Results for 'Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  96
    The BellKochenSpecker theorem.D. M. Appleby - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36 (1):1-28.
    Meyer, Kent and Clifton (MKC) claim to have nullified the Bell-Kochen-Specker (Bell-KS) theorem. It is true that they invalidate KS's account of the theorem's physical implications. However, they do not invalidate Bell's point, that quantum mechanics is inconsistent with the classical assumption, that a measurement tells us about a property previously possessed by the system. This failure of classical ideas about measurement is, perhaps, the single most important implication of quantum mechanics. In a (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  2. Logical Reflections On the Kochen-Specker Theorem.John L. Bell - unknown
    IN THEIR WELL-KNOWN PAPER, Kochen and Specker (1967) introduce the concept of partial Boolean algebra (pBa) and show that certain (finitely generated) partial Boolean algebras arising in quantum theory fail to possess morphisms to any Boolean algebra (we call such pBa's intractable in the sequel). In this note we begin by discussing partial..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3.  73
    Parity Proofs of the Bell-Kochen-Specker Theorem Based on the 600-cell.Mordecai Waegell, P. K. Aravind, Norman D. Megill & Mladen Pavičić - 2011 - Foundations of Physics 41 (5):883-904.
    The set of 60 real rays in four dimensions derived from the vertices of a 600-cell is shown to possess numerous subsets of rays and bases that provide basis-critical parity proofs of the Bell-Kochen-Specker (BKS) theorem (a basis-critical proof is one that fails if even a single basis is deleted from it). The proofs vary considerably in size, with the smallest having 26 rays and 13 bases and the largest 60 rays and 41 bases. There are (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. The Kochen-Specker theorem and Bell's theorem: An algebraic approach. [REVIEW]José L. Cereceda - 1995 - Foundations of Physics 25 (6):925-949.
    In this paper we present a systematic formulation of some recent results concerning the algebraic demonstration of the two major no-hidden-variables theorems for N spin-1/2 particles. We derive explicitly the GHZ states involved and their associated eigenvalues. These eigenvalues turn out to be undefined for N=∞, this fact providing a new proof showing that the nonlocality argument breaks down in the limit of a truly infinite number of particles.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  10
    Generalised KochenSpecker Theorem in Three Dimensions.Mirko Navara & Václav Voráček - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (3):1-7.
    We show that there is no non-constant assignment of zeros and ones to points of a unit sphere in R3\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\mathbb{R}^3$$\end{document} such that for every three pairwisely orthogonal vectors, an odd number of them is assigned 1. This is a new strengthening of the BellKochenSpecker theorem, which proves the non-existence of hidden variables in quantum theories.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. The Kochen - Specker theorem in quantum mechanics: a philosophical comment (part 1).Vasil Penchev - 2013 - Philosophical Alternatives 22 (1):67-77.
    Non-commuting quantities and hidden parameters – Wave-corpuscular dualism and hidden parameters – Local or nonlocal hidden parameters – Phase space in quantum mechanics – Weyl, Wigner, and Moyal – Von Neumann’s theorem about the absence of hidden parameters in quantum mechanics and Hermann – Bell’s objection – Quantum-mechanical and mathematical incommeasurability – KochenSpecker’s idea about their equivalence – The notion of partial algebra – Embeddability of a qubit into a bit – Quantum computer is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Kochen-Specker epsilon-Obstruction for Position and Momentum.Wayne C. Myrvold - 2002 - Physics Letters A 299:8-14.
    The BellKochenSpecker theorem shows that, in any Hilbert space of dimension of at least 3, it is impossible to assign noncontextual definite values to all observables in such a way that the quantum-mechanical predictions are reproduced. This leaves open the issue of what subsets of observables may be assigned definite values. Clifton has shown that, for a system of at least two continuous degrees of freedom, it is not possible to assign simultaneous noncontextual values to two (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  19
    Bell Non-locality and KochenSpecker Contextuality: How are They Connected?Adán Cabello - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (3):1-13.
    Bell non-locality and KochenSpecker contextuality are logically independent concepts, fuel different protocols with quantum vs classical advantage, and have distinct classical simulation costs. A natural question is what are the relations between these concepts, advantages, and costs. To address this question, it is useful to have a map that captures all the connections between Bell non-locality and KS contextuality in quantum theory. The aim of this work is to introduce such a map. After defining the theory-independent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. KochenSpecker -obstruction for position and momentum using a single degree of freedom.P. R. Holland - unknown
    The BellKochenSpecker theorem shows that, in any Hilbert space of dimension of at least 3, it is impossible to assign noncontextual definite values to all observables in such a way that the quantum-mechanical predictions are reproduced. This leaves open the issue of what subsets of observables may be assigned definite values. Clifton has shown that, for a system of at least two continuous degrees of freedom, it is not possible to assign simultaneous noncontextual values to two (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  33
    Must hidden variables theories be contextual? Kochen & Specker meet von Neumann and Gleason.Pablo Acuña - 2021 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (2):1-30.
    It is a widespread belief that the Kochen-Specker theorem imposes a contextuality constraint on the ontology of beables in quantum hidden variables theories. On the other hand, after Bell’s influential critique, the importance of von Neumann’s wrongly called ‘impossibility proof’ has been severely questioned. However, Max Jammer, Jeffrey Bub and Dennis Dieks have proposed insightful reassessments of von Neumann’s theorem: what it really shows is that hidden variables theories cannot represent their beables by means of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11.  14
    Kochen-Specker Theorem, Physical Invariance and Quantum Individuality.Christian de Ronde & Cesar Massri - unknown
    In this paper we attempt to discuss what has Kochen-Specker theorem to say about physical invariance and quantum individuality. In particular, we will discuss the impossibility of making reference to objective physical properties within the orthodox formalism of quantum mechanics. Through an analysis of the meaning of physical invariance and quantum contextuality we will derive a Corollary to KS theorem that proves that a vector in Hilbert space cannot be interpreted coherently as an object possessing physical (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12. The Kochen - Specker theorem in quantum mechanics: a philosophical comment (part 2).Vasil Penchev - 2013 - Philosophical Alternatives 22 (3):74-83.
    The text is a continuation of the article of the same name published in the previous issue of Philosophical Alternatives. The philosophical interpretations of the Kochen- Specker theorem (1967) are considered. Einstein's principle regarding the,consubstantiality of inertia and gravity" (1918) allows of a parallel between descriptions of a physical micro-entity in relation to the macro-apparatus on the one hand, and of physical macro-entities in relation to the astronomical mega-entities on the other. The Bohmian interpretation ( 1952) of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  96
    Interpreting the Modal KochenSpecker theorem: Possibility and many worlds in quantum mechanics.Christian de Ronde, Hector Freytes & Graciela Domenech - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 45:11-18.
    In this paper we attempt to physically interpret the Modal KochenSpecker theorem. In order to do so, we analyze the features of the possible properties of quantum systems arising from the elements in an orthomodular lattice and distinguish the use of “possibility” in the classical and quantum formalisms. Taking into account the modal and many worlds non-collapse interpretation of the projection postulate, we discuss how the MKS theorem rules the constraints to actualization, and thus, the relation (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14. Generalized Kochen-Specker theorem.Asher Peres - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (6):807-812.
    A generalized Kochen-Specker theorem is proved. It is shown that there exist sets of n projection operators, representing n yes-no questions about a quantum system, such that none of the 2″ possible answers is compatible with sum rules imposed by quantum mechanics. Namely, if a subset of commuting projection operators sums up to a matrix having only even or only odd eigenvalues, the number of “yes” answers ought to he even or odd, respectively. This requirement may lead (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  15
    A Kochen-Specker theorem for unsharp spin 1 observables.Thomas Breuer - 2002 - In T. Placek & J. Butterfield (eds.), Non-Locality and Modality. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 195--203.
  16.  38
    Parity Proofs of the Kochen-Specker Theorem Based on the 24 Rays of Peres.Mordecai Waegell & P. K. Aravind - 2011 - Foundations of Physics 41 (12):1786-1799.
    A diagrammatic representation is given of the 24 rays of Peres that makes it easy to pick out all the 512 parity proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem contained in them. The origin of this representation in the four-dimensional geometry of the rays is pointed out.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  33
    Parity Proofs of the KochenSpecker Theorem Based on the 120-Cell.Mordecai Waegell & P. K. Aravind - 2014 - Foundations of Physics 44 (10):1085-1095.
    It is shown how the 300 rays associated with the antipodal pairs of vertices of a 120-cell (a four-dimensional regular polytope) can be used to give numerous “parity proofs” of the KochenSpecker theorem ruling out the existence of noncontextual hidden variables theories. The symmetries of the 120-cell are exploited to give a simple construction of its KochenSpecker diagram, which is exhibited in the form of a “basis table” showing all the orthogonalities between its rays. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Isomorphism between the Peres and Penrose Proofs of the BKS Theorem in Three Dimensions.Elizabeth Gould & P. K. Aravind - 2010 - Foundations of Physics 40 (8):1096-1101.
    It is shown that the 33 complex rays in three dimensions used by Penrose to prove the Bell-Kochen-Specker theorem have the same orthogonality relations as the 33 real rays of Peres, and therefore provide an isomorphic proof of the theorem. It is further shown that the Peres and Penrose rays are just two members of a continuous three-parameter family of unitarily inequivalent rays that prove the theorem.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. A topos perspective on the kochen-Specker theorem: I. Quantum states as generalised valuations.Chris Isham & Jeremy Butterfield - unknown
    Any attempt to construct a realist interpretation of quantum theory founders on the Kochen-Specker theorem, which asserts the impossibility of assigning values to quantum quantities in a way that preserves functional relations between them. We construct a new type of valuation which is defined on all operators, and which respects an appropriate version of the functional composition principle. The truth-values assigned to propositions are (i) contextual; and (ii) multi-valued, where the space of contexts and the multi-valued logic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  20.  89
    A topos perspective on the kochen-Specker theorem: II. Conceptual aspects, and classical analogues.Jeremy Butterfield & Chris Isham - unknown
    In a previous paper, we have proposed assigning as the value of a physical quantity in quantum theory, a certain kind of set (a sieve) of quantities that are functions of the given quantity. The motivation was in part physical---such a valuation illuminates the Kochen-Specker theorem; and in part mathematical---the valuation arises naturally in the topos theory of presheaves. This paper discusses the conceptual aspects of this proposal. We also undertake two other tasks. First, we explain how (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  21.  44
    Conway–Kochen and the Finite Precision Loophole.Ronnie Hermens - 2014 - Foundations of Physics 44 (10):1038-1048.
    Recently Cator and Landsman made a comparison between Bell’s Theorem and Conway and Kochen’s Strong Free Will Theorem. Their overall conclusion was that the latter is stronger in that it uses fewer assumptions, but also that it has two shortcomings. Firstly, no experimental test of the Conway–Kochen Theorem has been performed thus far, and, secondly, because the Conway–Kochen Theorem is strongly connected to the KochenSpecker Theorem it may be susceptible (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Hidden Variables and the Two Theorems of John Bell.N. David Mermin - 1993 - Reviews of Modern Physics 65:803--815.
    Although skeptical of the prohibitive power of no-hidden-variables theorems, John Bell was himself responsible for the two most important ones. I describe some recent versions of the lesser known of the two (familiar to experts as the "Kochen-Specker theorem") which have transparently simple proofs. One of the new versions can be converted without additional analysis into a powerful form of the very much better known "Bell's Theorem," thereby clarifying the conceptual link between these two (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  23. A topos perspective on the kochen-Specker theorem: III. Von Neumann algebras as the base category.John Hamilton, Chris Isham & Jeremy Butterfield - unknown
    We extend the topos-theoretic treatment given in previous papers of assigning values to quantities in quantum theory, and of related issues such as the Kochen-Specker theorem. This extension has two main parts: the use of von Neumann algebras as a base category (Section 2); and the relation of our generalized valuations to (i) the assignment to quantities of intervals of real numbers, and (ii) the idea of a subobject of the coarse-graining presheaf (Section 3).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  93
    Non-contextuality, finite precision measurement and the KochenSpecker theorem.Jonathan Barrett & Adrian Kent - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2):151-176.
  25.  20
    Non-contextuality, finite precision measurement and the KochenSpecker theorem.Jonathan Barrett & Adrian Kent - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2):151-176.
  26. Observables have No Value: A no-go Theorem for Position and Momentum Observables. [REVIEW]Alberto C. de la Torre - 2007 - Foundations of Physics 37 (8):1243-1252.
    The BellKochenSpecker contradiction is presented using continuous observables in infinite dimensional Hilbert space. It is shown that the assumption of the existence of putative values for position and momentum observables for one single particle is incompatible with quantum mechanics.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Fermat’s last theorem proved in Hilbert arithmetic. II. Its proof in Hilbert arithmetic by the Kochen-Specker theorem with or without induction.Vasil Penchev - 2022 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 14 (10):1-52.
    The paper is a continuation of another paper published as Part I. Now, the case of “n=3” is inferred as a corollary from the Kochen and Specker theorem (1967): the eventual solutions of Fermat’s equation for “n=3” would correspond to an admissible disjunctive division of qubit into two absolutely independent parts therefore versus the contextuality of any qubit, implied by the KochenSpecker theorem. Incommensurability (implied by the absence of hidden variables) is considered (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  50
    A topos perspective on the kochen-Specker theorem: IV. Interval valuations.Jeremy Butterfield & Chris Isham - unknown
    We extend the topos-theoretic treatment given in previous papers of assigning values to quantities in quantum theory. In those papers, the main idea was to assign a sieve as a partial and contextual truth-value to a proposition that the value of a quantity lies in a certain set D of real numbers. Here we relate such sieve-valued valuations to valuations that assign to quantities subsets, rather than single elements, of their spectrum (we call these interval valuations). There are two main (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29. Schütte's tautology and the Kochen-Specker theorem.Jeffrey Bub - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (6):787-806.
    I present a new 33-ray proof of the Kochen and Specker “no-go” hidden variable theorem in ℋ3, based on a classical tautology that corresponds to a contingent quantum proposition in ℋ3 proposed by Kurt Schütte in an unpublished letter to Specker in 1965. 1 discuss the relation of this proof to a 31-ray proof by Conway and Kochen, and to a 33-ray proof by Peres.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  77
    Aristotle's sea battle and the kochen-Specker theorem.Kent Peacock - manuscript
    I explore the application of the “no-go” theorems of quantum mechanics to the problem of the openness of the future. The notion of fatalism can be made precise if we think of it as a claim that the future has a Boolean property structure. However, if this is correct, then it may be the case that by the “no-go” theorems of quantum mechanics the future must be at least partially open in the precise sense that there cannot be a fact (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Independently Motivating the Kochen—Dieks Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.Rob Clifton - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (1):33-57.
    The distinguishing feature of ‘modal’ interpretations of quantum mechanics is their abandonment of the orthodox eigenstate–eigenvalue rule, which says that an observable possesses a definite value if and only if the system is in an eigenstate of that observable. Kochen's and Dieks' new biorthogonal decomposition rule for picking out which observables have definite values is designed specifically to overcome the chief problem generated by orthodoxy's rule, the measurement problem, while avoiding the no-hidden-variable theorems. Otherwise, their new rule seems completely (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32. The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics.Simon Kochen & E. P. Specker - 1967 - Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics 17:59--87.
  33.  90
    Logical Bell Inequalities.Samson Abramsky & Lucien Hardy - 2012 - Physical Review A 85:062114-1 - 062114-11.
    Bell inequalities play a central role in the study of quantum nonlocality and entanglement, with many applications in quantum information. Despite the huge literature on Bell inequalities, it is not easy to find a clear conceptual answer to what a Bell inequality is, or a clear guiding principle as to how they may be derived. In this paper, we introduce a notion of logical Bell inequality which can be used to systematically derive testable inequalities for a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Semantic realism versus EPR-Like paradoxes: The Furry, Bohm-Aharonov, and Bell paradoxes.Claudio Garola & Luigi Solombrino - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (10):1329-1356.
    We prove that the general scheme for physical theories that we have called semantic realism(SR) in some previous papers copes successfully with a number of EPR-like paradoxes when applied to quantum physics (QP). In particular, we consider the old arguments by Furry and Bohm- Aharonov and show that they are not valid within a SR framework. Moreover, we consider the Bell-Kochen-Specker und the Bell theorems that should prove that QP is inherently contextual and nonlocal, respectively, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35.  37
    Logical Structures Arising in Quantum Theory.Simon Kochen, E. P. Specker, C. A. Hooker & P. D. Finch - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):558-566.
  36.  12
    Spin and Contextuality in Extended de Broglie-Bohm-Bell Quantum Mechanics.Jeroen C. Vink - 2022 - Foundations of Physics 52 (5):1-27.
    This paper introduces an extension of the de Broglie-Bohm-Bell formulation of quantum mechanics, which includes intrinsic particle degrees of freedom, such as spin, as elements of reality. To evade constraints from the Kochen-Specker theorem the discrete spin values refer to a specific basis – i.e., a single spin vector orientation for each particle; these spin orientations are, however, not predetermined, but dynamic and guided by the wave function of the system, which is conditional on the realized (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  55
    No-Go Theorems Face Background-Based Theories for Quantum Mechanics.Louis Vervoort - 2016 - Foundations of Physics 46 (4):458-472.
    Recent experiments have shown that certain fluid-mechanical systems, namely oil droplets bouncing on oil films, can mimic a wide range of quantum phenomena, including double-slit interference, quantization of angular momentum and Zeeman splitting. Here I investigate what can be learned from these systems concerning no-go theorems as those of Bell and Kochen-Specker. In particular, a model for the Bell experiment is proposed that includes variables describing a ‘background’ field or medium. This field mimics the surface wave (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  89
    Bohm, spin, and the bell inequalities.Katherine Bedard - 1998 - Synthese 114 (3):405-444.
    In this paper I discuss how Bohm's interpretation models spin measurements and how the two ways in which spin is a contextual property pertains to the Kochen-Specker theorem. I then present locality principles from which a Bell Inequality can be derived, and I identify which of the locality principles Bohm's interpretation violates at which times. I also present reasons why the spin vector should not be attributed to the Bohmian particles.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  38
    No-Go Theorems and the Foundations of Quantum Physics.Andrea Oldofredi - 2018 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 49 (3):355-370.
    In the history of quantum physics several no-go theorems have been proved, and many of them have played a central role in the development of the theory, such as Bell’s or the KochenSpecker theorem. A recent paper by F. Laudisa has raised reasonable doubts concerning the strategy followed in proving some of these results, since they rely on the standard framework of quantum mechanics, a theory that presents several ontological problems. The aim of this paper is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Nonlocality and the Kochen-Specker paradox.Peter Heywood & Michael L. G. Redhead - 1983 - Foundations of Physics 13 (5):481-499.
    A new proof of the impossibility of reconciling realism and locality in quantum mechanics is given. Unlike proofs based on Bell's inequality, the present work makes minimal and transparent use of probability theory and proceeds by demonstrating a Kochen-Specker type of paradox based on the value assignments to the spin components of two spatially separated spin-1 systems in the singlet state of their total spin. An essential part of the argument is to distinguish carefully two commonly confused (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  41.  13
    Ontological indistinguishability as a central tenet of quantum theory.José Acacio de Barros & Federico Holik - 2023 - Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A 381:20220100.
    Quantum indistinguishability directly relates to the philosophical debate on the notions of identity and individuality. They are crucial for our understanding of multipartite quantum systems. Furthermore, the correct interpretation of this feature of quantum theory has implications that transcend fundamental science and philosophy, given that quantum indistinguishability is a resource in quantum information theory. Most of the conceptual analysis of quantum indistinguishability is restricted to studying the permutational invariance of quantum states, the concomitant quantum statistics and their entanglement. Here, we (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Entanglement Between Degrees of Freedom in a Single-Particle System Revealed in Neutron Interferometry.Yuji Hasegawa - 2012 - Foundations of Physics 42 (1):29-45.
    Initially Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) and later Bell shed light on the non-local properties exhibited by subsystems in quantum mechanics. Separately, Kochen and Specker analyzed sets of measurements of compatible observables and found that a consistent coexistence of these results is impossible, i.e., quantum indefiniteness of measurement results. As a consequence, quantum contextuality, a more general concept compared to non-locality, leads to striking phenomena predicted by quantum theory. Here, we report neutron interferometric experiments which investigate entangled (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43.  23
    Quantum Physics with Neutrons: From Spinor Symmetry to Kochen-Specker Phenomena. [REVIEW]Helmut Rauch - 2012 - Foundations of Physics 42 (1):153-172.
    In 1974 perfect crystal interferometry has been developed and immediately afterwards the 4π-symmetry of spinor wave-functions has been verified. The new method opened a new access to the observation of intrinsic quantum phenomena. Spin-superposition, quantum state reconstruction and quantum beat effects are examples of such investigations. In this connection efforts have been made to separate and measure various dynamical and geometrical phases. Non-cyclic and non-adiabatic topological phases have been identified and their stability against various fluctuations and dissipative forces has been (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  19
    Objectivity versus Nonobjectivity in Quantum Mechanics.Claudio Garola - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (9):1539-1565.
    Nonobjectivity of physical properties enters physics with the standard interpretation of quantum mechanics (QM), and a number of paradoxes of this theory follow from it. It seems, however, based on sound physical arguments (double slit experiment, Heisenberg's principle, BellKochenSpecker theorem, etc.), so that most physicists think that avoiding it is impossible. We discuss these arguments here and show that they can be criticized from a physical viewpoint. Our criticism proves that nonobjectivity must be considered an epistemological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  45.  45
    Foundations of Quantum Mechanics.Emily Adlam - 2021 - Cambridge University Press.
    Quantum mechanics is an extraordinarily successful scientific theory. But more than 100 years after it was first introduced, the interpretation of the theory remains controversial. This Element introduces some of the most puzzling questions at the foundations of quantum mechanics and provides an up-to-date and forward-looking survey of the most prominent ways in which physicists and philosophers of physics have attempted to resolve them. Topics covered include nonlocality, contextuality, the reality of the wavefunction and the measurement problem. The discussion is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  22
    Quantum contextuality as a topological property, and the ontology of potentiality.Marek Woszczek - 2020 - Philosophical Problems in Science 69:145-189.
    Quantum contextuality and its ontological meaning are very controversial issues, and they relate to other problems concerning the foundations of quantum theory. I address this controversy and stress the fact that contextuality is a universal topological property of quantum processes, which conflicts with the basic metaphysical assumption of the definiteness of being. I discuss the consequences of this fact and argue that generic quantum potentiality as a real physical indefiniteness has nothing in common with the classical notions of possibility and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  27
    Generalizations of Kochen and Specker's theorem and the effectiveness of Gleason's theorem.Ehud Hrushovski & Itamar Pitowsky - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2):177-194.
    Kochen and Specker's theorem can be seen as a consequence of Gleason's theorem and logical compactness. Similar compactness arguments lead to stronger results about finite sets of rays in Hilbert space, which we also prove by a direct construction. Finally, we demonstrate that Gleason's theorem itself has a constructive proof, based on a generic, finite, effectively generated set of rays, on which every quantum state can be approximated.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  42
    Evidence for the Epistemic View of Quantum States: A Toy Theory.Robert W. Spekkens - 2007 - Physical Review A 75:032110.
    We present a toy theory that is based on a simple principle: the number of questions about the physical state of a system that are answered must always be equal to the number that are unanswered in a state of maximal knowledge. Many quantum phenomena are found to have analogues within this toy theory. These include the noncommutativity of measurements, interference, the multiplicity of convex decompositions of a mixed state, the impossibility of discriminating nonorthogonal states, the impossibility of a universal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  49. Generalizations of Kochen and Specker's theorem and the effectiveness of Gleason's theorem.Itamar Pitowsky - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2):177-194.
    Kochen and Specker’s theorem can be seen as a consequence of Gleason’s theorem and logical compactness. Similar compactness arguments lead to stronger results about finite sets of rays in Hilbert space, which we also prove by a direct construction. Finally, we demonstrate that Gleason’s theorem itself has a constructive proof, based on a generic, finite, effectively generated set of rays, on which every quantum state can be approximated. r 2003 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  67
    Nonlocality and Gleason's lemma. Part I. Deterministic theories.H. R. Brown & G. Svetlichny - 1990 - Foundations of Physics 20 (11):1379-1387.
    J. S. Bell's classic 1966 review paper on the foundations of quantum mechanics led directly to the Bell nonlocality theorem. It is not widely appreciated that the review paper contained the basic ingredients needed for a nonlocality result which holds in certain situations where the Bell inequality is not violated. We present in this paper a systematic formulation and evaluation of an argument due to Stairs in 1983, which establishes a nonlocality result based on the (...)-Kochen-Specker “paradox” in quantum mechanics. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000