Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mind and Language

Oxford University Press (1975)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Indétermination de la traduction et sous-détermination des théories scientifiques.Martin Montminy - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (4):623-.
    La thèse de l'indétermination de la traduction de W. V. O. Quine est certainement une des thèses les plus controversées de la philosophie du langage. Le présent article explique en quoi consiste cette thèse et examine les liens qu'elle entretient avec la thèse de la sous-détermination des théories scientifiques. La première section montre comment la thèse de l'indétermination de la traduction découle de la conception behavioriste du langage de Quine. Les sections suivantes exposent deux façons de dériver la thèse de (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • iTabula si, rasa no!James D. McCawley - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):26-27.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language learning versus grammar growth.Robert J. Matthews - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):25-26.
  • The new organology.John C. Marshall - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):23-25.
  • Naturalism, scientism and the independence of epistemology.James Maffie - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (1):1 - 27.
    Naturalists seek continuity between epistemology and science. Critics argue this illegitimately expands science into epistemology and commits the fallacy of scientism. Must naturalists commit this fallacy? I defend a conception of naturalized epistemology which upholds the non-identity of epistemic ends, norms, and concepts with scientific evidential ends, norms, and concepts. I argue it enables naturalists to avoid three leading scientistic fallacies: dogmatism, one dimensionalism, and granting science an epistemic monopoly.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology I: The modern reduction of intentionality.William E. Lyons - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (2 & 3):247-69.
    In rounded terms and modem dress a theory of intentionality is a theory about how humans take in information via the senses and in the very process of taking it in understand it and, most often, make subsequent use of it in guiding human behaviour. The problem of intentionality in this century has been the problem of providing an adequate explanation of how a purely physical causal system, the brain, can both receive information and at the same time understand it, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What ever happened to deep structure?George Lakoff - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):22-23.
  • Ende oder Wende der analytischen Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie?Dirk Koppelberg - 1981 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 12 (2):364-400.
    My concern in what follows is to give a comparative report on some important lectures held at the Hegel-Kongreß 1981 in Stuttgart. In discussing the views of Quine, Hacking, Davidson, Putnam and Habermas I want to confront them with some details of Rorty's recent critique of our philosophical tradition. At last I try to give a tentative answer whether there is an end or a turning-point for current analytical philosophy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Quine on Objects: Realism or Anti-Realism?Antti Keskinen - 2012 - Theoria 78 (2):128-145.
    W. V. Quine describes himself as a “robust realist” about physical objects in the external world. This realism about objects is due to Quine's naturalism. On the other hand, Quine's naturalistic epistemology involves a conception of objects as posits that we introduce in our theories about the world. This conception of objects can be seen as anti-realist rather than realist. In this article, I discuss the questions whether there is a tension between Quine's realism and his epistemological conception of objects, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Spiders in the web of belief: The tangled relations between concepts and theories.Frank C. Keil - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):43-50.
  • Reclaiming Quine’s epistemology.Bredo C. Johnsen - 2014 - Synthese 191 (5):1-28.
    Central elements of W. V. Quine’s epistemology are widely and deeply misunderstood, including the following. He held from first to last that our evidence consists of the stimulations of our sense organs, and of our observations, and of our sensory experiences; meeting the interpretive challenge this poses is a sine qua non of understanding his epistemology. He counted both “This is blue” and “This looks blue” as observation sentences. He took introspective reports to have a high degree of certainty. He (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Generality Problem.Robert G. Hudson - 2004 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 42 (2):193-211.
  • Pritchard’s angst.Robert G. Hudson - 2006 - Acta Analytica 21 (3):85-92.
    In this paper, I raise some questions about Pritchard ’s internalist argument for scepticism. I argue that his internalism begs the question in support of scepticism. Correlatively I advance what I take to be a better internalist argument for scepticism, one that leaves open the possibility of empirically adjudicating sceptical hypotheses. I close by discussing what it means to be an internalist.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minimalism in cognition and language: rich man, poor man.Patrick T. W. Hudson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):22-22.
  • Dispositions, logical states, and mental occurrents.Ronald C. Hoy - 1980 - Synthese 44 (2):207-40.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Getting Real or Staying Positive: Legal Realism, Legal Positivism and the Prospects of Naturalism in Jurisprudence.Jakob V. H. Holtermann - 2015 - Ratio Juris 28 (1):535-555.
    The relationship between Legal Realism and Legal Positivism has been a recurrent source of debate. The question has been further complicated by the related difficulty of assessing the internal relationship between the two main original strands of Legal Realism: American and Scandinavian. This paper suggests considering American and Scandinavian Realism as instantiations of forward-looking and backward-looking rule skepticism respectively. This distinction brings into sharp relief not only the fundamentally different relationship between each of these two Realist schools and Legal Positivism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deflationism about Truth and Meaning.Jakob Hohwy - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):217-242.
  • The deflationary theory of meaning.Jeffrey Hershfield - 2001 - Philosophia 28 (1-4):191-208.
  • Two quibbles about analyticity and psychological reality.Gilbert Harman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):21-22.
  • Knowledge and learning.Robert Van Gulick - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):40-42.
  • Unnatural epistemology.John D. Greenwood - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (2):132-149.
    ‘Naturalized’ philosophers of mind regularly appeal to the empirical psychological literature in support of the ‘theory-theory’ account of the natural epistemology of mental state ascription (to self and others). It is argued that such appeals are not philosophically neutral, but in fact presuppose the theory-theory account of mental state ascription. It is suggested that a possible explanation of the popularity of the theory-theory account is that it is generally assumed that alternative accounts in terms of introspection (and simulation) presuppose a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elaboration of maturational and experiential contributions to the development of rules and representations.Gilbert Gottlieb - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):21-21.
  • The relation between epistemology and psychology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1985 - Synthese 64 (1):29-68.
    In the wake of Frege's attack on psychologism and the subsequent influence of Logical Positivism, psychological considerations in philosophy came to be viewed with suspicion. Philosophical questions, especially epistemological ones, were viewed as 'logical' questions, and logic was sharply separated from psychology. Various efforts have been made of late to reconnect epistemology with psychology. But there is little agreement about how such connections should be made, and doubts about the place of psychology within epistemology are still much in evidence. It (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Quine and Davidson: Two naturalized epistemologists.Roger F. Gibson - 1994 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (4):449 – 463.
    I juxtapose Quine's and Davidson's approaches to naturalized epistemology and assess Davidson's reasons for rejecting Quine's account of the nature of knowledge. Davidson argues that Quine's account of the nature of knowledge is Cartesian in spirit and consequence, i.e. it is essentially first person and invites global skepticism. I survey Quine's response to Davidson's criticisms and suggest that the view that Davidson criticizes may not be Quine's after all. I conclude by raising some questions about Quine's definition of ?observation sentence?
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Quine's dilemma.Roger F. Gibson - 1986 - Synthese 69 (1):27 - 39.
    Quine has long maintained in connection with his theses of under-determination of physical theory and indeterminacy of translation that there is a fact of the matter to physics but no fact of the matter to translation. In this paper, I investigate Quine's reasoning for this claim. I show that Quine's thinking about under-determination over the last twenty-five years has landed him in a contradiction: he says of two global physical theories that are empirically equivalent but logically incompatible that only one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Evolutionary anatomy and language.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):20-20.
  • Quine's notion of fact of the matter.Eve Gaudet - 2006 - Dialectica 60 (2):181–193.
    Quine’s notion of fact of the matter has received very little attention, although a good grasp of it is crucial to an understanding of some of Quine’s famous formulations of the indeterminacy of translation thesis. The notion is used and cited by many but has to my knowledge never been thoroughly analysed. In the present article, I attempt to analyse and clarify it. In the first section, my exposition focuses on the relations Quine has developed between his notion of fact (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Quine, Davidson, and the naturalization of metaethics.Robert Feleppa - 2001 - Dialectica 55 (2):145–166.
    Quine's ethical views typify what might seem to be natural sympathies between empiricism and ethical noncognitivism. LikeAyer, he sees a case for noncognitivism rooted in an epistemic discontinuity between ethics and science. Quine argues that the absence of genuine moral observation sentences, and thus the absence of empirical checkpoints for the resolution of theoretical disputes, renders ethics, as he terms it, “methodologically infirm” However, recent papers in this journal make clear that Quine appears to be voicing mutually incompatible commitments to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Realism and freethinking in metaphysics.Alan Donagan - 1976 - Theoria 42 (1-3):1-19.