Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Unmatched chains and the representation of plural pronouns.Mark C. Baker - 1992 - Natural Language Semantics 1 (1):33-73.
    Plural pronouns create the possibility of overlapping reference, which does not not fit naturally into the classical GB theory of anaphora, where each NP has a single integer as its referential index. Thus, one must either complicate the indexing system used in syntax or complicate the semantic interpretation of indices. This paper argues for the former approach based on the properties of a particular comitative-like construction found in Mohawk and certain other languages. This construction is analyzed as a type of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The distribution of quantificational suffixes in Japanese.Kazuko Yatsushiro - 2009 - Natural Language Semantics 17 (2):141-173.
    The existential and universal quantifiers in Japanese both consist of two morphemes: an indeterminate pronoun and a quantificational suffix. This paper examines the distributional characteristics of these suffixes (ka for the existential quantifier and mo for the universal quantifier). It is shown that ka can appear in a wider range of structural positions than mo can. This difference receives explanation on semantic grounds. I propose that mo is a generalized quantifier. More specifically, I assume that the phrase headed by mo (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Grammer and Social Interaction in Japanese and Anglo-American English: The Display of Context, Social Identity and Social Relation.Hiroko Tanaka - 1999 - Human Studies 22 (2):363-395.
    This paper employs conversation analysis to examine the inter-connection between grammar and displays of contextual understanding, social identity, and social relationships as well as other activities clustering around turn-endings in Japanese talk-in-interaction, while undertaking a restricted comparison with the realisation of similar activities in English. A notable feature of turn-endings in Japanese is the particular salience of grammatical construction on the interactional activities they accomplish. Complete turns which are also syntactically complete are shown to be associated with the explicit display (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Action-projection in Japanese conversation: topic particles wa, mo, and tte for triggering categorization activities.Hiroko Tanaka - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Pragmatic Nature of the So-Called Subject Marker Ga in Japanese: Evidence from Conversation.Ryoko Suzuki, Sandra A. Thompson & Tsuyoshi Ono - 2000 - Discourse Studies 2 (1):55-84.
    Since the inception of modern approaches to grammar, Japanese ga has been treated as a marker indicating the grammatical relation `subject.' If this is an accurate characterization of ga, then we would expect ga to occur to mark a grammatical category consisting of `A' and `S'. Our examination of the contexts in which ga is actually used in everyday Japanese conversations shows that this expectation is not borne out. Our findings suggest that it is not appropriate to describe ga in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Expressing an alternative view from second position: Reversed polarity questions in everyday Japanese conversation.Hideyuki Sugiura - 2017 - Discourse Studies 19 (3):291-313.
    This conversation-analytic study examines a type of action accomplished through a reversed polarity question responding to initial assessments in everyday Japanese conversation. This study demonstrates that RPQs deployed in this specific position express alternative views to initial assessments by appealing to participants’ common sense or knowledge and index participants’ epistemic symmetry over a particular assessable. These RPQs do not simply convey the speakers’ disagreement with initial assessments, however, but are designed to be situated as ‘new’ first assessments by triggering the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A bound on synchronically interpretable structure.Jon M. Slack - 2004 - Mind and Language 19 (3):305–333.
    Multiple explanatory frameworks may be required to provide an adequate account of human cognition. This paper embeds the classical account within a neural network framework, exploring the encoding of syntacticallystructured objects over the synchronicdiachronic characteristics of networks. Synchronic structure is defined in terms of temporal binding and the superposition of states. To accommodate asymmetric relations, synchronic structure is subject to the type uniqueness constraint. The nature of synchronic structure is shown to underlie Xbar theory that characterizes the phrasal structure of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A “Maximal Exclusion” Approach to Structural Underspecification in Dynamic Syntax.Tohru Seraku - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 30 (2):407-428.
    ‘Case’ and ‘grammatical relations’ are central to syntactic theory, but rigorous treatments of these concepts in surface-oriented grammars such as Dynamic Syntax are pending. In this respect, Japanese is worthy of mention; in this language, the nominative case particle ga, which typically marks a subject, may mark an object in certain syntactic contexts, and more than one instance of ga may be present within a single clause. These patterns cannot be captured if we simply assume that ga marks a subject. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Incremental Grammar Approach to Multiple Nominative Constructions in Japanese.Tohru Seraku - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (2):297-331.
    Japanese exhibits the Multiple Nominative Construction (MNC), where more than one nominative-marked NP appear within a single clause. Though the MNC has been extensively investigated in the syntax literature, its relation to rightward-displacement constructions has hardly been discussed. In the present article, we provide new sets of MNC data relating to the three types of right-displacement constructions: relatives, clefts, and postposing. The generalisation is that for the linearly ordered nominative-marked NPs in an MNC string, only the leftmost NP may be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On syntactic binding into adjuncts in the Russian noun phrase.Gilbert C. Rappaport - 1987 - Linguistics and Philosophy 10 (4):475 - 501.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Japanese atashi/ore/boku I: Theyre not just pronouns.Tsuyoshi Ono & Sandra A. Thompson - 2003 - Cognitive Linguistics 14 (4).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Exhaustivity as agreement: The case of Korean man 'only'.Youngjoo Lee - 2005 - Natural Language Semantics 13 (2):169-200.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Information structure in subordinate and subordinate-like clauses.Nobo Komagata - 2003 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (3):301-318.
    While information structure has traditionally been viewed as a singlepartition of information within an utterance, there are opposing viewsthat identify multiple such partitions in an utterance. The existenceof alternative proposals raises questions about the notion ofinformation structure and also its relation to discoursestructure. Exploring various linguistic aspects, this paper supports thetraditional view by arguing that there is no information structure partition within a subordinate clause.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Individual-denoting classifiers.Mana Kobuchi-Philip - 2007 - Natural Language Semantics 15 (2):95-130.
    This paper discusses Japanese numeral quantifiers that are used to count individuals, rather than quantities, of a substance, and which may occur either as floated or non-floated quantifiers. It is argued that such morphologically complex numeral quantifiers (NQs) are semantically complex as well: The numeral within the NQ is the quantifier itself, the classifier its domain of quantification. The proposed analysis offers a unified semantic account of floated and non-floated NQs that adheres closely to their surface morphology and syntax. It (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Syntax and semantics of questions.Lauri Karttunen - 1977 - Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1):3--44.
    W. Labov's & T. Labov's findings concerning their child grammar acquisition ("Learning the Syntax of Questions" in Recent Advances in the Psychology of Language, Campbell, R. & Smith, P. Eds, New York: Plenum Press, 1978) are interpreted in terms of different semantics of why & other wh-questions. Z. Dubiel.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   307 citations  
  • Definite descriptions and the alleged east–west variation in judgments about reference.Yu Izumi, Masashi Kasaki, Yan Zhou & Sobei Oda - 2018 - Philosophical Studies 175 (5):1183-1205.
    Machery et al. presented data suggesting the existence of cross-cultural variation in judgments about the reference of proper names. In this paper, we examine a previously overlooked confound in the subsequent studies that attempt to replicate the results of Machery et al. using East Asian languages. Machery et al. and Sytsma et al. claim that they have successfully replicated the original finding with probes written in Chinese and Japanese, respectively. These studies, however, crucially rely on uses of articleless, ‘bare noun (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Processing Cost of Scrambling and Topicalization in Japanese.Satoshi Imamura, Yohei Sato & Masatoshi Koizumi - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Licensing of PPI indefinites: Movement or pseudoscope?Vincent Homer & Rajesh Bhatt - 2019 - Natural Language Semantics 27 (4):279-321.
    Positive Polarity indefinites, such as some in English, are licensed in simplex negative sentences as long as they take wide scope over negation. When it surfaces under a clausemate negation, some can in principle take wide scope either by movement or by some semantic mechanism; e.g., it can take pseudoscope if it is interpreted as a choice function variable. Therefore, there is some uncertainty regarding the way in which PPI indefinites get licensed: can pseudoscope suffice? In this article we show, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Generalized phrase structure grammar and japanese reflexivization.Takao Gunji - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (1):115 - 156.
  • Is there a universal answering strategy for rejecting negative propositions? Typological evidence on the use of prosody and gesture.Santiago González-Fuente, Susagna Tubau, M. Teresa Espinal & Pilar Prieto - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
  • Illusive Scope of Universal Quantifiers.Danny Fox & Uli Sauerland - 1997 - In Jill Beckman (ed.), Proceedings of NELS 26. GLSA, UMass Amhert.
    It is widely believed that existential quantifiers can bring about the semantic effects of a scope which is wider than their actual syntactic scope (See Fodor & Sag (1982), Cresti (1995), Kratzer (1995), Reinhart (1995) and Winter (1995), among many others.) On the other hand, it is assumed that the syntactic scope of universal quantifiers can be determined unequivocally by the semantics. This paper shows that this second assumption is wrong; universal quantifiers can also bring about scope illusions, though in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Distinctive functions of quotative markers: Evidence from Meidai Kaiwa Corpus.Chad Nilep - 2013 - Gengo bunka ronshu 35 (1):87-103.
    The Japanese particle 'to' serves as a quotative marker, either indicating the content of speech or thought, or serving related functions. The particle 'tte' is frequently identified as an informal variant of 'to', serving identical or nearly identical functions. Scholars have suggested the two forms may have different distribution or function, but to date there has been little empirical work to distinguish the forms using broad-based corpus methods. This study of a corpus 129 informal conversations suggests that both particles are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Possessors and definiteness effects in two Austronesian languages.Sandra Chung - 2008 - In Lisa Matthewson (ed.), Quantification: A Cross-Linguistic Perspective. Emerald. pp. 179--224.
  • The interpretation of null and overt pronouns in Japanese: Grammatical and pragmatic factors.Mieko Ueno & Andrew Kehler - 2010 - In S. Ohlsson & R. Catrambone (eds.), Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Cognitive Science Society. pp. 2057--2062.
  • Mapping the terrain of language learning.Mark Baker - manuscript
    Language learning and language typology are often studied separately, and it is common for experts in one area to know rather little about the other. This is not merely an unfortunate historical coincidence; there are some powerful practical reasons why it is so. The detailed study of language learning typically involves the experimental investigation of groups of people who are at various stages in the learning process—i.e., children. Hence it prototypically takes place at university daycares in North America, where the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implicature calculation, only, and lumping: Another look at the puzzle of disjunction.Danny Fox - unknown
    Principles of communication allow the listener to infer (upon hearing (1) that unless the speaker believed that (1alt) were false, the speaker would have uttered (1alt).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations