Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Human and nonhuman systems are adaptive in a different sense.Tamás Zétényi - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):507-508.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational resources do constrain behavior.John K. Tsotsos - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):506-507.
  • Sketch of a componential subtheory of human intelligence.Robert J. Sternberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):573-584.
  • Components of human intelligence.Robert J. Sternberg - 1983 - Cognition 15 (1-3):1-48.
  • Claims, counterclaims, and components: A countercritique of componential analysis.Robert J. Sternberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):599-614.
  • Componential analysis and componential theory.Robert J. Sternberg & Janet E. Davidson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):350-351.
  • Rationality and irrationality: Still fighting words.Paul Snow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):505-506.
  • A Bayesian theory of thought.Howard Smokler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):505-505.
  • But how does the brain think?Steven L. Small - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):504-505.
  • The rationality of causal inference.Thomas R. Shultz - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):503-504.
  • On the nonapplicability of a rational analysis to human cognition.Eldar Shafir - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):502-503.
  • Rational analysis will not throw off the yoke of the precision-importance trade-off function.Wolfgang Schwarz - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):501-502.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On theory and metatheory, and normal and revolutionary science.Joseph R. Royce - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):599-599.
  • Categorization as causal reasoning⋆.Bob Rehder - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (5):709-748.
    A theory of categorization is presented in which knowledge of causal relationships between category features is represented in terms of asymmetric and probabilistic causal mechanisms. According to causal‐model theory, objects are classified as category members to the extent they are likely to have been generated or produced by those mechanisms. The empirical results confirmed that participants rated exemplars good category members to the extent their features manifested the expectations that causal knowledge induces, such as correlations between feature pairs that are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The cognitive laboratory, the library and the Skinner box.Howard Rachlin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):501-501.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Three perspectives on intelligence.James W. Pellegrino - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):598-599.
  • A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 1994 - Psychological Review 101 (4):608-631.
  • Assessing interactive causal influence.Laura R. Novick & Patricia W. Cheng - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (2):455-485.
    The discovery of conjunctive causes--factors that act in concert to produce or prevent an effect--has been explained by purely covariational theories. Such theories assume that concomitant variations in observable events directly license causal inferences, without postulating the existence of unobservable causal relations. This article discusses problems with these theories, proposes a causal-power theory that overcomes the problems, and reports empirical evidence favoring the new theory. Unlike earlier models, the new theory derives (a) the conditions under which covariation implies conjunctive causation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Sufficiency and Necessity Assumptions in Causal Structure Induction.Ralf Mayrhofer & Michael R. Waldmann - 2016 - Cognitive Science 40 (8):2137-2150.
    Research on human causal induction has shown that people have general prior assumptions about causal strength and about how causes interact with the background. We propose that these prior assumptions about the parameters of causal systems do not only manifest themselves in estimations of causal strength or the selection of causes but also when deciding between alternative causal structures. In three experiments, we requested subjects to choose which of two observable variables was the cause and which the effect. We found (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Adaptive rationality and identifiability of psychological processes.Dominic W. Massaro & Daniel Friedman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):499-501.
  • Judgment dissociation theory: An analysis of differences in causal, counterfactual and covariational reasoning.David R. Mandel - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (3):419.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Effect of counterfactual and factual thinking on causal judgements.David R. Mandel - 2003 - Thinking and Reasoning 9 (3):245 – 265.
    The significance of counterfactual thinking in the causal judgement process has been emphasized for nearly two decades, yet no previous research has directly compared the relative effect of thinking counterfactually versus factually on causal judgement. Three experiments examined this comparison by manipulating the task frame used to focus participants' thinking about a target event. Prior to making judgements about causality, preventability, blame, and control, participants were directed to think about a target actor either in counterfactual terms (what the actor could (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Discovering and training the components of intelligence.Colin M. MacLeod - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):597-598.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • BUCKLE: A model of unobserved cause learning.Christian C. Luhmann & Woo-Kyoung Ahn - 2007 - Psychological Review 114 (3):657-677.
  • Bayesian generic priors for causal learning.Hongjing Lu, Alan L. Yuille, Mimi Liljeholm, Patricia W. Cheng & Keith J. Holyoak - 2008 - Psychological Review 115 (4):955-984.
  • Argument as Cognition: A Putnamian Criticism of Dale Hample’s Cognitive Conception of Argument.Louise Cummings - 2004 - Argumentation 18 (3):191-209.
    The study of argument has never before been so wide-ranging. The evidence for this claim is to be found in a growing number of different conceptions of argument, each of which purports to describe some component of argument that is effectively over-looked by other conceptions of this notion. Just this same sense that a vital component of argument is being overlooked by current conceptions of this notion is what motivates Dale Hample to pursue a specifically cognitive conception of argument. However, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intelligence: Toward a modern sketch of a good g.Herbert Lansdell - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):597-597.
  • Do reasoning limitations undermine discourse?Deanna Kuhn & Anahid Modrek - 2018 - Thinking and Reasoning 24 (1):97-116.
    Why does discourse so often seem shallow, with people arguing past one another more than with one another? Might contributing causes be individual and logical rather than only dialogical? We consider here whether there exist errors in reasoning that could be particularly damaging in their effects on argumentive discourse. In particular, we examine implications for discourse of two such errors – explanation as a replacement for evidence and neglecting the likelihood of multiple causes contributing to an outcome. In Studies 1 (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Factors or processes in intelligence.Paul Kline - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):596-597.
  • Confirmation, disconfirmation, and information in hypothesis testing.Joshua Klayman & Young-won Ha - 1987 - Psychological Review 94 (2):211-228.
  • Sternberg's sketchy theory: Defining details desired.Daniel P. Keating - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):595-596.
  • The language of componential analysis.Earl Hunt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):592-595.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What the Bayesian framework has contributed to understanding cognition: Causal learning as a case study.Keith J. Holyoak & Hongjing Lu - 2011 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (4):203-204.
    The field of causal learning and reasoning (largely overlooked in the target article) provides an illuminating case study of how the modern Bayesian framework has deepened theoretical understanding, resolved long-standing controversies, and guided development of new and more principled algorithmic models. This progress was guided in large part by the systematic formulation and empirical comparison of multiple alternative Bayesian models.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probing the “Achilles' heel” of rational analysis.Keith J. Holyoak - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):498-499.
  • Effects of amount of evidence and range of rule on the use of hypothesis and target tests by groups in rule-discovery tasks.Christine Hoffmann & Helmut Crott - 2004 - Thinking and Reasoning 10 (4):321 – 354.
    This experiment investigated the use of positive and negative hypothesis and target tests by groups in an adaptation of the 2-4-6 Wason task. The experimental variables were range of rule (small vs large), amount of evidence (low vs high), and trial block (1 vs 2). The results were in accordance with Klayman and Ha's (1987) analysis of base rate probabilities of falsification and with additional theoretical considerations. Base rate probabilities were more descriptive of participants' behaviour in target than in hypothesis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental models and causal explanation: Judgements of probable cause and explanatory relevance.Denis J. Hilton - 1996 - Thinking and Reasoning 2 (4):273 – 308.
    Good explanations are not only true or probably true, but are also relevant to a causal question. Current models of causal explanation either only address the question of the truth of an explanation, or do not distinguish the probability of an explanation from its relevance. The tasks of scenario construction and conversational explanation are distinguished, which in turn shows how scenarios can interact with conversational principles to determine the truth and relevance of explanations. The proposed model distinguishes causal discounting from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Dual frames for causal induction: the normative and the heuristic.Ikuko Hattori, Masasi Hattori, David E. Over, Tatsuji Takahashi & Jean Baratgin - 2017 - Thinking and Reasoning 23 (3):292-317.
    Causal induction in the real world often has to be quick and efficient as well as accurate. We propose that people use two different frames to achieve these goals. The A-frame consists of heuristic processes that presuppose rarity and can detect causally relevant factors quickly. The B-frame consists of analytic processes that can be highly accurate in detecting actual causes. Our dual frame theory implies that several factors affect whether people use the A-frame or the B-frame in causal induction: among (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptive Non‐Interventional Heuristics for Covariation Detection in Causal Induction: Model Comparison and Rational Analysis.Masasi Hattori & Mike Oaksford - 2007 - Cognitive Science 31 (5):765-814.
    In this article, 41 models of covariation detection from 2 × 2 contingency tables were evaluated against past data in the literature and against data from new experiments. A new model was also included based on a limiting case of the normative phi‐coefficient under an extreme rarity assumption, which has been shown to be an important factor in covariation detection (McKenzie & Mikkelsen, 2007) and data selection (Hattori, 2002; Oaksford & Chater, 1994, 2003). The results were supportive of the new (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Rational analysis and the Lens model.Reid Hastie & Kenneth R. Hammond - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):498-498.
  • Components versus factors.J. P. Guilford - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):591-592.
  • Bayes in the context of suboptimality.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):497-498.
  • Naive causality: a mental model theory of causal meaning and reasoning.Eugenia Goldvarg & P. N. Johnson-Laird - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (4):565-610.
    This paper outlines a theory and computer implementation of causal meanings and reasoning. The meanings depend on possibilities, and there are four weak causal relations: A causes B, A prevents B, A allows B, and A allows not‐B, and two stronger relations of cause and prevention. Thus, A causes B corresponds to three possibilities: A and B, not‐A and B, and not‐A and not‐B, with the temporal constraint that B does not precede A; and the stronger relation conveys only the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Optimality and psychological explanation.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):496-497.
  • Does the environment have the same structure as Bayes' theorem?Gerd Gigerenzer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):495-496.
  • Beyond Helmholtz, or why not include inner determinants from the beginning?Hans-Georg Geissler - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):494-495.
  • Examining the representation of causal knowledge.Jonathan A. Fugelsang, Valerie A. Thompson & Kevin N. Dunbar - 2006 - Thinking and Reasoning 12 (1):1 – 30.
    Three experiments investigated reasoners' beliefs about causal powers; that is, their beliefs about the capacity of a putative cause to produce a given effect. Covariation-based theories (e.g., Cheng, 1997; Kelley, 1973; Novick & Cheng, 2004) posit that beliefs in causal power are represented in terms of the degree of covariation between the cause and its effect; covariation is defined in terms of the degree to which the effect occurs in the presence of the cause, and fails tooccur in the absence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Thurstonian's reaction to a componential theory of intelligence.John R. Frederiksen - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):590-591.
  • Rational analysis and illogical inference.Edmund Fantino & Stephanie Stolarz-Fantino - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):494-494.
  • Adaptive cognition: The question is how.Jonathan St B. T. Evans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):493-494.
  • A heuristic for componential analysis: “Try old goals”.Dennis E. Egan - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):348-350.