Consequences

Critical Inquiry 11 (3):433-458 (1985)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Nothing I wrote in Is There a Text in This Class? has provoked more opposition or consternation than my claim that the argument of the book has no consequences for the practice of literary criticism.1 To many it seemed counterintuitive to maintain that an argument in theory could leave untouched the practice it considers: After all, isn’t the very point of theory to throw light on or reform or guide practice? In answer to this question, I want to say, first, that this claim is unsupportable. Here, I am in agreement with Steven Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels, who are almost alone in agreeing with me and who fault me not for making the “no consequences” argument but for occasionally falling away from it. Those dislike Is There a Text in This Class? tend to dislike “Against Theory” even more, and it is part of my purpose here to account for the hostility to both pieces. But since the issues at stake are fundamental, it is incumbent to begin at the beginning with a discussion of what theory is and is not. 1. See my Is There a Text in This Class?: The Authority of Interpretive Communities , p. 370. For a response to the “no consequences” claim, see Mary Louise Pratt, “Interpretive Strategies/Strategic Interpretations: on Anglo-American Reader Response Criticism,” Boundary 2 11 : 222. Stanley Fish is the William Kenan, Jr., Professor of English and the Humanities at the Johns Hopkins University. His most recent contributions to Critical Inquiry are “Profession Despise Thyself: Fear and Self-Loathing in Literary Studies” and “Fear of Fish:”A Reply to Walter Davis” . The present essay is the concluding chapter of Change

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,475

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Consequentialism and Side Constraints.Daniel Nolan - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (1):5-22.
Choices, consequences and desert.Teun J. Dekker - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (2):109 – 126.
“Marginal Consequences” and Utilitarianism.C. L. Sheng - 1988 - Philosophy Research Archives 14:143-163.
Choices, consequences, and rationality.Walter Bossert - 2001 - Synthese 129 (3):343 - 369.
Fish's consequences.Peter Kivy - 1989 - British Journal of Aesthetics 29 (1):57-64.
Belief and pretense: A reply to Gendler.Martijn Blaauw - 2006 - Metaphilosophy 37 (2):204-209.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-10-30

Downloads
25 (#627,007)

6 months
3 (#974,323)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

For theory.Martin Jay - 1996 - Theory and Society 25 (2):167-183.
Towards a Pragmatist Aesthetics.Erlend Lavik - forthcoming - British Journal of Aesthetics.
Pragmatic Constructivism: Revisiting William James's Critique of Herbert Spencer.Michael P. Lempert - 1997 - Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society 11 (1):33-50.

View all 6 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references