Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Modeling generalized implicatures using non-monotonic logics.Jacques Wainer - 2007 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16 (2):195-216.
    This paper reports on an approach to model generalized implicatures using nonmonotonic logics. The approach, called compositional, is based on the idea of compositional semantics, where the implicatures carried by a sentence are constructed from the implicatures carried by its constituents, but it also includes some aspects nonmonotonic logics in order to model the defeasibility of generalized implicatures.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bounded rationality: from fast and frugal heuristics to logic programming and back.Francisco Vargas, Laura Martignon & Keith Stenning - 2023 - Mind and Society 22 (1):33-51.
    The notion of “bounded rationality” was introduced by Simon as an appropriate framework for explaining how agents reason and make decisions in accordance with their computational limitations and the characteristics of the environments in which they exist (seen metaphorically as two complementary scissor blades).We elaborate on how bounded rationality is usually conceived in psychology and on its relationship with logic. We focus on the relationship between heuristics and some non-monotonic logical systems. These two categories of cognitive tools share fundamental features. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Note on a Description Logic of Concept and Role Typicality for Defeasible Reasoning Over Ontologies.Ivan Varzinczak - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (3-4):297-325.
    In this work, we propose a meaningful extension of description logics for non-monotonic reasoning. We introduce \, a logic allowing for the representation of and reasoning about both typical class-membership and typical instances of a relation. We propose a preferential semantics for \ in terms of partially-ordered DL interpretations which intuitively captures the notions of typicality we are interested in. We define a tableau-based algorithm for checking \ knowledge-base consistency that always terminates and we show that it is sound and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generics and typicality: a bounded rationality approach.Robert van Rooij & Katrin Schulz - 2020 - Linguistics and Philosophy 43 (1):83-117.
    Cimpian et al. observed that we accept generic statements of the form ‘Gs are f’ on relatively weak evidence, but that if we are unfamiliar with group G and we learn a generic statement about it, we still treat it inferentially in a much stronger way: all Gs are f. This paper makes use of notions like ‘representativeness’, ‘contingency’ and ‘relative difference’ from psychology to provide a uniform semantics of generics that explains why people accept generics based on weak evidence. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Reasoning agents in a dynamic world: The frame problem.Jozsef A. Toth - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 73 (1-2):323-369.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Qualification Problem: A solution to the problem of anomalous models.Michael Thielscher - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 131 (1-2):1-37.
  • When adjunction fails.Choh Man Teng - 2012 - Synthese 186 (2):501-510.
    The rule of adjunction is intuitively appealing and uncontroversial for deductive inference, but in situations where information can be uncertain, the rule is neither needed nor wanted for rational acceptance, as illustrated by the lottery paradox. Practical certainty is the acceptance of statements whose chances of error are smaller than a prescribed threshold parameter, when evaluated against an evidential corpus. We examine the failure of adjunction in relation to the threshold parameter for practical certainty, with an eye towards reinstating the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Normality and Majority: Towards a Statistical Understanding of Normality Statements.Corina Strößner - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (4):793-809.
    Normality judgements are frequently used in everyday communication as well as in biological and social science. Moreover they became increasingly relevant to formal logic as part of defeasible reasoning. This paper distinguishes different kinds of normality statements. It is argued that normality laws like “Birds can normally fly” should be understood essentially in a statistical way. The argument has basically two parts: firstly, a statistical semantic core is mandatory for a descriptive reading of normality in order to explain the logical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Characterizing generics are material inference tickets: a proof-theoretic analysis.Preston Stovall - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy (5):668-704.
    An adequate semantics for generic sentences must stake out positions across a range of contested territory in philosophy and linguistics. For this reason the study of generic sentences is a venue for investigating different frameworks for understanding human rationality as manifested in linguistic phenomena such as quantification, classification of individuals under kinds, defeasible reasoning, and intensionality. Despite the wide variety of semantic theories developed for generic sentences, to date these theories have been almost universally model-theoretic and representational. This essay outlines (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Resolving ambiguity in nonmonotonic inheritance hierarchies.Lynn Andrea Stein - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 55 (2-3):259-310.
  • Motivated action theory: a formal theory of causal reasoning.Lynn Andrea Stein & Leora Morgenstern - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 71 (1):1-42.
  • Formalizing sensing actions— A transition function based approach.Tran Cao Son & Chitta Baral - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 125 (1-2):19-91.
  • Ceteris Paribus Conditionals and Comparative Normalcy.Martin Smith - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (1):97-121.
    Our understanding of subjunctive conditionals has been greatly enhanced through the use of possible world semantics and, more precisely, by the idea that they involve variably strict quantification over possible worlds. I propose to extend this treatment to ceteris paribus conditionals – that is, conditionals that incorporate a ceteris paribus or ‘other things being equal’ clause. Although such conditionals are commonly invoked in scientific theorising, they traditionally arouse suspicion and apprehensiveness amongst philosophers. By treating ceteris paribus conditionals as a species (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Extending and implementing the stable model semantics.Patrik Simons, Ilkka Niemelä & Timo Soininen - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence 138 (1-2):181-234.
  • Perception as Abduction: Turning Sensor Data Into Meaningful Representation.Murray Shanahan - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (1):103-134.
    This article presents a formal theory of robot perception as a form of abduction. The theory pins down the process whereby low‐level sensor data is transformed into a symbolic representation of the external world, drawing together aspects such as incompleteness, top‐down information flow, active perception, attention, and sensor fusion in a unifying framework. In addition, a number of themes are identified that are common to both the engineer concerned with developing a rigorous theory of perception, such as the one on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A framework for knowledge-based temporal abstraction.Yuval Shahar - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 90 (1-2):79-133.
  • A circumscriptive calculus of events.Murray Shanahan - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 77 (2):249-284.
  • Nonmonotonic consequence based on intuitionistic logic.Gisèle Fischer Servi - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (4):1176-1197.
  • What is 'normal'? An evolution-theoretic foundation for normic laws and their relation to statistical normality.Gerhard Schurz - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (4):476-497.
    Normic laws have the form "if A, then normally B." They are omnipresent in everyday life and non-physical 'life' sciences such as biology, psychology, social sciences, and humanities. They differ significantly from ceteris-paribus laws in physics. While several authors have doubted that normic laws are genuine laws at all, others have argued that normic laws express a certain kind of prototypical normality which is independent of statistical majority. This paper presents a foundation for normic laws which is based on generalized (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Pragmatic Meaning and Non-Monotonic Reasoning: The Case of Exhaustive Interpretation.Katrin Schulz & Robert van Rooij - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (2):205 - 250.
    In this paper an approach to the exhaustive interpretation of answers is developed. It builds on a proposal brought forward by Groenendijk and Stokhof (1984). We will use the close connection between their approach and McCarthy's (1980, 1986) predicate circumscription and describe exhaustive interpretation as an instance of interpretation in minimal models, well-known from work on counterfactuals (see for instance Lewis (1973)). It is shown that by combining this approach with independent developments in semantics/pragmatics one can overcome certain limitations of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Non-Monotonic Reasoning from an Evolution-Theoretic Perspective: Ontic, Logical and Cognitive Foundations.Gerhard Schurz - 2005 - Synthese 146 (1-2):37-51.
    In the first part I argue that normic laws are the phenomenological laws of evolutionary systems. If this is true, then intuitive human reasoning should be fit in reasoning from normic laws. In the second part I show that system P is a tool for reasoning with normic laws which satisfies two important evolutionary standards: it is probabilistically reliable, and it has rules of low complexity. In the third part I finally report results of an experimental study which demonstrate that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Normische gesetzeshypothesen und die wissenschaftsphilosophische bedeutung Des nichtmonotonen schliessens.Gerhard Schurz - 2001 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 32 (1):65-107.
    Normic Laws and the Significance of Nonmonotonic Reasoning for Philosophy of Science. Normic laws have the form ‘if A then normally B’. They have been discovered in the explanation debate, but were considered as empirically vacuous (§1). I argue that the prototypical (or ideal) normality of normic laws implies statistical normality (§2), whence normic laws have empirical content. In §3–4 I explain why reasoning from normic laws is nonmonotonic, and why the understanding of the individual case is so important here. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dynamic reasoning with qualified syllogisms.Daniel G. Schwartz - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 93 (1-2):103-167.
  • Decidability and definability with circumscription.John S. Schlipf - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 35 (C):173-191.
    We consider McCarthy's notions of predicate circumscription and formula circumscription. We show that the decision problems “does θ have a countably infinite minimal model” and “does φ hold in every countably infinite minimal model of θ” are complete Σ 1 2 and complete π 1 2 over the integers, for both forms of circumscription. The set of structures definable as first order definable subsets of countably infinite minimal models is the set of structures which are Δ 1 2 over the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ceteris paribus laws: Classification and deconstruction. [REVIEW]Gerhard Schurz - 2002 - Erkenntnis 57 (3):351Ð372.
    It has not been sufficiently considered in philosophical discussions of ceteris paribus (CP) laws that distinct kinds of CP-laws exist in science with rather different meanings. I distinguish between (1.) comparative CP-laws and (2.) exclusive CP-laws. There exist also mixed CP-laws, which contain a comparative and an exclusive CP-clause. Exclusive CP-laws may be either (2.1) definite, (2.2) indefinite or (2.3) normic. While CP-laws of kind (2.1) and (2.2) exhibit deductivistic behaviour, CP-laws of kind (2.3) require a probabilistic or non-monotonic reconstruction. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • From systems to logic in the early development of nonmonotonic reasoning.Erik Sandewall - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence 175 (1):416-427.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reduction revisited.Emma Ruttkamp - 2006 - South African Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):102-112.
    This is a first tentative examination of the possibility of reinstating reduction as a valid candidate for presenting relations between mental and physical properties. Classical Nagelian reduction is undoubtedly contaminated in many ways, but here I investigate the possibility of adapting to problems concerning mental properties an alternative definition for theory reduction in philosophy of science. The definition I offer is formulated with the aid of non-monotonic logic, which I suspect might be a very interesting realm for testing notions concerning (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reviewing Reduction in a Preferential Model‐Theoretic Context.Emma Ruttkamp & Johannes Heidema - 2005 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (2):123 – 146.
    In this article, we redefine classical notions of theory reduction in such a way that model-theoretic preferential semantics becomes part of a realist depiction of this aspect of science. We offer a model-theoretic reconstruction of science in which theory succession or reduction is often better - or at a finer level of analysis - interpreted as the result of model succession or reduction. This analysis leads to 'defeasible reduction', defined as follows: The conjunction of the assumptions of a reducing theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A theory of diagnosis from first principles.Raymond Reiter - 1987 - Artificial Intelligence 32 (1):57-95.
  • Three-valued nonmonotonic formalisms and semantics of logic programs.Teodor Przymusinski - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 49 (1-3):309-343.
  • An algorithm to compute circumscription.Teodor C. Przymusinski - 1989 - Artificial Intelligence 38 (1):49-73.
  • The independent choice logic for modelling multiple agents under uncertainty.David Poole - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 94 (1-2):7-56.
  • The effect of knowledge on belief.David Poole - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 49 (1-3):281-307.
  • A logical framework for default reasoning.David Poole - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 36 (1):27-47.
  • Vision, Knowledge, and the Mystery Link.John L. Pollock & Iris Oved - 2005 - Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1):309-351.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Vision, knowledge, and the mystery link.John L. Pollock & Iris Oved - 2005 - Noûs 39 (1):309-351.
    Imagine yourself sitting on your front porch, sipping your morning coffee and admiring the scene before you. You see trees, houses, people, automobiles; you see a cat running across the road, and a bee buzzing among the flowers. You see that the flowers are yellow, and blowing in the wind. You see that the people are moving about, many of them on bicycles. You see that the houses are painted different colors, mostly earth tones, and most are one-story but a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The theory of nomic probability.John L. Pollock - 1992 - Synthese 90 (2):263 - 299.
    This article sketches a theory of objective probability focusing on nomic probability, which is supposed to be the kind of probability figuring in statistical laws of nature. The theory is based upon a strengthened probability calculus and some epistemological principles that formulate a precise version of the statistical syllogism. It is shown that from this rather minimal basis it is possible to derive theorems comprising (1) a theory of direct inference, and (2) a theory of induction. The theory of induction (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Justification and defeat.John L. Pollock - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 67 (2):377-407.
  • ``Defeasible Reasoning with Variable Degrees of Justification".John L. Pollock - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 133 (1-2):233-282.
    The question addressed in this paper is how the degree of justification of a belief is determined. A conclusion may be supported by several different arguments, the arguments typically being defeasible, and there may also be arguments of varying strengths for defeaters for some of the supporting arguments. What is sought is a way of computing the “on sum” degree of justification of a conclusion in terms of the degrees of justification of all relevant premises and the strengths of all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Circumscribing with sets.Donald Perlis - 1987 - Artificial Intelligence 31 (2):201-211.
  • Completeness results for circumscription.Donald Perlis & Jack Minker - 1986 - Artificial Intelligence 28 (1):29-42.
  • Autocircumscription.Donald Perlis - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 36 (2):223-236.
  • Prolegomena to concise theories of action.Pavlos Peppas, Costas D. Koutras & Mary-Anne Williams - 2001 - Studia Logica 67 (3):403-418.
    A new methodology for developing theories of action has recently emerged which provides means for formally evaluating the correctness of such theories. Yet, for a theory of action to qualify as a solution to the frame problem, not only does it need to produce correct inferences, but moreover, it needs to derive these inferences from a concise representation of the domain at hand. The new methodology however offers no means for assessing conciseness. Such a formal account of conciseness is developed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Case for Psychologism in Default and Inheritance Reasoning.Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Renée Elio - 2005 - Synthese 146 (1-2):7-35.
    Default reasoning occurs whenever the truth of the evidence available to the reasoner does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion being drawn. Despite this, one is entitled to draw the conclusion “by default” on the grounds that we have no information which would make us doubt that the inference should be drawn. It is the type of conclusion we draw in the ordinary world and ordinary situations in which we find ourselves. Formally speaking, ‘nonmonotonic reasoning’ refers to argumentation in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Probabilistic single function dual process theory and logic programming as approaches to non-monotonicity in human vs. artificial reasoning.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 2014 - Thinking and Reasoning 20 (2):269-295.
  • Logic and artificial intelligence.Nils J. Nilsson - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 47 (1-3):31-56.
  • Generically free choice.Bernhard Nickel - 2010 - Linguistics and Philosophy 33 (6):479-512.
    This paper discusses free-choice like effects in generics. Just as Jane may drink coffee or tea can be used to convey Jane may drink coffee and Jane may drink tea (she is free to choose ), some generics with disjunctive predicates can be used to convey conjunctions of simpler generics: elephants live in Africa or Asia can be used to convey elephants live in Africa and elephants live in Asia. Investigating these logically slightly more complex generics and especially the free-choice (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Imitation Game: Threshold or Watershed?Eric Neufeld & Sonje Finnestad - 2020 - Minds and Machines 30 (4):637-657.
    Showing remarkable insight into the relationship between language and thought, Alan Turing in 1950 proposed the Imitation Game as a proxy for the question “Can machines think?” and its meaning and practicality have been debated hotly ever since. The Imitation Game has come under criticism within the Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence communities with leading scientists proposing alternatives, revisions, or even that the Game be abandoned entirely. Yet Turing’s imagined conversational fragments between human and machine are rich with complex instances (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A theorem on the consistency of circumscription.Peter L. Mott - 1987 - Artificial Intelligence 31 (1):87-98.
  • The anomalous extension problem in default reasoning.Paul H. Morris - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 35 (3):383-399.