Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Hume's Phenomenology of the Imagination.Timothy M. Costelloe - 2007 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 5 (1):31-45.
    This paper examines the role of the imagination in Hume's epistemology. Three specific powers of the imagination are identified – the imagistic, conceptual and productive – as well as three corresponding kinds of fictions based on the degree of belief contained in each class of ideas the imagination creates. These are generic fictions, real and mere fictions, and necessary fictions, respectively. Through these manifestations, it is emphasized, Hume presents the imagination both as the positive force behind human creativity and a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume's "Dialectic".Dorothy P. Coleman - 1984 - Hume Studies 10 (2):139-155.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:139 HUME'S "DIALECTIC" Hume's treatment of contradiction in his discussion of external existence has generally been understood to resemble the Pyrrhonian model of dialectic; consequently, Hume has been viewed as a sceptic and an irrationalist. According to that model of dialectic, the sceptic, by showing that equally strong arguments can be constructed both for and against a proposition, raises doubts about the ability of reason to determine the truth (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hume's "Dialectic".Dorothy P. Coleman - 1984 - Hume Studies 10 (2):139-155.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:139 HUME'S "DIALECTIC" Hume's treatment of contradiction in his discussion of external existence has generally been understood to resemble the Pyrrhonian model of dialectic; consequently, Hume has been viewed as a sceptic and an irrationalist. According to that model of dialectic, the sceptic, by showing that equally strong arguments can be constructed both for and against a proposition, raises doubts about the ability of reason to determine the truth (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The distinction between coherence and constancy in Hume's Treatise I.iv.2.Tim Black - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (1):1-25.
    In the Treatise, Book I, Part iv, Section 2, Hume seeks to explain what causes us to believe that objects continue to exist even when they are not perceived. He argues that we won't be able to prov...
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Identity, Continued Existence, and the External World.Donald L. M. Baxter - 2006 - In Saul Traiger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Hume's Treatise. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 114–132.
    To the question whether Hume believed in mind-independent physical objects (or as he would put it, bodies), the answer is Yes and No. It is Yes when Hume writes “We may well ask, What causes induce us to believe in the existence of body? but ’tis in vain to ask, Whether there be body or not? That is a point, which we must take for granted in all our reasonings.” However the answer is No after inquiring into the causes of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Hume's Difficulty: Time and Identity in the Treatise.Donald L. M. Baxter - 2008 - New York: Routledge.
    In this volume--the first, focused study of Hume on time and identity--Baxter focuses on Hume’s treatment of the concept of numerical identity, which is central to Hume's famous discussions of the external world and personal identity. Hume raises a long unappreciated, and still unresolved, difficulty with the concept of identity: how to represent something as "a medium betwixt unity and number." Superficial resemblance to Frege’s famous puzzle has kept the difficulty in the shadows. Hume’s way of addressing it makes sense (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Natural Instinct, Perceptual Relativity, and Belief in the External World in Hume’s Enquiry.Annemarie Butler - 2008 - Hume Studies 34 (1):115-158.
    In part 1 of Enquiry 12, Hume presents a skeptical argument against belief in external existence. The argument involves a perceptual relativity argument that seems to conclude straightaway the double existence of objects and perceptions, where objects cause and resemble perceptions. In Treatise 1.4.2, Hume claimed that the belief in double existence arises from imaginative invention, not reasoning about perceptual relativity. I dissolve this tension by distinguishing the effects of natural instinct and showing that some ofthese effects supplement the Enquiry’s (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hume.Barry Stroud - 1977 - New York: Routledge.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
  • Hume, Kant, and the "Antinomy of Taste".Timothy M. Costelloe - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (2):165-185.
    This paper traces the systematic connections between the structure of Hume's argument in "Of the Standard of Taste" and the way Kant presents the Antinomy of Taste in his Critique of Judgment. It is argued, however, that although there are striking parallels between the way Hume and Kant formulate their respective antinomies, there are significant differences in the way the two philosophers solve them. For while Hume's approach reflects his scepticism about the place of philosophy in common life, Kant's solution (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hume's theory of the external world.Henry Habberley Price - 1940 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
  • The External World and Our Knowledge of It: Hume's Critical Realism, an Exposition and a Defence.Fred Wilson (ed.) - 2008 - University of Toronto Press.
  • Reid on single and double vision: Mechanics and morals.James van Cleve - 2008 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 6 (1):1-20.
    When we look at a tree, two images of it are formed, one on each of our retinas. Why, then, asks the child or the philosopher, do we not see two trees?1 Thomas Reid offers an answer to this question in the section of his Inquiry into the Human Mind entitled ‘Of seeing objects single with two eyes’. The principles he invokes in his answer serve at the same time to explain why we do occasionally see objects double. In Part (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • ‘The Table, Which We See’: An Irresolvable Ambiguity.James Somerville - 2006 - Philosophy 81 (1):33-63.
    The argument presented on behalf of ‘the slightest philosophy’ by Hume that ‘The table, which we see, seems to diminish, as we remove farther from it: But the real table, which exists independent of us, suffers no alteration’, in contrasting the seen with the real table requires the first relative clause to be defining; but the possibility of identifying tables independently of being seen requires the clause to be non-defining. John P. Wright's objection to Reid's rejoinder is rebutted. A similarly (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hume's argument against the continuing existence of unperceived perceptions.Jean Pierre Schachter - 1978 - Mind 87 (347):436-442.
  • An Inquiry Into the Human Mind, on the Principles of Common Sense.Thomas Reid - 1997 - Cambridge University Press. Edited by Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Richard McCarty, Fritz Allhoff & Anand Vaidya.
    Thomas Reid, the Scottish natural and moral philosopher, was one of the founding members of the Aberdeen Philosophical Society and a significant figure in the Scottish Enlightenment. Reid believed that common sense should form the foundation of all philosophical inquiry. He criticised the sceptical philosophy propagated by his fellow Scot David Hume and the Anglo-Irish bishop George Berkeley, who asserted that the external world did not exist outside the human mind. Reid was also critical of the theory of ideas propagated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   217 citations  
  • Hume's argument for the dependent existence of perceptions: An alternative reading.Aleksandar Pavković - 1982 - Mind 91 (364):585-592.
  • Hume's philosophy of common life.Donald W. Livingston - 1984 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Hume's Antinomies.Manfred Kuehn - 1983 - Hume Studies 9 (1):25-45.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:25. HUME'S ANTINOMIES I There are many contradictions in Hume. So much is readily admitted by all Hume scholars. But there is little agreement on what these contradictions show about Hume's thought in general. Many interpretations are based upon the view that Hume's contradictions are signs of his carelessness or lack of thoroughness. He is seen either as having lost all interest in giving a comprehensive or consistent account (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Three Questions about Treatise 1.4.2.Georges Dicker - 2007 - Hume Studies 33 (1):115-153.
    Why does Hume think that the "distinct existence" of sensible objects implies their "continu'd existence"? Does Hume have any reason for thinking that objects have an intermittent existence, other than that they lack a "distinct" existence? Why does Hume think that the inference from the "coherence" of our impressions to the continued existence of objects is "at bottom" considerably different from causal reasoning? The answers proposed are, respectively, that perceptually delimited objects would for Hume be causally dependent on being perceived; (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hume's Philosophy of Mind.John Bricke (ed.) - 1894 - Princeton University Press.
  • Thomas Reid: An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense: A Critical Edition.Derek R. Brookes (ed.) - 1997 - University Park, Pa.: Edinburgh University Press.
    Thomas Reid (1710–96) is increasingly being seen as a highly significant philosopher and a central figure in the Scottish Enlightenment. This new edition of Reid's classic philosophical text in the philosophy of mind at long last gives scholars a complete, critically edited text of the Inquiry. The critical text is based on the fourth life-time edition (1785). A selection of related documents showing the development of Reid's thought, textual notes, bibliographical details of previous editions and a full introduction by the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Notes on Hume and Skepticism of the Senses.Bryson Brown - 2003 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 3 (3):289-303.
    In A Treatise of Human Nature Hume wrote a long section titled “Of skepticism with regard to the senses.” The discussion examines two key features of our beliefs about the objects making up the external world: 1. They continue to exist, even when unperceived. 2. They are distinct from the mind and its perceptions. The upshot of the discussion is a graceful sort of intellectual despair:I cannot conceive how such trivial qualities of the fancy, conducted by such false suppositions, can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hume's Scepticism with Regard to the Senses.John W. Cook - 1968 - American Philosophical Quarterly 5 (1):1 - 17.
  • The Mind of David Hume.Oliver A. Johnson - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191):266-268.