Results for ' Pettigrew'

(not author) ( search as author name )
53 found
Order:
  1. Bible Characters in Cross Word Puzzles.Lucile Pettigrew Johnson - unknown
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  62
    Epistemology, Pettigrew Style: A Critical Notice of Accuracy and the Laws of Credence, by Richard Pettigrew1.Scott Sturgeon - 2019 - Mind 128 (512):1319-1336.
    The sharpest corner of the cutting edge of recent epistemology is to be found in Richard Pettigrew’s Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. In this fine book Pettigrew argues that a certain kind of accuracy-based value monism entails that rational credence manifests a host of features emphasized by anti-externalists in epistemology. Specifically, he demonstrates how a particular version of accuracy-based value monism—to be discussed at length below—when placed with some not implausible views about how epistemic value and rationality (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Transformative Experience: Replies to Pettigrew, Barnes and Campbell.L. A. Paul - 2015 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91 (3):794-813.
    Summary of Transformative Experience by L.A. Paul and replies to symposiasts. Discussion of undefined values, preference change, authenticity, experiential value, collective minds, mind control.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  4. Leitgeb and Pettigrew on Accuracy and Updating.Benjamin Anders Levinstein - 2012 - Philosophy of Science 79 (3):413-424.
    Leitgeb and Pettigrew argue that (1) agents should minimize the expected inaccuracy of their beliefs and (2) inaccuracy should be measured via the Brier score. They show that in certain diachronic cases, these claims require an alternative to Jeffrey Conditionalization. I claim that this alternative is an irrational updating procedure and that the Brier score, and quadratic scoring rules generally, should be rejected as legitimate measures of inaccuracy.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  5.  46
    Richard Pettigrew. Accuracy and the Laws of Credence.Chad Marxen & Gerard Rothfus - 2018 - Philosophy of Science 85 (2):316-320.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  46
    Richard Pettigrew: Accuracy and the Laws of Credence.R. A. Briggs - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy 114 (9):503-508.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Pettigrew & Raffoul (ed.) , French Interpretations of Heidegger: An Exceptional Reception (State University of New York Press, 2008) & Garo , Foucault, Deleuze, Althusser et Marx–La politique dans la philosophie (Demopolis, 2011). [REVIEW]Andrew Ryder - 2013 - Foucault Studies 16:212-215.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  12
    D. Pettigrew and F. Raffoul (eds.), French Interpretations of Heidegger: An Exceptional Reception, SUNY Press, Albany, 2008. [REVIEW]Guillaume Fagniez - 2010 - Revue Philosophique De Louvain 108 (4):749-751.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  18
    Comments on Richard Pettigrew's Accuracy and the Laws of Credence.Matthew Kotzen - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (3):776-783.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  61
    David Pettigrew and François Raffoul (eds.), French Interpretations of Heidegger: An Exceptional Reception. [REVIEW]David Tkach - 2011 - Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 15 (1):208-211.
  11.  49
    Remarks on Richard Pettigrew's Accuracy and the Laws of Credence.James M. Joyce - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 96 (3):755-762.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Revisiting Risk and Rationality: a reply to Pettigrew and Briggs.Lara Buchak - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5):841-862.
    I have claimed that risk-weighted expected utility maximizers are rational, and that their preferences cannot be captured by expected utility theory. Richard Pettigrew and Rachael Briggs have recently challenged these claims. Both authors argue that only EU-maximizers are rational. In addition, Pettigrew argues that the preferences of REU-maximizers can indeed be captured by EU theory, and Briggs argues that REU-maximizers lose a valuable tool for simplifying their decision problems. I hold that their arguments do not succeed and that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13.  28
    Epistemic Risk and the Demands of Rationality, by Richard Pettigrew.Lara Buchak - forthcoming - Mind.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  17
    Review of Richard Pettigrew's Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. [REVIEW]Chad Marxen & Gerard Rothfus - forthcoming - Philosophy of Science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  15
    Review of Richard Pettigrew’s Choosing for Changing Selves - Richard Pettigrew, Choosing for Changing Selves. Oxford: Oxford University Press (2020), 272 pp., $72.00 (hardcover; also available as an e-book). [REVIEW]Susanne Burri - 2022 - Philosophy of Science 89 (2):398-401.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  49
    In Defense of IP: A Response to Pettigrew.J. T. Ismael - 2013 - Noûs 49 (1):197-200.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  3
    Review of Richard Pettigrew’s Dutch Book Arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020, 96 pp. [REVIEW]Luc Lichtsteiner - 2022 - Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 15 (2):aa–aa.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  34
    Assessing the credence of Bayesian epistemology: Richard Pettigrew’s: Accuracy and the laws of credence. Oxford University Press, 2016, 256 pp, $74.00 HB.Erik J. Olsson - 2017 - Metascience 26 (2):245-247.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  53
    Choosing for Changing Selves, by Richard Pettigrew.Krister Bykvist - forthcoming - Mind.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  63
    Choosing for Changing Selves, Richard Pettigrew. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019, xiv + 253 pages. [REVIEW]Arif Ahmed - 2021 - Economics and Philosophy 37 (3):484-489.
  21.  13
    Heidegger in France. By Dominique Janicaud. Translated by François Raffoul and David Pettigrew. Pp. xv, 540, Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2015, $68.31. [REVIEW]Brian Harding - 2017 - Heythrop Journal 58 (4):725-726.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Accuracy Uncomposed: Against Calibrationism.Ben Levinstein - 2017 - Episteme 14 (1):59-69.
    Pettigrew offers new axiomatic constraints on legitimate measures of inaccuracy. His axiom called ‘Decomposition’ stipulates that legitimate measures of inaccuracy evaluate a credence function in part based on its level of calibration at a world. I argue that if calibration is valuable, as Pettigrew claims, then this fact is an explanandum for accuracy-rst epistemologists, not an explanans, for three reasons. First, the intuitive case for the importance of calibration isn’t as strong as Pettigrew believes. Second, calibration is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  33
    Learning is a Risky Business.Wayne C. Myrvold - 2017 - Erkenntnis:1-8.
    Richard Pettigrew has recently advanced a justification of the Principle of Indifference on the basis of a principle that he calls “cognitive conservatism,” or “extreme epistemic conservatism.” However, the credences based on the Principle of Indifference, as Pettigrew formulates it, violate another desideratum, namely, that learning from experience be possible. If it is accepted that learning from experience should be possible, this provides grounds for rejecting cognitive conservatism. Another set of criteria considered by Pettigrew, which involves a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  25
    Learning is a Risky Business.Wayne C. Myrvold - 2019 - Erkenntnis 84 (3):577-584.
    Richard Pettigrew has recently advanced a justification of the Principle of Indifference on the basis of a principle that he calls “cognitive conservatism,” or “extreme epistemic conservatism.” However, the credences based on the Principle of Indifference, as Pettigrew formulates it, violate another desideratum, namely, that learning from experience be possible. If it is accepted that learning from experience should be possible, this provides grounds for rejecting cognitive conservatism. Another set of criteria considered by Pettigrew, which involves a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  60
    The Structuralist Thesis Reconsidered.Georg Schiemer & John Wigglesworth - 2019 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (4):1201-1226.
    Øystein Linnebo and Richard Pettigrew have recently developed a version of non-eliminative mathematical structuralism based on Fregean abstraction principles. They argue that their theory of abstract structures proves a consistent version of the structuralist thesis that positions in abstract structures only have structural properties. They do this by defining a subset of the properties of positions in structures, so-called fundamental properties, and argue that all fundamental properties of positions are structural. In this article, we argue that the structuralist thesis, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. On the Best Accuracy Arguments for Probabilism.Michael Nielsen - 2022 - Philosophy of Science 89 (3):621-630.
    In a recent paper, Pettigrew reports a generalization of the celebrated accuracy-dominance theorem due to Predd et al., but Pettigrew’s proof is incorrect. I will explain the mistakes and provide a correct proof.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  43
    The Structuralist Thesis Reconsidered.Georg Schiemer & John Wigglesworth - 2017 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science:axy004.
    Øystein Linnebo and Richard Pettigrew have recently developed a version of non-eliminative mathematical structuralism based on Fregean abstraction principles. They argue that their theory of abstract structures proves a consistent version of the structuralist thesis that positions in abstract structures only have structural properties. They do this by defining a subset of the properties of positions in structures, so-called fundamental properties, and argue that all fundamental properties of positions are structural. In this paper, we argue that the structuralist thesis, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  51
    Non-eliminative Structuralism, Fregean Abstraction, and Non-rigid Structures.John Wigglesworth - 2018 - Erkenntnis 86 (1):113-127.
    Linnebo and Pettigrew have recently developed a version of non-eliminative mathematical structuralism based on Fregean abstraction principles. They recognize that this version of structuralism is vulnerable to the well-known problem of non-rigid structures. This paper offers a solution to the problem for this version of structuralism. The solution involves expanding the languages used to describe mathematical structures. We then argue that this solution is philosophically acceptable to those who endorse mathematical structuralism based on Fregean abstraction principles.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29. Category Theory is a Contentful Theory.Shay Logan - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1):110-115.
    Linnebo and Pettigrew present some objections to category theory as an autonomous foundation. They do a commendable job making clear several distinct senses of ‘autonomous’ as it occurs in the phrase ‘autonomous foundation’. Unfortunately, their paper seems to treat the ‘categorist’ perspective rather unfairly. Several infelicities of this sort were addressed by McLarty. In this note I address yet another apparent infelicity.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30. Expected Accuracy Supports Conditionalization—and Conglomerability and Reflection.Kenny Easwaran - 2013 - Philosophy of Science 80 (1):119-142.
    Expected accuracy arguments have been used by several authors (Leitgeb and Pettigrew, and Greaves and Wallace) to support the diachronic principle of conditionalization, in updates where there are only finitely many possible propositions to learn. I show that these arguments can be extended to infinite cases, giving an argument not just for conditionalization but also for principles known as ‘conglomerability’ and ‘reflection’. This shows that the expected accuracy approach is stronger than has been realized. I also argue that we (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  31. Identity, indiscernibility, and Ante Rem structuralism: The tale of I and –I.Stewart Shapiro - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):285-309.
    Some authors have claimed that ante rem structuralism has problems with structures that have indiscernible places. In response, I argue that there is no requirement that mathematical objects be individuated in a non-trivial way. Metaphysical principles and intuitions to the contrary do not stand up to ordinary mathematical practice, which presupposes an identity relation that, in a sense, cannot be defined. In complex analysis, the two square roots of –1 are indiscernible: anything true of one of them is true of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  32. Categorical Foundations and Mathematical Practice.C. McLarty - 2012 - Philosophia Mathematica 20 (1):111-113.
    Linnebo and Pettigrew's critique in this journal of categorical foundations well emphasizes that the particulars of various categorical foundations matter, and that mathematical practice must be a major consideration. But several categorists named by the authors as proposing categorical foundations do not propose foundations, notably Awodey, and the article's description of current textbook practice seems inaccurate. They say that categorical foundations have justificatory autonomy if and only if mathematics can be justified simply by its practice. Do they seriously believe (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Accuracy-dominance and conditionalization.Michael Nielsen - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 178 (10):3217-3236.
    Epistemic decision theory produces arguments with both normative and mathematical premises. I begin by arguing that philosophers should care about whether the mathematical premises (1) are true, (2) are strong, and (3) admit simple proofs. I then discuss a theorem that Briggs and Pettigrew (2020) use as a premise in a novel accuracy-dominance argument for conditionalization. I argue that the theorem and its proof can be improved in a number of ways. First, I present a counterexample that shows that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34. Accuracy for Believers.Julia Staffel - 2017 - Episteme 14 (1):39-48.
    In Accuracy and the Laws of Credence Richard Pettigrew assumes a particular view of belief, which states that people don't have any other doxastic states besides credences. This is in tension with the popular position that people have both credences and outright beliefs. Pettigrew claims that such a dual view of belief is incompatible with the accuracy-first approach. I argue in this paper that it is not. This is good news for Pettigrew, since it broadens the appeal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  35.  44
    The Principal Principle, admissibility, and normal informal standards of what is reasonable.Jürgen Landes, Christian Wallmann & Jon Williamson - 2021 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (2):1-15.
    This paper highlights the role of Lewis’ Principal Principle and certain auxiliary conditions on admissibility as serving to explicate normal informal standards of what is reasonable. These considerations motivate the presuppositions of the argument that the Principal Principle implies the Principle of Indifference, put forward by Hawthorne et al.. They also suggest a line of response to recent criticisms of that argument, due to Pettigrew and Titelbaum and Hart, 621–632, 2020). The paper also shows that related concerns of Hart (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36. On Accuracy and Coherence with Infinite Opinion Sets.Mikayla Kelley - 2023 - Philosophy of Science 90 (1):92-128.
    There is a well-known equivalence between avoiding accuracy dominance and having probabilistically coherent credences (see, e.g., de Finetti 1974, Joyce 2009, Predd et al. 2009, Pettigrew 2016). However, this equivalence has been established only when the set of propositions on which credence functions are defined is finite. In this paper, I establish connections between accuracy dominance and coherence when credence functions are defined on an infinite set of propositions. In particular, I establish the necessary results to extend the classic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37. Criteria of identity and structuralist ontology.Hannes Leitgib & James Ladyman - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):388-396.
    In discussions about whether the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles is compatible with structuralist ontologies of mathematics, it is usually assumed that individual objects are subject to criteria of identity which somehow account for the identity of the individuals. Much of this debate concerns structures that admit of non-trivial automorphisms. We consider cases from graph theory that violate even weak formulations of PII. We argue that (i) the identity or difference of places in a structure is not to be (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  38.  39
    A rational route to transformative decisions.Daniel Https://Orcidorg624X Villiger - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):14535-14553.
    According to Paul (Transformative experience, 1st edn, Oxford University Press, 2014), transformative experiences pose a challenge to decision theory since their value cannot be anticipated. Building on Pettigrew’s (in: Lambert, Schwenkler (eds) Becoming someone new: essays on transformative experience, choice, and change, Oxford University Press, pp 100–121, 2020) redescription, this paper presents a new approach to how and when transformative decisions can nevertheless be made rationally. Thanks to fundamental higher-order facts that apply to any kind of experience, an agent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Can All-Accuracy Accounts Justify Evidential Norms?Christopher J. G. Meacham - 2018 - In Kristoffer Ahlstrom-Vij & Jeff Dunn (eds.), Epistemic Consequentialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Some of the most interesting recent work in formal epistemology has focused on developing accuracy-based approaches to justifying Bayesian norms. These approaches are interesting not only because they offer new ways to justify these norms, but because they potentially offer a way to justify all of these norms by appeal to a single, attractive epistemic goal: having accurate beliefs. Recently, Easwaran & Fitelson (2012) have raised worries regarding whether such “all-accuracy” or “purely alethic” approaches can accommodate and justify evidential Bayesian (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40. The problems of transformative experience.Yoaav Isaacs - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (4):1065-1084.
    Laurie Paul has recently argued that transformative experiences pose a problem for decision theory. According to Paul, agents facing transformative experiences do not possess the states required for decision theory to formulate its prescriptions. Agents facing transformative experiences are impoverished relative to their decision problems, and decision theory doesn’t know what to do with impoverished agents. Richard Pettigrew takes Paul’s challenge seriously. He grants that decision theory cannot handle decision problems involving transformative experiences. To deal with the problems posed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  36
    Why Average When You Can Stack? Better Methods for Generating Accurate Group Credences.David Kinney - 2022 - Philosophy of Science 89 (4):845-863.
    Formal and social epistemologists have devoted significant attention to the question of how to aggregate the credences of a group of agents who disagree about the probabilities of events. Moss and Pettigrew argue that group credences can be a linear mean of the credences of each individual in the group. By contrast, I argue that if the epistemic value of a credence function is determined solely by its accuracy, then we should, where possible, aggregate the underlying statistical models that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  59
    Sleeping Beauty and the Evidential Centered Principle.Namjoong Kim - 2024 - Erkenntnis 89 (5):2073-2095.
    Since Elga published his “Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem,” there has been an intense debate about which credence between 1/2 and 1/3 Beauty should assign to (H) the coin’s landing heads, when she is awakened on Monday. The Halfers claim that she ought to assign 1/2 to H at that moment. The Thirders argue that she ought to assign 1/3 to H then. Meanwhile, Pettigrew defended a new chance-credence coordination principle, called the “Evidential Temporal Principle” (ETP), in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Choosing for Changing Selves. [REVIEW]L. A. Paul - 2022 - Philosophical Review 131 (2):230-235.
    Review of Richard Pettigrew, Choosing for Changing Selves.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  76
    Falsificationism is not just ‘potential’ falsifiability, but requires ‘actual’ falsification: Social psychology, critical rationalism, and progress in science.Peter Holtz & Peter Monnerjahn - 2017 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 47 (3):348-362.
    Based on an analysis of ten popular introductions to social psychology, we will show that Karl Popper's philosophy of ‘critical rationalism’ so far has had little to no traceable influence on the epistemology and practice of social psychology. If Popper is quoted or mentioned in the textbooks at all, the guiding principle of ‘falsificationism’ is reduced to a mere ‘falsifiability’ and some central elements of critical rationalism are left out – those that are incompatible with positivism and inductivism. Echoing earlier (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  74
    Shrinking three arguments for conditionalization.Sophie Horowitz - 2021 - Philosophical Perspectives 35 (1):303-319.
    I argue that three arguments for conditionalization -- the Diachronic Dutch Book, the expected-accuracy maximization argument from Greaves and Wallace, and the accuracy-dominance argument from Briggs and Pettigrew -- can all be improved by narrowing their focus. I suggest alternative, targeted arguments which better identify the flaw involved in non-conditionalizing updates.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Ideal counterpart theorizing and the accuracy argument for probabilism.Clinton Castro & Olav Vassend - 2018 - Analysis 78 (2):207-216.
    One of the main goals of Bayesian epistemology is to justify the rational norms credence functions ought to obey. Accuracy arguments attempt to justify these norms from the assumption that the source of value for credences relevant to their epistemic status is their accuracy. This assumption and some standard decision-theoretic principles are used to argue for norms like Probabilism, the thesis that an agent’s credence function is rational only if it obeys the probability axioms. We introduce an example that shows (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  32
    A novel Process Reliabilist response to the Swamping Problem.Sanford Goldberg - 2023 - Analysis 83 (3):465-473.
    This paper aims to provide a novel response on behalf of Process Reliabilism to the Swamping Problem. Unlike previous responses, the present response does not involve conditional probabilities (as Goldman and Olsson do), it does not appeal to permissivism or attitudes towards epistemic risk (as Pettigrew does), it will not depend on the generality of the problem (as Carter and Jarvis do) and it does not embrace either evidentialism or evidence monism (as Bjelde does). Instead it appeals to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  30
    Laws of Credence and Laws of Choice.Sophie Horowitz - 2017 - Episteme 14 (1):31-37.
    ABSTRACTInAccuracy and the Laws of Credence, Richard Pettigrew gives several decision-theoretic arguments for formal requirements on rational credence. Pettigrew's arguments build on a central notion of epistemic value, but employ different decision rules. These comments explore how our choice of decision rule might matter, and discuss one of Pettigrew's arguments in detail: his argument for the Principle of Indifference, which relies on Maximin.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Chance, Credence and Circles.Fabrizio Cariani - 2017 - Episteme 14 (1):49-58.
    This is a discussion of Richard Pettigrew's book "Accuracy and the Laws of Credence". I target Pettigrew's application of the accuracy framework to derive chance-credence principles. My principal contention is that Pettigrew's preferred version of the argument might in one sense be circular and, moreover, that Pettigrew's premises have content that go beyond that of standard chance-credence principles.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  57
    The Value of Risk in Transformative Experience.Petronella Randell - forthcoming - Episteme:1-13.
    Risk is inherent to many, if not all, transformative decisions. The risk of regret, of turning into a person you presently consider to be morally objectionable, or of value change are all risks of choosing to transform. This aspect of transformative decision-making has thus far been ignored, but carries important consequences to those wishing to defend decision theory from the challenge posed by transformative decision-making. I contend that a problem lies in a common method used to cardinalise utilities – the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 53