compatible with CTC. The view is explored (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is logicist cognitive science possible?Alan Garnham - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (1):49-71.
    This paper argues against Oaksford and Chater's claim that logicist cognitive science is not possible. It suggests that there arguments against logicist cognitive science are too closely tied to the account of Pylyshyn and of Fodor, and that the correct way of thinking about logicist cognitive science is in a mental models framework.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Art for art's sake.Alan Garnham - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):543-544.
    This piece is a commentary on a precis of Maggie Boden's book "The creative mind" published in Behavioral and Brain Sciences.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does the nervous system depend on kinesthetic information to control natural limb movements?S. C. Gandevia & David Burke - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):614-632.
    This target article draws together two groups of experimental studies on the control of human movement through peripheral feedback and centrally generated signals of motor commands. First, during natural movement, feedback from muscle, joint, and cutaneous afferents changes; in human subjects these changes have reflex and kinesthetic consequences. Recent psychophysical and microneurographic evidence suggests that joint and even cutaneous afferents may have a proprioceptive role. Second, the role of centrally generated motor commands in the control of normal movements and movements (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Progress in machine consciousness.David Gamirez - 2008 - Consciousness and Cognition 17 (3):887-910.
    This paper is a review of the work that has been carried out on machine consciousness. A clear overview of this diverse field is achieved by breaking machine consciousness down into four different areas, which are used to understand its aims, discuss its relationship with other subjects and outline the work that has been carried out so far. The criticisms that have been made against machine consciousness are also covered, along with its potential benefits, and the work that has been (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Empirically grounded claims about consciousness in computers.David Gamez - 2012 - International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4 (2):421-438.
    Research is starting to identify correlations between consciousness and some of the spatiotemporal patterns in the physical brain. For theoretical and practical reasons, the results of experiments on the correlates of consciousness have ambiguous interpretations. At any point in time a number of hypotheses co-exist about and the correlates of consciousness in the brain, which are all compatible with the current experimental results. This paper argues that consciousness should be attributed to any system that exhibits spatiotemporal physical patterns that match (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Don't ask Plato about the emperor's mind.Alan Gamham - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):664-665.
  • Where meanings arise and how: Building on Shannon's foundations.Charles R. Gallistel - 2020 - Mind and Language 35 (3):390-401.
    Information theory provides a quantitative conceptual framework for understanding the flow of information from the world into and through brains. It focuses our attention on the sets of possible messages a brain's anatomy and physiology enable it to receive. The meanings of the messages arise from the inferences licensed by the brain's processing of them. Different meanings arise at different levels because different representations of the input license different inferences.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Where do philosophers appeal to intuitions (if they do)?Richard Galvin & William Roche - 2024 - Metaphilosophy 55 (1):44-58.
    It might be that intuitions are central to philosophy, and it might be that this is true because when philosophers give case‐based arguments for philosophical claims (in published philosophy), the case verdict is typically (a) an intuited proposition and (b) either left undefended or defended on the grounds that it is an intuited proposition. This paper remains neutral on these global issues, however, and instead focuses on whether there is a nontrivial (or many‐membered) class of case‐based arguments in philosophy in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John D. Greenwood, ed., the future of folk psychology: Intentionality and cognitive science; Scott M. Christensen and Dale R. Turner, eds., Folk psychology and the philosophy of mind. [REVIEW]Norman R. Gall - 2000 - Minds and Machines 10 (3):416-423.
  • The birth of an idea.Liane M. Gabora - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):543-543.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural transitions occur when mind parasites learn new tricks.Liane M. Gabora - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):760-761.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity, madness, and extra strong Al.K. W. M. Fulford - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):542-543.
  • On the Conceivability of a Cognitive Phenomenology Zombie.Martina Fürst - 2019 - Dialectica 73 (1-2):105-127.
    The cognitive phenomenology thesis has it that conscious cognitive states essentially exhibit a phenomenal character. Defenders of ‘conservatism’ about cognitive phenomenology think that the phenomenology of thought is reducible to sensory phenomenology. In contrast, proponents of ‘liberalism’ hold that there is a proprietary, sui generis cognitive phenomenology. Horgan develops a morph-sequence argument to argue for liberalism. The argument is based on the conceivability of a cognitive phenomenology zombie, i.e. a man who does not understand Chinese but shares the behavior and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Enactive artificial intelligence: Investigating the systemic organization of life and mind.Tom Froese & Tom Ziemke - 2009 - Artificial Intelligence 173 (3-4):466-500.
  • Is Unified theories of cognition good strategy?Nico H. Frijda & Jan Elshout - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):445-446.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Ed Tech in Reverse’: Information technologies and the cognitive revolution.Norm Friesen & Andrew Feenberg - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (7):720–736.
    As we rapidly approach the 50th year of the much‐celebrated ‘cognitive revolution’, it is worth reflecting on its widespread impact on individual disciplines and areas of multidisciplinary endeavour. Of specific concern in this paper is the example of the influence of cognitivism's equation of mind and computer in education. Within education, this paper focuses on a particular area of concern to which both mind and computer are simultaneously central: educational technology. It examines the profound and lasting effect of cognitive science (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consciousness is for other people.Chris Frith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-683.
    Gray has expanded his account of schizophrenia to explain consciousness as well. His theory explains neither phenomenon adequately because he treats individual minds in isolation. The primary function of consciousness is to permit high level interactions with other conscious beings. The key symptoms of schizophrenia reflect a failure of this mechanism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Turing test: The first fifty years.Robert M. French - 2000 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (3):115-121.
    The Turing Test, originally proposed as a simple operational definition of intelligence, has now been with us for exactly half a century. It is safe to say that no other single article in computer science, and few other articles in science in general, have generated so much discussion. The present article chronicles the comments and controversy surrounding Turing's classic article from its publication to the present. The changing perception of the Turing Test over the last fifty years has paralleled the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The indeterminacy of computation.Nir Fresco, B. Jack Copeland & Marty J. Wolf - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):12753-12775.
    Do the dynamics of a physical system determine what function the system computes? Except in special cases, the answer is no: it is often indeterminate what function a given physical system computes. Accordingly, care should be taken when the question ‘What does a particular neuronal system do?’ is answered by hypothesising that the system computes a particular function. The phenomenon of the indeterminacy of computation has important implications for the development of computational explanations of biological systems. Additionally, the phenomenon lends (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Explanatory Role of Computation in Cognitive Science.Nir Fresco - 2012 - Minds and Machines 22 (4):353-380.
    Which notion of computation (if any) is essential for explaining cognition? Five answers to this question are discussed in the paper. (1) The classicist answer: symbolic (digital) computation is required for explaining cognition; (2) The broad digital computationalist answer: digital computation broadly construed is required for explaining cognition; (3) The connectionist answer: sub-symbolic computation is required for explaining cognition; (4) The computational neuroscientist answer: neural computation (that, strictly, is neither digital nor analogue) is required for explaining cognition; (5) The extreme (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Plasticity of the neural coding metaphor: An unnoticed rhetoric in scientific discourse.Giulia Frezza & Pierluigi Zoccolotti - 2019 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42.
    The convincing argument that Brette makes for the neural coding metaphor as imposing one view of brain behavior can be further explained through discourse analysis. Instead of a unified view, we argue, the coding metaphor's plasticity, versatility, and robustness throughout time explain its success and conventionalization to the point that its rhetoric became overlooked.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grammar and consciousness.Robert Freidin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):605-606.
  • Dynamic systems and the “subsymbolic level”.Walter J. Freeman - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):33-34.
  • Consciousness as physiological self-organizing process.Walter J. Freeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):604-605.
  • Connectionism and the study of language.R. Freidin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):34-35.
  • Robert G. Burton, ed., natural and artificial minds, SUNY series, scientific studies in natural and artificial intelligence, albany: State university of new York press, 1993, VII + 245 pp., $21.95 (paper), ISBN 0-7914-1508-. [REVIEW]Stan Franklin - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (1):143-156.
  • The Hybridization of the Human with Brain Implants: The Neuralink Project.Éric Fourneret - 2020 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 29 (4):668-672.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The problem of survival from an algorithmic point of view.J. -D. Fouks & L. Signac - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 133 (1-2):87-116.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of Searle (2008): Philosophy in a New Century: Selected Essays. [REVIEW]Nicholas Fotion - 2011 - Pragmatics and Cognition 19 (1):117-124.
  • Radical behaviorism is a dead end.Jeff Foss - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):59-59.
  • On seeking the mythical fountain of consciousness.Jeffrey Foss - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-682.
    Because consciousness has an organizational, or functional, center, Gray supposes that there must be a corresponding physical center in the brain. He proposes further that since this center generates consciousness, ablating it would eliminate consciousness, while leaving behavior intact. But the center of consciousness is simply the product of the functional linkages among sensory input, memory, inner speech, and so on, and behavior.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the evolution of intentionality as seen from the intentional stance.Jeffrey E. Foss - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):287-310.
    Like everyone with a scientific bent of mind, Dennett thinks our capacity for meaningful language and states of mind is the product of evolution (Dennett [1987, ch. VIII]). But unlike many of this bent, he sees virtue in viewing evolution itself from the intentional stance. From this stance, ?Mother Nature?, or the process of evolution by natural selection, bestows intentionality upon us, hence we are not Unmeant Meaners. Thus, our intentionality is extrinsic, and Dennett dismisses the theories of meaning of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Artificial Moral Agents: Moral Mentors or Sensible Tools?Fabio Fossa - 2018 - Ethics and Information Technology (2):1-12.
    The aim of this paper is to offer an analysis of the notion of artificial moral agent (AMA) and of its impact on human beings’ self-understanding as moral agents. Firstly, I introduce the topic by presenting what I call the Continuity Approach. Its main claim holds that AMAs and human moral agents exhibit no significant qualitative difference and, therefore, should be considered homogeneous entities. Secondly, I focus on the consequences this approach leads to. In order to do this I take (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations