Switch to: Citations

References in:

Moore’s Paradox for God

Philosophia 47 (1):265-270 (2019)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A reply to my critics.George Edward Moore - 1942 - In Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore. New York,: Tudor Pub. Co..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • God and Other Minds: A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God.Alvin Plantinga - 1967 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
    Can belief in God be rationally justified? Reviewing in detail traditional and modern arguments for and against the existence of God, Professor Plantinga concludes that they must all be judged unsuccessful. He then turns to the related philosophical problem of the existence of other minds, and defends the so-called analogical argument against current criticisms. He goes on to show, however, that although this argument affords us the best reasons we have for belief in other minds, it finally succumbs to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Moore’s Paradox and the Priority of Belief Thesis.John N. Williams - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (3):1117-1138.
    Moore’s paradox is the fact that assertions or beliefs such asBangkok is the capital of Thailand but I do not believe that Bangkok is the capital of Thailand or Bangkok is the capital of Thailand but I believe that Bangkok is not the capital of Thailand are ‘absurd’ yet possibly true. The current orthodoxy is that an explanation of the absurdity should first start with belief, on the assumption that once the absurdity in belief has been explained then this will (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Moore's Paradox in Thought: A Critical Survey.John N. Williams - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (1):24-37.
    It is raining but you don’t believe that it is raining. Imagine silently accepting this claim. Then you believe both that it is raining and that you don’t believe that it is raining. This would be an ‘absurd’ thing to believe,yet what you believe might be true. Itmight be raining, while at the same time, you are completely ignorant of the state of the weather. But how can it be absurd of you to believe something about yourself that might be (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Moore’s Paradox in Speech: A Critical Survey.John N. Williams - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (1):10-23.
    It is raining but you don’t believe that it is raining. Imagine accepting this claim. Then you are committed to saying ‘It is raining but I don’t believe that it is raining’. This would be an ‘absurd’ thing to claim or assert, yet what you say might be true. It might be raining, while at the same time, you are completely ignorant of the state of the weather. But how can it be absurd of you to assert something about yourself (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Moorean Absurdity and the Intentional 'Structure' of Assertion.John N. Williams - 1994 - Analysis 54 (3):160 - 166.
  • Presupposition, implication, and self-reference.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (5):136-152.
  • Blindspots.Michael Levin - 1991 - Noûs 25 (3):389-392.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • On Doxastic Justification and Properly Basing One’s Beliefs.Paul Silva - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (5):945-955.
    According to an orthodox account of the relationship between propositional and doxastic justification, basing one’s belief in P on one’s source of propositional justification to believe P suffices for having a doxastically justified belief. But in an increasingly recognized work Turri argues that this thesis fails and proposes a new view according to which having propositional justification depends on having the ability to acquire doxastic justification. Turri’s novel position has surprisingly far-reaching epistemological consequences, ruling out some common epistemological positions that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind, by John Searle. [REVIEW]Mark William Rowe - 1992 - Philosophy 68 (265):415-418.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   649 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind.John R. Searle - 1992 - MIT Press. Edited by Ned Block & Hilary Putnam.
    The title of The Rediscovery of the Mind suggests the question "When was the mind lost?" Since most people may not be aware that it ever was lost, we must also then ask "Who lost it?" It was lost, of course, only by philosophers, by certain philosophers. This passed unnoticed by society at large. The "rediscovery" is also likely to pass unnoticed. But has the mind been rediscovered by the same philosophers who "lost" it? Probably not. John Searle is an (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   666 citations  
  • Truth, Omniscience, and Cantorian Arguments: An Exchange.Alvin Plantinga & Patrick Grim - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (3):267-306.
    An exchange between Patrick Grim and Alvin Plantinga regarding Cantorian arguments against the possibility of an omniscient being.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Russell's "Theory of Descriptions.".G. E. Moore - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):78-78.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • ``Truth, Omniscience and Cantorian Arguments: An Exchange". [REVIEW]Patrick Grim & Alvin Plantinga - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (3):267-306.
  • Logic and limits of knowledge and truth.Patrick Grim - 1988 - Noûs 22 (3):341-367.
    Though my ultimate concern is with issues in epistemology and metaphysics, let me phrase the central question I will pursue in terms evocative of philosophy of religion: What are the implications of our logic-in particular, of Cantor and G6del-for the possibility of omniscience?
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Epistemic closure, skepticism and defeasibility.Claudio de Almeida - 2012 - Synthese 188 (2):197-215.
    Those of us who have followed Fred Dretske’s lead with regard to epistemic closure and its impact on skepticism have been half-wrong for the last four decades. But those who have opposed our Dretskean stance, contextualists in particular, have been just wrong. We have been half-right. Dretske rightly claimed that epistemic status is not closed under logical implication. Unlike the Dretskean cases, the new counterexamples to closure offered here render every form of contextualist pro-closure maneuvering useless. But there is a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • God and Other Minds: A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God.I. M. Crombie - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (80):312.
  • Belief and Indeterminacy.Michael Caie - 2012 - Philosophical Review 121 (1):1-54.
    An attractive approach to the semantic paradoxes holds that cases of semantic pathology give rise to indeterminacy. What attitude should a rational agent have toward a proposition that it takes to be indeterminate in this sense? Orthodoxy holds that rationality requires that an agent disbelieve such a proposition. I argue that a rational agent should be such that it is indeterminate whether it believes the proposition in question. For rational agents, indeterminacy in the objects of their attitudes will filter up (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Epistemic closure, skepticism and defeasibility.Claudio Almeida - 2012 - Synthese 188 (2):197-215.
    Those of us who have followed Fred Dretske's lead with regard to epistemic closure and its impact on skepticism have been half-wrong for the last four decades. But those who have opposed our Dretskean stance, contextualists in particular, have been just wrong. We have been half-right. Dretske rightly claimed that epistemic status is not closed under logical implication. Unlike the Dretskean cases, the new counterexamples to closure offered here render every form of contextualist pro-closure maneuvering useless. But there is a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Selected writings.George Edward Moore - 1993 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Thomas Baldwin.
    G. E. Moore was one of the most interesting and influential philosophers of the first half of the twentieth century. This selection of his writings makes the best of his work once again available, and also includes previously unpublished writings. Moore's first published writings, represented in this collection by his papers "The Nature of Judgment" and "The Refutation of Idealism," contributed decisively to the break with idealism which led to the development of analytic philosophy. Moore went on to develop his (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The Rediscovery of the Mind.John Searle - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (1):201-207.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   496 citations  
  • Blindspots.Roy Sorensen - 1990 - Mind 99 (393):137-140.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • God and Other Minds: A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God.Alvin Plantinga - 1969 - Religious Studies 4 (2):288-291.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations