Results for ' theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis'

999 found
Order:
  1.  8
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis and almost theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis.James S. Barnes, Jun le Goh & Richard A. Shore - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (1):133-149.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion-theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed iterations of the Turing jump but below ATR $_{0}$. There is a long history of proof-theoretic principles which are THAs. Until the papers reported on in this communication, there was only one mathematical example. Barnes, Goh, and Shore [1] analyze an array of ubiquity theorems in graph theory descended from Halin’s [9] work on rays in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  14
    Almost Theorems of Hyperarithmetic Analysis.Richard A. Shore - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-33.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis (THAs) occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed (recursive) iterations of the Turing Jump but below ATR $_{0}$ (and so $\Pi _{1}^{1}$ -CA $_{0}$ or the hyperjump). There is a long history of proof theoretic principles which are THAs. Until Barnes, Goh, and Shore [ta] revealed an array of theorems in graph theory living in this neighborhood, there was only one mathematical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  45
    Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (1):89-120.
    A statement of hyperarithmetic analysis is a sentence of second order arithmetic S such that for every Y⊆ω, the minimum ω-model containing Y of RCA0 + S is HYP, the ω-model consisting of the sets hyperarithmetic in Y. We provide an example of a mathematical theorem which is a statement of hyperarithmetic analysis. This statement, that we call INDEC, is due to Jullien [13]. To the author's knowledge, no other already published, purely mathematical statement (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4.  20
    Antonio Montalbán, Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 6 (2006), no. 1, pp. 89–120. - Itay Neeman, _The strength of Jullien’s indecomposability theorem_. Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 8 (2008), no. 1, pp. 93–119. - Itay Neeman, _Necessary use of_ _induction in a reversal. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76 (2011), no. 2, pp. 561–574. [REVIEW]Henry Towsner - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):366-368.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  15
    Halin’s infinite ray theorems: Complexity and reverse mathematics.James S. Barnes, Jun Le Goh & Richard A. Shore - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    Halin in 1965 proved that if a graph has [Formula: see text] many pairwise disjoint rays for each [Formula: see text] then it has infinitely many pairwise disjoint rays. We analyze the complexity of this and other similar results in terms of computable and proof theoretic complexity. The statement of Halin’s theorem and the construction proving it seem very much like standard versions of compactness arguments such as König’s Lemma. Those results, while not computable, are relatively simple. They only (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  13
    The strength of Jullien's indecomposability theorem.Itay Neeman - 2008 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 8 (1):93-119.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis. We identify the strength of the theorem relative to standard reverse mathematics markers. We show that it lies strictly between weak [Formula: see text] choice and [Formula: see text] comprehension.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  7.  20
    A recursion theoretic analysis of the clopen Ramsey theorem.Peter Clote - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (2):376-400.
    Solovay has shown that if F: [ω] ω → 2 is a clopen partition with recursive code, then there is an infinite homogeneous hyperarithmetic set for the partition (a basis result). Simpson has shown that for every 0 α , where α is a recursive ordinal, there is a clopen partition F: [ω] ω → 2 such that every infinite homogeneous set is Turing above 0 α (an anti-basis result). Here we refine these results, by associating the "order type" (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  18
    Necessary use of [image] induction in a reversal.Itay Neeman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):561 - 574.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem (INDEC) states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis, and then, in the base system RCA₀ plus ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}$ induction, it was shown by Neeman to have strength strictly between weak ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ choice and ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{1}^{1}$ comprehension. We prove in this paper that ${\mathrm{\Sigma (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9. Fisher’s Fundamental Theorem of Natural Selection--A Philosophical Analysis.Samir Okasha - 2008 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (3):319-351.
    This paper provides a philosophical analysis of the ongoing controversy surrounding R.A. Fisher's famous ‘fundamental theorem’ of natural selection. The difference between the ‘traditional’ and ‘modern’ interpretations of the theorem is explained. I argue that proponents of the modern interpretation have captured Fisher's intended meaning correctly and shown that the theorem is mathematically correct, pace the traditional consensus. However, whether the theorem has any real biological significance remains an unresolved issue. I argue that the answer (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  10. Review: I. D. Zaspavskij, Disproof of Some Theorems of Classical Analysis in Constructive Analysis[REVIEW]F. J. Cogan - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):409-409.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  10
    A short proof of a well‐known theorem of intuitionistic analysis.Horst Luckhardt - 1975 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 21 (1):185-186.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  14
    The Strength of an Axiom of Finite Choice for Branches in Trees.G. O. H. Jun Le - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (4):1367-1386.
    In their logical analysis of theorems about disjoint rays in graphs, Barnes, Shore, and the author (hereafter BGS) introduced a weak choice scheme in second-order arithmetic, called the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of finite choice (hereafter finite choice). This is a special case of the $\Sigma ^1_1$ axiom of choice ( $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ ) introduced by Kreisel. BGS showed that $\Sigma ^1_1\text {-}\mathsf {AC}_0$ suffices for proving many of the aforementioned theorems in graph theory. While it is not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  16
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis II the Stone‐Weierstrass Theorem and Ascoli's Theorem.H. de Swart - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):501-508.
  14.  17
    Equivalence between Fraïssé’s conjecture and Jullien’s theorem.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 139 (1):1-42.
    We say that a linear ordering is extendible if every partial ordering that does not embed can be extended to a linear ordering which does not embed either. Jullien’s theorem is a complete classification of the countable extendible linear orderings. Fraïssé’s conjecture, which is actually a theorem, is the statement that says that the class of countable linear ordering, quasiordered by the relation of embeddability, contains no infinite descending chain and no infinite antichain. In this paper we study (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15.  18
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis. Rolle's Theorem and Complete, Totally bounded, Metric Spaces.H. de Swart - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):289-298.
  16.  26
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis II the Stone-Weierstrass Theorem and Ascoli's Theorem.H. de Swart - 1976 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 22 (1):501-508.
  17.  34
    Elements of Intuitionistic Analysis. Rolle's Theorem and Complete, Totally bounded, Metric Spaces.H. de Swart - 1976 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 22 (1):289-298.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  50
    An Incompleteness Theorem Via Ordinal Analysis.James Walsh - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (1):80-96.
    We present an analogue of Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem for systems of second-order arithmetic. Whereas Gödel showed that sufficiently strong theories that are $\Pi ^0_1$ -sound and $\Sigma ^0_1$ -definable do not prove their own $\Pi ^0_1$ -soundness, we prove that sufficiently strong theories that are $\Pi ^1_1$ -sound and $\Sigma ^1_1$ -definable do not prove their own $\Pi ^1_1$ -soundness. Our proof does not involve the construction of a self-referential sentence but rather relies on ordinal analysis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  10
    Borel combinatorics fail in HYP.Henry Towsner, Rose Weisshaar & Linda Westrick - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 23 (2).
    We characterize the completely determined Borel subsets of HYP as exactly the [Formula: see text] subsets of HYP. As a result, HYP believes there is a Borel well-ordering of the reals, that the Borel Dual Ramsey Theorem fails, and that every Borel d-regular bipartite graph has a Borel perfect matching, among other examples. Therefore, the Borel Dual Ramsey Theorem and several theorems of descriptive combinatorics are not theories of hyperarithmetic analysis. In the case of the Borel (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  57
    On a theorem of Feferman.Michael Detlefsen - 1980 - Philosophical Studies 38 (2):129 - 140.
    In this paper I argue that Feferman's theorem does not signify the existence of skeptic-satisfying consistency proofs. However, my argument for this is much different than other arguments (most particularly Resnik's) for the same claim. The argument that I give arises form an analysis of the notion of 'expression', according to which the specific character of that notion is seen as varying from one context of application (of a result of arithmetic metamathematics) to another.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  37
    Grafen, the Price equations, fitness maximization, optimisation and the fundamental theorem of natural selection.Warren J. Ewens - 2014 - Biology and Philosophy 29 (2):197-205.
    This paper is a commentary on the focal article by Grafen and on earlier papers of his on which many of the results of this focal paper depend. Thus it is in effect a commentary on the “formal Darwinian project”, the focus of this sequence of papers. Several problems with this sequence are raised and discussed. The first of these concerns fitness maximization. It is often claimed in these papers that natural selection leads to a maximization of fitness and that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22. Hidden Variables and the Two Theorems of John Bell.N. David Mermin - 1993 - Reviews of Modern Physics 65:803--815.
    Although skeptical of the prohibitive power of no-hidden-variables theorems, John Bell was himself responsible for the two most important ones. I describe some recent versions of the lesser known of the two (familiar to experts as the "Kochen-Specker theorem") which have transparently simple proofs. One of the new versions can be converted without additional analysis into a powerful form of the very much better known "Bell's Theorem," thereby clarifying the conceptual link between these two results of Bell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  23.  4
    Herbrand analysis of 2 proofs of the Roth theorem-polynomial Bounds.H. Luckhardt - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):234-263.
    A previously unexplored method, combining logical and mathematical elements, is shown to yield substantial numerical improvements in the area of Diophantine approximations. Kreisel illustrated the method abstractly by noting that effective bounds on the number of elements are ensured if Herbrand terms from ineffective proofs ofΣ2-finiteness theorems satisfy certain simple growth conditions. Here several efficient growth conditions for the same purpose are presented that are actually satisfied in practice, in particular, by the proofs of Roth's theorem due to Roth (...))
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  12
    Error analysis of digital filters using HOL theorem proving.Behzad Akbarpour & Sofiène Tahar - 2007 - Journal of Applied Logic 5 (4):651-666.
  25.  69
    Branching space-time analysis of the GHZ theorem.Nuel Belnap & László E. Szabó - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (8):989-1002.
    Greenberger. Horne. Shimony, and Zeilinger gave a new version of the Bell theorem without using inequalities (probabilities). Mermin summarized it concisely; but Bohm and Hiley criticized Mermin's proof from contextualists' point of view. Using the branching space-time language, in this paper a proof will be given that is free of these difficulties. At the same time we will also clarify the limits of the validity of the theorem when it is taken as a proof that quantum mechanics is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  26.  95
    An Analysis of Stapp’s “A Bell-Type Theorem without Hidden Variables”.Abner Shimony - 2006 - Foundations of Physics 36 (1):61-72.
    H.P. Stapp has proposed a number of demonstrations of a Bell-type theorem which dispensed with an assumption of hidden variables, but relied only upon locality together with an assumption that experimenters can choose freely which of several incompatible observables to measure. In recent papers his strategy has centered upon counterfactual conditionals. Stapp’s paper in American Journal of Physics, 2004, replies to objections raised against earlier expositions of this strategy and proposes a simplified demonstration. The new demonstration is criticized, several (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  19
    Characterizations of ordinal analysis.James Walsh - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (4):103230.
    Ordinal analysis is a research program wherein recursive ordinals are assigned to axiomatic theories. According to conventional wisdom, ordinal analysis measures the strength of theories. Yet what is the attendant notion of strength? In this paper we present abstract characterizations of ordinal analysis that address this question. -/- First, we characterize ordinal analysis as a partition of $\Sigma^1_1$-definable and $\Pi^1_1$-sound theories, namely, the partition whereby two theories are equivalent if they have the same proof-theoretic ordinal. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. The extent of computation in malament–hogarth spacetimes.P. D. Welch - 2008 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (4):659-674.
    We analyse the extent of possible computations following Hogarth ([2004]) conducted in Malament–Hogarth (MH) spacetimes, and Etesi and Németi ([2002]) in the special subclass containing rotating Kerr black holes. Hogarth ([1994]) had shown that any arithmetic statement could be resolved in a suitable MH spacetime. Etesi and Németi ([2002]) had shown that some relations on natural numbers that are neither universal nor co-universal, can be decided in Kerr spacetimes, and had asked specifically as to the extent of computational limits there. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  29.  13
    An analysis of Fierz identities, factorization and inversion theorems.Suemi Rodríguez-Romo - 1993 - Foundations of Physics 23 (11):1535-1542.
    We show that the full set of Fierz identities which are used to compute electro-weak interactions reported by Y. Takahashi can be considered as particular cases of the Clifford product between multivector Cartan maps. Moreover, we think that our approach can be generalized to higher-dimensional models.We discuss the factorization and inversion theorems for the recovery of the spinor from its multivectorial Cartan map.A new classification given by P. Lounesto is applied to the recovered spinors for Cl1,3 space-time symmetry and SU(2)×U(1) (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  10
    The computational content of Nonstandard Analysis.Sam Sanders - unknown
    Kohlenbach's proof mining program deals with the extraction of effective information from typically ineffective proofs. Proof mining has its roots in Kreisel's pioneering work on the so-called unwinding of proofs. The proof mining of classical mathematics is rather restricted in scope due to the existence of sentences without computational content which are provable from the law of excluded middle and which involve only two quantifier alternations. By contrast, we show that the proof mining of classical Nonstandard Analysis has a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  4
    An analysis and revision of Hull's Theorem 30.A. C. Pereboom - 1957 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 53 (4):234.
  32. Review: G. S. Cejtin, On Cauchy's Theorem in Constructive Analysis[REVIEW]F. J. Cogan - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):408-409.
  33.  38
    The vicious circle theorem – a graph-theoretical analysis of dialectical structures.Gregor Betz - 2005 - Argumentation 19 (1):53-64.
    This article sets up a graph-theoretical framework for argumentation-analysis (dialectical analysis) which expands classical argument-analysis. Within this framework, a main theorem on the existence of inconsistencies in debates is stated and proved: the vicious circle theorem. Subsequently, two corollaries which generalize the main theorem are derived. Finally, a brief outlook is given on further expansions and possible applications of the developed framework.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34.  29
    Mathematical Models and Robustness Analysis in Epistemic Democracy: A Systematic Review of Diversity Trumps Ability Theorem Models.Ryota Sakai - 2020 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 50 (3):195-214.
    This article contributes to the revision of the procedure of robustness analysis of mathematical models in epistemic democracy using the systematic review method. It identifies the drawbacks of robustness analysis in epistemic democracy in terms of sample universality and inference from samples with the same results. To exemplify the effectiveness of systematic review, this article conducted a pilot review of diversity trumps ability theorem models, which are mathematical models of deliberation often cited by epistemic democrats. A review (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  24
    Barrow, Leibniz and the Geometrical Proof of the Fundamental Theorem of the Calculus.Michael Nauenberg - 2014 - Annals of Science 71 (3):335-354.
    SummaryIn 1693, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz published in the Acta Eruditorum a geometrical proof of the fundamental theorem of the calculus. It is shown that this proof closely resembles Isaac Barrow's proof in Proposition 11, Lecture 10, of his Lectiones Geometricae, published in 1670. This comparison provides evidence that Leibniz gained substantial help from Barrow's book in formulating and presenting his geometrical formulation of this theorem. The analysis herein also supports the work of J. M. Child, who in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  29
    A Reverse Analysis of the Sylvester-Gallai Theorem.Victor Pambuccian - 2009 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (3):245-260.
    Reverse analyses of three proofs of the Sylvester-Gallai theorem lead to three different and incompatible axiom systems. In particular, we show that proofs respecting the purity of the method, using only notions considered to be part of the statement of the theorem to be proved, are not always the simplest, as they may require axioms which proofs using extraneous predicates do not rely upon.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  11
    Analysis of Cantor-Bendixson Theorem by Means of the Analytic Hierarchy.G. Kreisel - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):334-334.
  38.  43
    Theory and implementation of coalitional analysis in cooperative decision making.Haiyan Xu, D. Marc Kilgour, Keith W. Hipel & Edward A. McBean - 2014 - Theory and Decision 76 (2):147-171.
    Stability definitions for describing human behavior under conflict when coalitions may form are generalized within the Graph Model for Conflict Resolution and algebraic formulations of these definitions are provided to allow computer implementation. The more general definitions of coalitional stabilities relax the assumption of transitive graphs capturing movements under the control of decision makers, either independently or cooperatively, and allow the convenient expansion to the case of coalitions of the four basic individual stabilities consisting of Nash stability, general metarationality, symmetric (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Self-reference and gödel's theorem: A Husserlian analysis[REVIEW]Albert Johnstone - 2003 - Husserl Studies 19 (2):131-151.
    A Husserlian phenomenological approach to logic treats concepts in terms of their experiential meaning rather than in terms of reference, sets of individuals, and sentences. The present article applies such an approach in turn to the reasoning operative in various paradoxes: the simple Liar, the complex Liar paradoxes, the Grelling-type paradoxes, and Gödel’s Theorem. It finds that in each case a meaningless statement, one generated by circular definition, is treated as if were meaningful, and consequently as either true or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  64
    Free-variable axiomatic foundations of infinitesimal analysis: A fragment with finitary consistency proof.Rolando Chuaqui & Patrick Suppes - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (1):122-159.
    In treatises or advanced textbooks on theoretical physics, it is apparent that the way mathematics is used is very different from what is to be found in books of mathematics. There is, for example, no close connection between books on analysis, on the one hand, and any classical textbook in quantum mechanics, for example, Schiff, [11], or quite recent books, for example Ryder, [10], on quantum field theory. The differences run a good deal deeper than the fact that the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  41.  62
    Quantum Information Versus Epistemic Logic: An Analysis of the Frauchiger–Renner Theorem.Florian J. Boge - 2019 - Foundations of Physics 49 (10):1143-1165.
    A recent no-go theorem (Frauchiger and Renner in Nat Commun 9(1):3711, 2018) establishes a contradiction from a specific application of quantum theory to a multi- agent setting. The proof of this theorem relies heavily on notions such as ‘knows’ or ‘is certain that’. This has stimulated an analysis of the theorem by Nurgalieva and del Rio (in: Selinger P, Chiribella G (eds) Proceedings of the 15th international conference on quantum physics and logic (QPL 2018). EPTCS 287, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  49
    An empirical analysis of modal theorem provers.Ullrich Hustadt & Renate A. Schmidt - 1999 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 9 (4):479-522.
    ABSTRACT This paper reports on an empirical performance analysis of four modal theorem provers on benchmark suites of randomly generated formulae. The theorem provers tested are the Davis-Putnam-based procedure KSAT, the tableaux-based system KRZIS, the sequent-based Logics Workbench, and a translation approach combined with the first-order theorem prover SPASS. Our benchmark suites are sets of multi-modal formulae in a certain normal form randomly generated according to the scheme of Giunchiglia and Sebastiani [GS 96a, GS 96b]. We (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  54
    Equivalents of the (weak) fan theorem.Iris Loeb - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 132 (1):51-66.
    This article presents a weak system of intuitionistic second-order arithmetic, WKV, a subsystem of the one in S.C. Kleene, R.E. Vesley [The Foundations of Intuitionistic Mathematics: Especially in Relation to Recursive Functions, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1965]. It is then shown that some statements of real analysis, like a version of the Heine–Borel Theorem, and some statements of logic, e.g. compactness of classical proposition calculus, are equivalent to the Fan Theorem in this system.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  44.  53
    Brouwer's fan theorem and unique existence in constructive analysis.Josef Berger & Hajime Ishihara - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (4):360-364.
    Many existence propositions in constructive analysis are implied by the lesser limited principle of omniscience LLPO; sometimes one can even show equivalence. It was discovered recently that some existence propositions are equivalent to Bouwer's fan theorem FAN if one additionally assumes that there exists at most one object with the desired property. We are providing a list of conditions being equivalent to FAN, such as a unique version of weak König's lemma. This illuminates the relation between FAN and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  45.  25
    The shaping of the riesz representation theorem: A chapter in the history of analysis.J. D. Gray - 1984 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 31 (2):127-187.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  62
    A Formally Verified Proof of the Prime Number Theorem.Jeremy Avigad, Kevin Donnelly, David Gray & Paul Raff - 2007 - ACM Transactions on Computational Logic 9 (1).
    The prime number theorem, established by Hadamard and de la Vallée Poussin independently in 1896, asserts that the density of primes in the positive integers is asymptotic to 1/ln x. Whereas their proofs made serious use of the methods of complex analysis, elementary proofs were provided by Selberg and Erdos in 1948. We describe a formally verified version of Selberg's proof, obtained using the Isabelle proof assistant.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47. Comments on Shimony’s “An Analysis of Stapp’s ‘A Bell-Type Theorem without Hidden Variables’ ”.Henry P. Stapp - 2006 - Foundations of Physics 36 (1):73-82.
    The hidden-variable theorems of Bell and followers depend upon an assumption, namely the hidden-variable assumption, that conflicts with the precepts of quantum philosophy. Hence from an orthodox quantum perspective those theorems entail no faster-than-light transfer of information. They merely reinforce the ban on hidden variables. The need for some sort of faster-than-light information transfer can be shown by using counterfactuals instead of hidden variables. Shimony’s criticism of that argument fails to take into account the distinction between no-faster-than-light connection in one (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  21
    Non-constructive Proofs of a Metamathematical Theorem Concerning the Consistency of Analysis and its Extension.Sh^|^Ocirc Maehara, Ji, Toshio Nishimura & Setsuya Seki - 1960 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 1 (5):269-288.
  49.  9
    Non-constructive Proofs of a Metamathematical Theorem Concerning the Consistency of Analysis and its Extension.Shôji Maehara, Toshio Nishimura & Setsuya Seki - 1960 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 1 (5):269-288.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  31
    The Failure in Computable Analysis of a Classical Existence Theorem for Differential Equations.Brian H. Mayoh & Oliver Aberth - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1):85.
1 — 50 / 999