Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Paradox and cross purposes in recent work on consciousness.N. Block - 2001 - Cognition 79 (1-2):197--219.
    Dehaene and Naccache, Dennett and Jack and Shallice “see convergence coming from many different quarters on a version of the neuronal global workspace model†(Dennett, p. 1). (Boldface references are to papers in this volume.) On the contrary, even within this volume, there are commitments to very different perspectives on consciousness. And these differing perspectives are based on tacit differences in philosophical starting places that should be made explicit.  Indeed, it is not clear that different uses of “consciousness†and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • The brain circuitry of attention.Stewart Shipp - 2004 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (5):223-230.
  • Perceptual phenomenology.Bence Nanay - 2012 - Philosophical Perspectives 26 (1):235-246.
    I am looking at an apple. The apple has a lot of properties and some, but not all, of these are part of my phenomenology at this moment: I am aware of these properties. And some, but not all, of these properties that I am aware of are part of my perceptual (or sensory) phenomenology. If I am attending to the apple’s color, this property will be part of my perceptual phenomenology. The property of being a granny smith apple from (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Collected Papers.Colin McGinn - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (2):278.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • Why visual attention and awareness are different.Victor A. F. Lamme - 2003 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7 (1):12-18.
  • How to define an object: Evidence from the effects of action on perception and attention.Glyn W. Humphreys & M. Jane Riddoch - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (5):534–547.
    We present work demonstrating that the nature of an object for our visual system depends on the actions we are programming and on the presence of action relations between stimuli. For example, patients who show visual extinction are more likely to become aware of two objects if the objects fall in appropriate visual locations for a common action. This effect of the action relations between objects is modulated both by the familiarity of the positioning of the objects for action, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Perceptual awareness and its loss in unilateral neglect and extinction.John Driver & Patrik Vuilleumier - 2001 - Cognition 79 (1):39-88.
  • Which Properties Are Represented in Perception.Susanna Siegel - 2005 - In Tamar S. Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual Experience. Oxford University Press. pp. 481-503.
    In discussions of perception and its relation to knowledge, it is common to distinguish what one comes to believe on the basis of perception from the distinctively perceptual basis of one's belief. The distinction can be drawn in terms of propositional contents: there are the contents that a perceiver comes to believe on the basis of her perception, on the one hand; and there are the contents properly attributed to perception itself, on the other. Consider the content.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in the brain.M. Corbetta & G. L. Shulman - 2002 - Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3 (3):201-215.
  • Unilateral Neglect of Representational Space.E. Bisiach & C. Luzzatti - 1978 - Cortex 14:129-133.
  • Spatial Organization and the Appearances Thereof in Early Vision.Austen Clark - 2012 - In Gary Hatfield & Sarah Allred (eds.), Visual Experience: Sensation, Cognition, and Constancy. Oxford University Press. pp. 135.
    The perception of the lightness of surfaces has been shown to be affected by information about the spatial configuration of those surfaces and their illuminants. For example, two surfaces of equal luminance can appear to be of very different lightness if one of the two appears to lie in a shadow. How are we to understand the character of the processes that integrate such spatial configuration information so as to yield the eventual appearance of lightness? This paper makes some simple (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unilateral neglect, representational schema, and consciousness.E. Bisiach, C. Luzzatti & D. Perani - 1979 - Brain 102:609-18.
  • Unconscious visual processing in neuropsychological syndromes: A survey of the literature and evaluation of models of consciousness.S. Koehler & Morris Moscovitch - 1997 - In M. D. Rugg (ed.), Cognitive Neuroscience. MIT Press. pp. 305--373.
  • Visual processing without awareness: Evidence from unilateral neglect.Anna Berti & G. Rizzolatti - 1992 - Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 4:345-51.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations