Results for 'Unsharp quadrature observables'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  5
    On the Complementarity of the Quadrature Observables.Pekka Lahti & Juha-Pekka Pellonpää - 2010 - Foundations of Physics 40 (9-10):1419-1428.
    In this paper we investigate the coupling properties of pairs of quadrature observables, showing that, apart from the Weyl relation, they share the same coupling properties as the position-momentum pair. In particular, they are complementary. We determine the marginal observables of a covariant phase space observable with respect to an arbitrary rotated reference frame, and observe that these marginal observables are unsharp quadrature observables. The related distributions constitute the Radon transform of a phase (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  22
    Unsharp Quantum Reality.Paul Busch & Gregg Jaeger - 2010 - Foundations of Physics 40 (9-10):1341-1367.
    The positive operator (valued) measures (POMs) allow one to generalize the notion of observable beyond the traditional one based on projection valued measures (PVMs). Here, we argue that this generalized conception of observable enables a consistent notion of unsharp reality and with it an adequate concept of joint properties. A sharp or unsharp property manifests itself as an element of sharp or unsharp reality by its tendency to become actual or to actualize a specific measurement outcome. This (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  12
    Unsharp particle-wave duality in a photon split-beam experiment.P. Mittelstaedt, A. Prieur & R. Schieder - 1987 - Foundations of Physics 17 (9):891-903.
    In a quantum mechanical two-slit experiment one can observe a single photon simultaneously as particle (measuring the path) and as wave (measuring the interference pattern) if the path and the interference pattern are measured in the sense of unsharp observables. These theoretical predictions are confirmed experimentally by a photon split-beam experiment using a modified Mach—Zehnder interferometer.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  4.  5
    Quantum Unsharpness, Potentiality, and Reality.Gregg Jaeger - 2019 - Foundations of Physics 49 (6):663-676.
    Paul Busch argued that the positive operator measure, a generalization of the standard quantum observable, enables a consistent notion of unsharp reality based on a quantifiable degree of reality whereby systems can possess generalized properties jointly, whereas related sharp properties cannot be so possessed. Here, the work leading up to the formalization of this notion to which he made great contributions is reviewed and explicated in relation to Heisenberg’s notions of potentiality and actuality. The notion of unsharp reality (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  7
    EPR-Bell Tests with Unsharp Observables and Relativistic Quantum Measurement.Paul Busch - 2002 - In Tomasz Placek & Jeremy Butterfield (eds.), Non-locality and Modality. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 175--193.
  6.  8
    A concrete procedure for obtaining sharp reconstructions of unsharp observables in finite-dimensional quantum mechanics.Gianpiero Cattaneo, Tiziana Marsico, Giuseppe Nisticò & Guido Bacciagaluppi - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (10):1323-1343.
    We discuss the problem of how a (commutative) generalized observable in a finite-dimensional Hilbert space (communtative effect-valued resolution of the identity) can be considered as an unsharp realization of some standard observable (projection-valued resolution of the identity). In particular, we give a concrete procedure for constructing such a standard observable. Some results about the “uniqueness” of the resulting observable are also examined.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  2
    Axiomatic unsharp quantum theory (From Mackey to Ludwig and Piron).Gianpiero Cattaneo & Federico Laudisa - 1994 - Foundations of Physics 24 (5):631-683.
    On the basis of Mackey's axiomatic approach to quantum physics or, equivalently, of a “state-event-probability” (SEVP) structure, using a quite standard “fuzzification” procedure, a set of unsharp events (or “effects”) is constructed and the corresponding “state-effect-probability” (SEFP) structure is introduced. The introduction of some suitable axioms gives rise to a partially ordered structure of quantum Brouwer-Zadeh (BZ) poset; i.e., a poset endowed with two nonusual orthocomplementation mappings, a fuzzy-like orthocomplementation, and an intuitionistic-like orthocomplementation, whose set of sharp elements is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8.  8
    Insolubility of the quantum measurement problem for unsharp observables.Paul Busch & Abner Shimony - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (4):397-404.
  9.  9
    Insolubility of the quantum measurement problem for unsharp observables.Paul Busch & Abner Shimony - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (4):397-404.
  10.  7
    A Kochen-Specker theorem for unsharp spin 1 observables.Thomas Breuer - 2002 - In Tomasz Placek & Jeremy Butterfield (eds.), Non-locality and Modality. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 195--203.
  11.  6
    Complementary Observables in Quantum Mechanics.Jukka Kiukas, Pekka Lahti, Juha-Pekka Pellonpää & Kari Ylinen - 2019 - Foundations of Physics 49 (6):506-531.
    We review the notion of complementarity of observables in quantum mechanics, as formulated and studied by Paul Busch and his colleagues over the years. In addition, we provide further clarification on the operational meaning of the concept, and present several characterisations of complementarity—some of which new—in a unified manner, as a consequence of a basic factorisation lemma for quantum effects. We work out several applications, including the canonical cases of position–momentum, position–energy, number–phase, as well as periodic observables relevant (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  6
    Another no‐go theorem for hidden variable models of inaccurate spin 1 measurements.Thomas Breuer - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1368-1379.
    Uncertainty about the actual orientation of the measurement device has been claimed to open a loophole for hidden variable models of quantum mechanics. In this paper I describe the statistics of inaccurate spin measurements by unsharp spin observables. A no‐go theorem for hidden variable models of the inaccurate measurement statistics follows: There is a finite set of directions for which not all results of inaccurate spin measurements can be predetermined in a non‐contextual way. In contrast to an earlier (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  9
    Another No‐go Theorem for Hidden Variable Models of Inaccurate Spin 1 Measurements.Thomas Breuer - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1368-1379.
    Uncertainty about the actual orientation of the measurement device has been claimed to open a loophole for hidden variable models of quantum mechanics. In this paper I describe the statistics of inaccurate spin measurements by unsharp spin observables. A no-go theorem for hidden variable models of the inaccurate measurement statistics follows: There is a finite set of directions for which not all results of inaccurate spin measurements can be predetermined in a non-contextual way. In contrast to an earlier (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  15
    On the Sharpness and Bias of Quantum Effects.Paul Busch - 2009 - Foundations of Physics 39 (7):712-730.
    The question of quantifying the sharpness (or unsharpness) of a quantum mechanical effect is investigated. Apart from sharpness, another property, bias, is found to be relevant for the joint measurability or coexistence of two effects. Measures of bias will be defined and examples given.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  47
    Hero and the tradition of the circle segment.Henry Mendell - 2023 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 77 (5):451-499.
    In his Metrica, Hero provides four procedures for finding the area of a circular segment (with b the base of the segment and h its height): an Ancient method for when the segment is smaller than a semicircle, $$(b + h)/2 \, \cdot \, h$$ ( b + h ) / 2 · h ; a Revision, $$(b + h)/2 \, \cdot \, h + (b/2)^{2} /14$$ ( b + h ) / 2 · h + ( b / 2 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  4
    Euler’s beta integral in Pietro Mengoli’s works.Amadeu Delshams & Ma Rosa Massa Esteve - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (3):325-356.
    Beta integrals for several non-integer values of the exponents were calculated by Leonhard Euler in 1730, when he was trying to find the general term for the factorial function by means of an algebraic expression. Nevertheless, 70 years before, Pietro Mengoli (1626–1686) had computed such integrals for natural and half-integer exponents in his Geometriae Speciosae Elementa (1659) and Circolo(1672) and displayed the results in triangular tables. In particular, his new arithmetic–algebraic method allowed him to compute the quadrature of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  6
    Quantization by parts, self-adjoint extensions, and a novel derivation of the Josephson equation in superconductivity.K. Kong Wan & R. H. Fountain - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (9):1165-1199.
    There has been a lot of interest in generalizing orthodox quantum mechanics to include POV measures as observables, namely as unsharp obserrables. Such POV measures are related to symmetric operators. We have argued recently that only maximal symmetric operators should describe observables.1 This generalization to maximal symmetric operators has many physical applications. One application is in the area of quantization. We shall discuss a scheme, to he called quantization by parts,which can systematically deal with what may be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  25
    Nondemolition principle of quantum measurement theory.V. P. Belavkin - 1994 - Foundations of Physics 24 (5):685-714.
    We give an explicit axiomatic formulation of the quantum measurement theory which is free of the projection postulate. It is based on the generalized nondemolition principle applicable also to the unsharp, continuous-spectrum and continuous-in-time observations. The “collapsed state-vector” after the “objectification” is simply treated as a random vector of the a posterioristate given by the quantum filtering, i.e., the conditioning of the a prioriinduced state on the corresponding reduced algebra. The nonlinear phenomenological equation of “continuous spontaneous localization” has been (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  6
    Dimensional characterization in finite quasi-analysis.Daniel Schoch - 2001 - Erkenntnis 54 (1):121-131.
    The method of Quasi-Analysis used by Carnap in his program of theconstitution of concepts from finite observations has the following twogoals: (1) Given unsharp observations in terms of similarity relations thetrue properties of the observed objects shall be obtained by a suitablelogical construction. (2) From a single relation on a finite domain,different dimensions of qualities shall be reconstructed and identified. Inthis article I show that with a slight modification Quasi-Analysis iscapable of fulfilling the first goal for a single observable (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  8
    On the reality of spin and helicity.Paul Busch & Franklin E. Schroeck - 1989 - Foundations of Physics 19 (7):807-872.
    The possibilities of a realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics are investigated by means of a statistical analysis of experiments performed on the simplest type of quantum systems carrying spin or helicity. To this end, fundamental experiments, some new, for measuring polarization are reviewed and (re)analyzed. Theunsharp reality of spin is essential in the interpretation of some of these experiments and represents a natural motivation for recent generalizations of quantum mechanics to a theory incorporating effect-valued measures as unsharp observables (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21.  7
    Complementarity and uncertainty in Mach-zehnder interferometry and beyond.Paul Busch & Christopher Shilladay - unknown
    A coherent account of the connections and contrasts between the principles of complementarity and uncertainty is developed starting from a survey of the various formalizations of these principles. The conceptual analysis is illustrated by means of a set of experimental schemes based on Mach-Zehnder interferometry. In particular, path detection via entanglement with a probe system and (quantitative) quantum erasure are exhibited to constitute instances of joint unsharp measurements of complementary pairs of physical quantities, path and interference observables. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  6
    Philosophy of Science Association Observation Reconsidered.Observation Reconsidered - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (1):23-43.
    Several arguments are considered which purport to demonstrate the impossibility of theory-neutral observation. The most important of these infers the continuity of observation with theory from the presumed continuity of perception with cognition, a doctrine widely espoused in recent cognitive psychology. An alternative psychological account of the relation between cognition and perception is proposed and its epistemological consequences for the observation/theory distinction are then explored.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  3
    Julie Zahle.Participant Observation & Objectivity In Anthropology - 2013 - In Hanne Andersen, Dennis Dieks, Wenceslao J. Gonzalez, Thomas Uebel & Gregory Wheeler (eds.), New Challenges to Philosophy of Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 365.
  24.  11
    Kersten Reich.Participants Observers - 2009 - In Larry A. Hickman, Stefan Neubert & Kersten Reich (eds.), John Dewey between pragmatism and constructivism. New York: Fordham University Press. pp. 106.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  2
    Oe tl-mesons and oranges.Of Observability - 2008 - In Bernd Prien & David P. Schweikard (eds.), Robert Brandom: Analytic Pragmatist. ontos. pp. 10--59.
  26.  12
    Local Measurements of Nonlocal Observables and the Relativistic Reduction Process.GianCarlo Ghirardi - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (9):1337-1385.
    In this paper we reconsider the constraints which are imposed by relativistic requirements to any model of dynamical reduction. We review the debate on the subject and we call attention on the fundamental contributions by Aharonov and Albert. Having done this we present a new formulation, which is much simpler and more apt for our analysis, of the proposal put forward by these authors to perform measurements of nonlocal observables by means of local interactions and detections. We take into (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  27.  22
    Hidden Variables and Incompatible Observables in Quantum Mechanics.Benjamin Feintzeig - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (4):905-927.
    This article takes up a suggestion that the reason we cannot find certain hidden variable theories for quantum mechanics, as in Bell’s theorem, is that we require them to assign joint probability distributions on incompatible observables. These joint distributions are problematic because they are empirically meaningless on one standard interpretation of quantum mechanics. Some have proposed getting around this problem by using generalized probability spaces. I present a theorem to show a sense in which generalized probability spaces can’t serve (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  1
    Les observables et les participables.Raymond Ruyer - 1966 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 156:419 - 450.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  3
    Observables, Unobservables, and the "Disappearance" Version of the Identity Theory.Edward S. Shirley - 1974 - Journal of Critical Analysis 5 (3):99-103.
  30.  3
    Observables, Unobservables, and the.Edward S. Shirley - 1974 - Journal of Critical Analysis 5 (3):99-103.
  31.  8
    The image of observables.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):585-597.
    This paper challenges a central tenet of constructive empiricism, namely that empirical adequacy has a privileged epistemic status. I argue that perceptions of observables are theory-wrought, and theory-wrought in the same ways as the observation sentences we use to describe those perceptions, van Fraassen can draw no privileged or fundamental distinction between what we observe and interpreting those observations through theory. Since empirical adequacy depends upon accurately describing what we observe, and we have no theory-independent reason to believe that (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  10
    Peter Bergmann on observables in Hamiltonian General Relativity: A historical-critical investigation.J. Brian Pitts - 2022 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 95 (C):1-27.
  33.  6
    1.'Observables' versus beables.Rob Clifton - 1999 - In Jeremy Butterfield & Constantine Pagonis (eds.), From Physics to Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 12.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  6
    On the observables on quantum logics.S. Pulmannová - 1981 - Foundations of Physics 11 (1-2):127-136.
    Two postulates concerning observables on a quantum logic are formulated. By Postulate 1 compatibility of observables is defined by the strong topology on the set of observables. Postulate 2 requires that the range of the sum of observables ought to be contained in the smallestC-closed sublogic generated by their ranges. It is shown that the Hilbert space logicL(H) satisfies the two postulates. A theorem on the connection between joint distributions of types 1 and 2 on the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  8
    Compatible stochastic observables that do not commute.Franklin E. Schroeck - 1985 - Foundations of Physics 15 (6):677-681.
    It is shown that stochastic observables defined by an instrument need not, and generally do not, commute.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  9
    Convergence of observables on quantum logics.W. Tomé & S. Gudder - 1990 - Foundations of Physics 20 (4):417-434.
    We define two types of convergence for observables on a quantum logic which we call M-weak and uniform M-weak convergence. These convergence modes correspond to weak convergence of probability measures. They are motivated by the idea that two (in general unbounded) observables are “close” if bounded functions of them are “close.” We show that M-weak and uniform M-weak convergence generalize strong resolvent and norm resolvent convergence for self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. Also, these types of convergence strengthen (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  8
    Determinate values for quantum observables.Roderich Tumulka - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2):355 - 360.
    This is a comment on J. A. Barrett's article 'The Preferred-Basis Problem and the Quantum Mechanics of Everything' ([2005]), which concerns theories postulating that certain quantum observables have determinate values, corresponding to additional (often called 'hidden') variables. I point out that it is far from clear, for most observables, what such a postulate is supposed to mean, unless the postulated additional variable is related to a clear ontology in space-time, such as particle world lines, string world sheets, or (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  12
    A General Perspective On Time Observables.Bryan W. Roberts - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 47:50-54.
    I propose a general geometric framework in which to discuss the existence of time observables. This framework allows one to describe a local sense in which time observables always exist, and a global sense in which they can sometimes exist subject to a restriction on the vector fields that they generate. Pauli׳s prohibition on quantum time observables is derived as a corollary to this result. I will then discuss how time observables can be regained in modest (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39.  2
    Empirical relations between noncommuting observables.Giuseppe NisticÒ - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (12):1757-1767.
    A relation ≺ϕ between noncommuting 1-0 quantum observables (i.e., projections) is introduced, ϕ being the state vector of the system. This relation extends the empirical implication between commuting projections. An operational interpretation of the new relation is given, which can be expressed also in counterfactual terms. It is shown that a relation proposed some years ago by Hardegree, namely the Sasaki arrow ↪ϕ, can be interpreted in terms of the relation ≺ϕ; furthermore, this new relation turns out to be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  4
    Langage, mathématiques, et observables.Pius Servien - 1960 - Atti Del XII Congresso Internazionale di Filosofia 5:499-503.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  6
    La représentation mathématique des observables.Pius Servien - 1956 - Synthese 10:71.
  42.  9
    Equivalent Theories and Changing Hamiltonian Observables in General Relativity.J. Brian Pitts - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (5):579-590.
    Change and local spatial variation are missing in Hamiltonian general relativity according to the most common definition of observables as having 0 Poisson bracket with all first-class constraints. But other definitions of observables have been proposed. In pursuit of Hamiltonian–Lagrangian equivalence, Pons, Salisbury and Sundermeyer use the Anderson–Bergmann–Castellani gauge generator G, a tuned sum of first-class constraints. Kuchař waived the 0 Poisson bracket condition for the Hamiltonian constraint to achieve changing observables. A systematic combination of the two (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  2
    Alexander, D.(2002). UK Government: Alexander challenges business–“Social responsibility must not be just skin deep”. Coventry: M2 Presswire. [REVIEW]Oecd Observer - 2004 - Business Ethics 17 (9/10):1093-1102.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  6
    Toward an Understanding of Parochial Observables.Benjamin Feintzeig - 2018 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (1):161-191.
    ABSTRACT Ruetsche claims that an abstract C*-algebra of observables will not contain all of the physically significant observables for a quantum system with infinitely many degrees of freedom. This would signal that in addition to the abstract algebra, one must use Hilbert space representations for some purposes. I argue to the contrary that there is a way to recover all of the physically significant observables by purely algebraic methods. 1Introduction 2Preliminaries 3Three Extremist Interpretations 3.1Algebraic imperialism 3.2Hilbert space (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  10
    Complementarity of Mental Observables.Irina Basieva & Andrei Khrennikov - 2014 - Topics in Cognitive Science 6 (1):74-78.
    The aim of this note is to complete the discussion on the possibility of creation of quantum-like (QL) representation for the question order effect which was presented by Wang and Busemeyer (2013). We analyze the role of a fundamental feature of mental operators (given, e.g., by questions), namely, their complementarity.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  4
    Toward an Understanding of Parochial Observables.Benjamin Feintzeig - 2016 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science:axw010.
    Ruetsche claims that an abstract C*-algebra of observables will not contain all of the physically significant observables for a quantum system with infinitely many degrees of freedom. This would signal that in addition to the abstract algebra, one must use Hilbert space representations for some purposes. I argue to the contrary that there is a way to recover all of the physically significant observables by purely algebraic methods. 1 Introduction2 Preliminaries3 Three Extremist Interpretations3.1 Algebraic imperialism3.2 Hilbert space (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  47.  2
    ‘Einselection’ of pointer observables: The new H-theorem?Ruth E. Kastner - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 48 (1):56-58.
    In attempting to derive irreversible macroscopic thermodynamics from reversible microscopic dynamics, Boltzmann inadvertently smuggled in a premise that assumed the very irreversibility he was trying to prove: ‘molecular chaos.’ The program of ‘Einselection’ within Everettian approaches faces a similar ‘Loschmidt’s Paradox’: the universe, according to the Everettian picture, is a closed system obeying only unitary dynamics, and it therefore contains no distinguishable environmental subsystems with the necessary ‘phase randomness’ to effect einselection of a pointer observable. The theoretically unjustified assumption of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  48. Essays on Philanthropy and Civilization.Ma Lerner & A. Gift Observed - forthcoming - Common Knowledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  7
    The role of observables and non-observables in chemistry: A critique of chemical language. [REVIEW]Shant Shahbazian & Mansour Zahedi - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 8 (1):37-52.
    In this paper, aspects of observable and non-observable based models are discussed. A survey of recent literature was done to show how using non-observable-based language carelessly may cause disagreement, even in professional research programs and incorrect assertions, even in prestigious journals. The relation between physical measurements and observables is discussed and it is shown that, in contrast to general belief, this relation may be complicated and not always straightforward. The decomposition of the system into basic subsystems (physical or conceptual) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  50.  18
    An Einstein manuscript on the EPR paradox for spin observables.Tilman Sauer - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (4):879-887.
    A formulation by Einstein of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen incompleteness argument found in his scientific manuscripts is presented and briefly commented on. It is the only known version in which Einstein discussed the argument for spin observables. The manuscript dates, in all probability, from late 1954 or early 1955 and hence also represents Einstein's latest version of the incompleteness argument and one of his last statements on quantum theory in general. A puzzling formulation raises the question of Einstein's interpretation of space (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000