Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Sartre and the long distance truck driver: The reflexivity of consciousness.Kathleen Wider - 1993 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 24 (3):232-249.
  • Hume's notions of consciousness and reflection in context.Udo Thiel - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2):75 – 115.
  • The concept of consciousness: The interpersonal meaning.Thomas Natsoulas - 1991 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 21 (September):63-89.
  • In Defense of the What-It-Is-Likeness of Experience.Greg Janzen - 2011 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (3):271-293.
    It is common parlance among philosophers who inquire into the nature of consciousness to speak of there being something it is like for the subject of a mental state to be in it. The popularity of the ‘what-it-is-like’ phrase stems, in part, from the assumption that it enables us to distinguish, in an intuitive and illuminating way, between conscious and unconscious mental states: conscious mental states, unlike unconscious mental states, are such that there is something it is like for their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • An Adverbialist–Objectualist Account of Pain.Greg Janzen - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (4):859-876.
    Adverbialism, broadly construed, is the thesis that pains (and other sensations) are modes of awareness, and objectualism, broadly construed, is the thesis that pains are objects of awareness. Why are we inclined to say that pains are modes of awareness and yet also inclined to say that they are objects of awareness? Each inclination leads to an account of pain that seems to be incompatible with the other. If adverbialism is correct, it would seem that objectualism is mistaken (and vice (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation