Hegel’s Anticipation of the Early History of Analytic Philosophy

The Owl of Minerva 42 (1/2):18–40 (2010)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Putting it very crudely, it might be said that in the much discussed opening three chapters that make up the section “Consciousness” of his Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel sketches and “test-drives” various models for a consciousness able to experience and know the world.1 Kant had thought of objects of experience as necessarily having conceptual (as well as spatio-temporal) form, but non-conceptual (“intuitional”) content. But for Hegel, that objects show themselves to have a conceptual form emerges as one the first lessons of experience as tracked in Chapter 1. Moreover, in contrast to Kant’s focus on the unity and stability of such form, Hegel wants to display a series in which successive “shapes of consciousness” emerge from the resolution of contradictions affecting their predecessors.2 We might say that while Kant had famously asserted the identity of “the conditions of the possibility of experience in general” and the “conditions of the possibility of the objects of experience”,3 Hegel points to the ever-present tension between them, examining the fate of particular conceptions of the constitution of objects in the light of the “experience” based upon those conceptions, and with this transforms philosophy’s task, as Kant conceives it. Thus in the place of the reconfigured metaphysical project signalled by Kant which gives a definitive map of “what reason brings forth entirely out of itself” via the discovery of “reason’s common principle”,4 Hegel radically historicizes reason into a series of particular finite forms, each driven to selfovercoming because of the constitutive contradictions at its centre

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,709

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Between the Bounds of experience and divine intuition: Kant's epistemic limits and Hegel's ambitions.James Kreines - 2007 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):306 – 334.
Dewey's 'naturalized hegelianism' in operation: Experimental inquiry as self-consciousness.Scott Johnston - 2010 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (3):453-476.
Contemporary Epistemology: Kant, Hegel, McDowell.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (2):274–301.
A Theory of Tragic Experience According to Hegel.Julia Peters - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 19 (1):85-106.
Hegel's critique of Kant.Stephen Priest (ed.) - 1987 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Hegel's break with Kant: The leap from individual psychology to sociology.John Hund - 1998 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (2):226-243.
Hegel’s Concept of Desire.Scott Jenkins - 2008 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 47 (1):pp. 103-130.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-07-14

Downloads
100 (#173,111)

6 months
8 (#352,539)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Paul Redding
University of Sydney

References found in this work

Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 1905 - Mind 14 (56):479-493.
Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. V. O. Quine - 2011 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 202-220.
On Denoting.Bertrand Russell - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):873 - 887.
On What There Is.W. V. O. Quine - 2011 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 221-233.

View all 11 references / Add more references