Results for 'unary functions'

997 found
Order:
  1.  19
    Rigit Unary Functions and the Axiom of Choice.Wolfgang Degen - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (2):197-204.
    We shall investigate certain statements concerning the rigidity of unary functions which have connections with forms of the axiom of choice.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  14
    Bounded iteration and unary functions.Stefano Mazzanti - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (1):89-94.
    The set of unary functions of complexity classes defined by using bounded primitive recursion is inductively characterized by means of bounded iteration. Elementary unary functions, linear space computable unary functions and polynomial space computable unary functions are then inductively characterized using only composition and bounded iteration.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  18
    Iterative Characterizations of Computable Unary Functions: A General Method.Stefano Mazzanti - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (1):29-38.
    Iterative characterizations of computable unary functions are useful patterns for the definition of programming languages based on iterative constructs. The features of such a characterization depend on the pairing producing it: this paper offers an infinite class of pairings involving very nice features.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  14
    General iteration and unary functions.G. M. Germano & S. Mazzanti - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 54 (2):137-178.
    Programming practice suggests a notion of general iteration corresponding to the while-do construct. This leads to new characterizations of general computable unary functions usable in computer science.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  22
    Tennenbaum's Theorem and Unary Functions.Sakae Yaegasi - 2008 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (2):177-183.
    It is well known that in any nonstandard model of $\mathsf{PA}$ (Peano arithmetic) neither addition nor multiplication is recursive. In this paper we focus on the recursiveness of unary functions and find several pairs of unary functions which cannot be both recursive in the same nonstandard model of $\mathsf{PA}$ (e.g., $\{2x,2x+1\}$, $\{x^2,2x^2\}$, and $\{2^x,3^x\}$). Furthermore, we prove that for any computable injection $f(x)$, there is a nonstandard model of $\mathsf{PA}$ in which $f(x)$ is recursive.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  21
    Iteration on notation and unary functions.Stefano Mazzanti - 2013 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 59 (6):415-434.
  7.  23
    Primitive iteration and unary functions.G. Germano & S. Mazzanti - 1988 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 40 (3):217-256.
  8.  11
    The Maximal Closed Classes of Unary Functions in p‐Valued Logic.Liu Renren & Lo Czukai - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):234-240.
    In many-valued logic the decision of functional completeness is a basic and important problem, and the thorough solution to this problem depends on determining all maximal closed sets in the set of many-valued logic functions. It includes three famous problems, i.e., to determine all maximal closed sets in the set of the total, of the partial and of the unary many-valued logic functions, respectively. The first two problems have been completely solved , and the solution to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  2
    Spectra and satisfiability for logics with successor and a unary function.Arthur Milchior - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (4-5):286-311.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  65
    Computational complexity of logical theories of one successor and another unary function.Pascal Michel - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (2):123-148.
    The first-order logical theory Th $({\mathbb{N}},x + 1,F(x))$ is proved to be complete for the class ATIME-ALT $(2^{O(n)},O(n))$ when $F(x) = 2^{x}$ , and the same result holds for $F(x) = c^{x}, x^{c} (c \in {\mathbb{N}}, c \ge 2)$ , and F(x) = tower of x powers of two. The difficult part is the upper bound, which is obtained by using a bounded Ehrenfeucht–Fraïssé game.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  36
    Unary primitive recursive functions.Daniel E. Severin - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (4):1122-1138.
    In this article, we study some new characterizations of primitive recursive functions based on restricted forms of primitive recursion, improving the pioneering work of R. M. Robinson and M. D. Gladstone. We reduce certain recursion schemes (mixed/pure iteration without parameters) and we characterize one-argument primitive recursive functions as the closure under substitution and iteration of certain optimal sets.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  35
    The Expressive Unary Truth Functions of n -valued Logic.Stephen Pollard - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (1):93-105.
    The expressive truth functions of two-valued logic have all been identified. This paper begins the task of identifying the expressive truth functions of n-valued logic by characterizing the unary ones. These functions have distinctive algebraic, semantic, and closure-theoretic properties.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  36
    On Characterizing Unary Probability Functions and Truth-Value Functions.Hugues Leblanc - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (1):19 - 24.
    Consider a language SL having as its primitive signs one or more atomic statements, the two connectives ‘∼’ and ‘&,’ and the two parentheses ‘’; and presume the extra connectives ‘V’ and ‘≡’ defined in the customary manner. With the statements of SL substituting for sets, and the three connectives ‘∼,’ ‘&,’and ‘V’ substituting for the complementation, intersection, and union signs, the constraints that Kolmogorov places in [1] on probability functions come to read:K1. 0 ≤ P,K2. P) = 1,K3. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  6
    Factors of Functions, AC and Recursive Analogues.Wolfgang Degen - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (1):73-86.
    We investigate certain statements about factors of unary functions which have connections with weak forms of the axiom of choice. We discuss more extensively the fine structure of Howard and Rubin's Form 314 from [4]. Some of our set-theoretic results have also interesting recursive versions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  48
    Absolute probability functions for intuitionistic propositional logic.Peter Roeper & Hugues Leblanc - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (3):223-234.
    Provided here is a characterisation of absolute probability functions for intuitionistic (propositional) logic L, i.e. a set of constraints on the unary functions P from the statements of L to the reals, which insures that (i) if a statement A of L is provable in L, then P(A) = 1 for every P, L's axiomatisation being thus sound in the probabilistic sense, and (ii) if P(A) = 1 for every P, then A is provable in L, L's (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  24
    Pure inductive logic with functions.Elizabeth Howarth & Jeffrey B. Paris - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (4):1382-1402.
    We consider the version of Pure Inductive Logic which obtains for the language with equality and a single unary function symbol giving a complete characterization of the probability functions on this language which satisfy Constant Exchangeability.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  22
    Spiritus Asper versus Lambda: On the Nature of Functional Abstraction.Ansten Klev - 2023 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (2):205-223.
    The spiritus asper as used by Frege in a letter to Russell from 1904 bears resemblance to Church’s lambda. It is natural to ask how they relate to each other. An alternative approach to functional abstraction developed by Per Martin-Löf some thirty years ago allows us to describe the relationship precisely. Frege’s spiritus asper provides a way of restructuring a unary function name in Frege’s sense such that the argument place indicator occurs all the way to the right. Martin-Löf’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Normal forms for characteristic functions on n-ary relations.Jan van Eijck - unknown
    Functions of type n are characteristic functions on n-ary relations. Keenan [5] established their importance for natural language semantics, by showing that natural language has many examples of irreducible type n functions, i.e., functions of type n that cannot be represented as compositions of unary functions. Keenan proposed some tests for reducibility, and Dekker [3] improved on these by proposing an invariance condition that characterizes the functions with a reducible counterpart with the same (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  21
    Uniform model-completeness for the real field expanded by power functions.Tom Foster - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (4):1441-1461.
    We prove that given any first order formula φ in the language L' = {+,., <, (f i ) i ∈ I , (c i ) i ∈ I }, where the f i are unary function symbols and the c i are constants, one can find an existential formula ψ such that φ and ψ are equivalent in any L'-structure $\langle {\Bbb R},+,.,<,(x^{c_{i}})_{i\in I},(c_{i})_{i\in I}\rangle $.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  17
    Expressive Three-valued Truth Functions.Stephen Pollard - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Logic 4:226-245.
    The expressive truth functions of two-valued logic have all been characterized, as have the expressive unary truth functions of finitely-many-valued logic. This paper introduces some techniques for identifying expressive functions in three-valued logics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  41
    Conditional computability of real functions with respect to a class of operators.Ivan Georgiev & Dimiter Skordev - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (5):550-565.
    For any class of operators which transform unary total functions in the set of natural numbers into functions of the same kind, we define what it means for a real function to be uniformly computable or conditionally computable with respect to this class. These two computability notions are natural generalizations of certain notions introduced in a previous paper co-authored by Andreas Weiermann and in another previous paper by the same authors, respectively. Under certain weak assumptions about the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  35
    A reduction class containing formulas with one monadic predicate and one binary function symbol.Charles E. Hughes - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):45-49.
    A new reduction class is presented for the satisfiability problem for well-formed formulas of the first-order predicate calculus. The members of this class are closed prenex formulas of the form ∀ x∀ yC. The matrix C is in conjunctive normal form and has no disjuncts with more than three literals, in fact all but one conjunct is unary. Furthermore C contains but one predicate symbol, that being unary, and one function symbol which symbol is binary.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  88
    On the ranges of algebraic functions on lattices.Sergiu Rudeanu & Dan A. Simovici - 2006 - Studia Logica 84 (3):451 - 468.
    We study ranges of algebraic functions in lattices and in algebras, such as Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras which are obtained by extending standard lattice signatures with unary operations.We characterize algebraic functions in such lattices having intervals as their ranges and we show that in Artinian or Noetherian lattices the requirement that every algebraic function has an interval as its range implies the distributivity of the lattice.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  26
    On the Ranges of Algebraic Functions on Lattices.Sergiu Rudeanu & Dan A. Simovici - 2007 - Studia Logica 84 (3):451-468.
    We study ranges of algebraic functions in lattices and in algebras, such as Łukasiewicz-Moisil algebras which are obtained by extending standard lattice signatures with unary operations.We characterize algebraic functions in such lattices having intervals as their ranges and we show that in Artinian or Noetherian lattices the requirement that every algebraic function has an interval as its range implies the distributivity of the lattice.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  94
    Many-Valued Logics.Nicholas J. J. Smith - 2012 - In Gillian Russell Delia Graff Fara (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Language. Routledge. pp. 636--51.
    A many-valued (aka multiple- or multi-valued) semantics, in the strict sense, is one which employs more than two truth values; in the loose sense it is one which countenances more than two truth statuses. So if, for example, we say that there are only two truth values—True and False—but allow that as well as possessing the value True and possessing the value False, propositions may also have a third truth status—possessing neither truth value—then we have a many-valued semantics in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  13
    Polygones.Tolende G. Mustafin & Bruno Poizat - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (1):93-110.
    We study the class of structures formed by all the polygons over a given monoid, which is equivalent to the study of the varieties in a language containing only unary functions. We collect and amplify previous results concerning their stability and superstability. Then we characterize the regular monoids for which all these polygons are ω-stable; the question about the existence of a non regular monoid with this property is left open.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. On the Slowly Well Orderedness of ɛo.Toshiyasu Arai - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (1):125-130.
    For α < ε0, Nα denotes the number of occurrences of ω in the Cantor normal form of α with the base ω. For a binary number-theoretic function f let B denote the length n of the longest descending chain of ordinals <ε0 such that for all i < n, Nαi ≤ f . Simpson [2] called ε0 as slowly well ordered when B is totally defined for f = K · . Let |n| denote the binary length of the (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  54
    Using Logic to Evolve More Logic: Composing Logical Operators via Self-Assembly.Travis LaCroix - 2022 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 73 (2):407-437.
    I consider how complex logical operations might self-assemble in a signalling-game context via composition of simpler underlying dispositions. On the one hand, agents may take advantage of pre-evolved dispositions; on the other hand, they may co-evolve dispositions as they simultaneously learn to combine them to display more complex behaviour. In either case, the evolution of complex logical operations can be more efficient than evolving such capacities from scratch. Showing how complex phenomena like these might evolve provides an additional path to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29.  3
    The Order Types of Termination Orderings on Monadic Terms, Strings and Monadic Terms, Strings and Multisets.Ursula Martin & Elizabeth Scott - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):624-635.
    We consider total well-founded orderings on monadic terms satisfying the replacement and full invariance properties. We show that any such ordering on monadic terms in one variable and two unary function symbols must have order type $\omega, \omega^2$ or $\omega^\omega$. We show that a familiar construction gives rise to continuum many such orderings of order type $\omega$. We construct a new family of such orderings of order type $\omega^2$, and show that there are continuum many of these. We show (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  12
    Open core and small groups in dense pairs of topological structures.Elías Baro & Amador Martin-Pizarro - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (1):102858.
    Dense pairs of geometric topological fields have tame open core, that is, every definable open subset in the pair is already definable in the reduct. We fix a minor gap in the published version of van den Dries's seminal work on dense pairs of o-minimal groups, and show that every definable unary function in a dense pair of geometric topological fields agrees with a definable function in the reduct, off a small definable subset, that is, a definable set internal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  21
    Polynomial-time versus recursive models.Douglas Cenzer & Jeffrey Remmel - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 54 (1):17-58.
    The central problem considered in this paper is whether a given recursive structure is recursively isomorphic to a polynomial-time structure. Positive results are obtained for all relational structures, for all Boolean algebras and for the natural numbers with addition, multiplication and the unary function 2x. Counterexamples are constructed for recursive structures with one unary function and for Abelian groups and also for relational structures when the universe of the structure is fixed. Results are also given which distinguish primitive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32.  19
    Punctual Categoricity and Universality.Rod Downey, Noam Greenberg, Alexander Melnikov, Keng Meng Ng & Daniel Turetsky - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (4):1427-1466.
    We describe punctual categoricity in several natural classes, including binary relational structures and mono-unary functional structures. We prove that every punctually categorical structure in a finite unary language is${\text {PA}}(0')$-categorical, and we show that this upper bound is tight. We also construct an example of a punctually categorical structure whose degree of categoricity is$0''$. We also prove that, with a bit of work, the latter result can be pushed beyond$\Delta ^1_1$, thus showing that punctually categorical structures can possess (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  38
    Coset-minimal groups.Oleg Belegradek, Viktor Verbovskiy & Frank O. Wagner - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (2-3):113-143.
    A totally ordered group G is called coset-minimal if every definable subset of G is a finite union of cosets of definable subgroups intersected with intervals with endpoints in G{±∞}. Continuing work in Belegradek et al. 1115) and Point and Wagner 261), we study coset-minimality, as well as two weak versions of the notion: eventual and ultimate coset-minimality. These groups are abelian; an eventually coset-minimal group, as a pure ordered group, is an ordered abelian group of finite regular rank. Any (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  49
    Model Companions of $T_{\rm Aut}$ for Stable T.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (3):129-142.
    We introduce the notion T does not omit obstructions. If a stable theory does not admit obstructions then it does not have the finite cover property . For any theory T, form a new theory $T_{\rm Aut}$ by adding a new unary function symbol and axioms asserting it is an automorphism. The main result of the paper asserts the following: If T is a stable theory, T does not admit obstructions if and only if $T_{\rm Aut}$ has a model (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35.  38
    A monotonicity theorem for dp-minimal densely ordered groups.John Goodrick - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1):221-238.
    Dp-minimality is a common generalization of weak minimality and weak o-minimality. If T is a weakly o-minimal theory then it is dp-minimal (Fact 2.2), but there are dp-minimal densely ordered groups that are not weakly o-minimal. We introduce the even more general notion of inp-minimality and prove that in an inp-minimal densely ordered group, every definable unary function is a union of finitely many continuous locally monotonic functions (Theorem 3.2).
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  53
    Expansions of o-Minimal Structures by Iteration Sequences.Chris Miller & James Tyne - 2006 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 47 (1):93-99.
    Let P be the ω-orbit of a point under a unary function definable in an o-minimal expansion ℜ of a densely ordered group. If P is monotonically cofinal in the group, and the compositional iterates of the function are cofinal at +\infty in the unary functions definable in ℜ, then the expansion (ℜ, P) has a number of good properties, in particular, every unary set definable in any elementarily equivalent structure is a disjoint union of open (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37.  29
    Model Companions of for Stable T.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (3):129-142.
    We introduce the notion T does not omit obstructions. If a stable theory does not admit obstructions then it does not have the finite cover property (nfcp). For any theory T, form a new theory by adding a new unary function symbol and axioms asserting it is an automorphism. The main result of the paper asserts the following: If T is a stable theory, T does not admit obstructions if and only if has a model companion. The proof involves (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38.  14
    Cohesive powers of structures.Valentina Harizanov & Keshav Srinivasan - 2024 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 63 (5):679-702.
    A cohesive power of a structure is an effective analog of the classical ultrapower of a structure. We start with a computable structure, and consider its effective power over a cohesive set of natural numbers. A cohesive set is an infinite set of natural numbers that is indecomposable with respect to computably enumerable sets. It plays the role of an ultrafilter, and the elements of a cohesive power are the equivalence classes of certain partial computable functions determined by the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  34
    Les beaux automorphismes.Daniel Lascar - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (1):55-68.
    Assume that the class of partial automorphisms of the monster model of a complete theory has the amalgamation property. The beautiful automorphisms are the automorphisms of models ofT which: 1. are strong, i.e. leave the algebraic closure (inT eq) of the empty set pointwise fixed, 2. are obtained by the Fraïsse construction using the amalgamation property that we have just mentioned. We show that all the beautiful automorphisms have the same theory (in the language ofT plus one unary function (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40.  20
    Counting finite models.Alan R. Woods - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (3):925-949.
    Let φ be a monadic second order sentence about a finite structure from a class K which is closed under disjoint unions and has components. Compton has conjectured that if the number of n element structures has appropriate asymptotics, then unlabelled (labelled) asymptotic probabilities ν(φ) (μ(φ) respectively) for φ always exist. By applying generating series methods to count finite models, and a tailor made Tauberian lemma, this conjecture is proved under a mild additional condition on the asymptotics of the number (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  13
    A wild model of linear arithmetic and discretely ordered modules.Petr Glivický & Pavel Pudlák - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (6):501-508.
    Linear arithmetics are extensions of Presburger arithmetic () by one or more unary functions, each intended as multiplication by a fixed element (scalar), and containing the full induction schemes for their respective languages. In this paper, we construct a model of the 2‐linear arithmetic (linear arithmetic with two scalars) in which an infinitely long initial segment of “Peano multiplication” on is ‐definable. This shows, in particular, that is not model complete in contrast to theories and that are known (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  34
    Remarks on the church-Rosser property.E. G. K. López-Escobar - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):106-112.
    A reduction algebra is defined as a set with a collection of partial unary functions (called reduction operators). Motivated by the lambda calculus, the Church-Rosser property is defined for a reduction algebra and a characterization is given for those reduction algebras satisfying CRP and having a measure respecting the reductions. The characterization is used to give (with 20/20 hindsight) a more direct proof of the strong normalization theorem for the impredicative second order intuitionistic propositional calculus.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  22
    The First-Order Theories of Dedekind Algebras.George Weaver - 2003 - Studia Logica 73 (3):337-365.
    A Dedekind Algebra is an ordered pair (B,h) where B is a non-empty set and h is an injective unary function on B. Each Dedekind algebra can be decomposed into a family of disjoint, countable subalgebras called configurations of the Dedekind algebra. There are N0 isomorphism types of configurations. Each Dedekind algebra is associated with a cardinal-valued function on omega called its configuration signature. The configuration signature of a Dedekind algebra counts the number of configurations in the decomposition of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  7
    Generalization of Shapiro’s theorem to higher arities and noninjective notations.Dariusz Kalociński & Michał Wrocławski - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (1):257-288.
    In the framework of Stewart Shapiro, computations are performed directly on strings of symbols (numerals) whose abstract numerical interpretation is determined by a notation. Shapiro showed that a total unary function (unary relation) on natural numbers is computable in every injective notation if and only if it is almost constant or almost identity function (finite or co-finite set). We obtain a syntactic generalization of this theorem, in terms of quantifier-free definability, for functions and relations relatively intrinsically computable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  30
    A Conjecture on Numeral Systems.Karim Nour - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (2):270-275.
    A numeral system is an infinite sequence of different closed normal -terms intended to code the integers in -calculus. Barendregt has shown that if we can represent, for a numeral system, the functions Successor, Predecessor, and Zero Test, then all total recursive functions can be represented. In this paper we prove the independancy of these three particular functions. We give at the end a conjecture on the number of unary functions necessary to represent all total (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  11
    The order types of termination orderings on monadic terms, strings and multisets.Ursula Martin & Elizabeth Scott - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):624-635.
    We consider total well-founded orderings on monadic terms satisfying the replacement and full invariance properties. We show that any such ordering on monadic terms in one variable and two unary function symbols must have order typeω,ω2orωω. We show that a familiar construction gives rise to continuum many such orderings of order typeω. We construct a new family of such orderings of order typeω2, and show that there are continuum many of these. We show that there are only four such (...))
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  15
    O-minimal analytic separation of sets in dimension 2.Andreas Fischer - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):130-138.
    We study the Hardy field associated with an o-minimal expansion of the real numbers. If the set of analytic germs is dense in the Hardy field, then we can definably analytically separate sets in , and we can definably analytically approximate definable continuous unary functions. A similar statement holds for definable smooth functions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  69
    On spectra of sentences of monadic second order logic with counting.E. Fischer & J. A. Makowsky - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):617-640.
    We show that the spectrum of a sentence ϕ in Counting Monadic Second Order Logic (CMSOL) using one binary relation symbol and finitely many unary relation symbols, is ultimately periodic, provided all the models of ϕ are of clique width at most k, for some fixed k. We prove a similar statement for arbitrary finite relational vocabularies τ and a variant of clique width for τ-structures. This includes the cases where the models of ϕ are of tree width at (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  39
    The lazy logic of partial terms.Raymond D. Gumb - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):1065-1077.
    The Logic of Partial Terms LPT is a strict negative free logic that provides an economical framework for developing many traditional mathematical theories having partial functions. In these traditional theories, all functions and predicates are strict. For example, if a unary function (predicate) is applied to an undefined argument, the result is undefined (respectively, false). On the other hand, every practical programming language incorporates at least one nonstrict or lazy construct, such as the if-then-else, but nonstrict (...) cannot be either primitive or introduced in definitional extensions in LPT. Consequently, lazy programming language constructs do not fit the traditional mathematical mold inherent in LPT. A nonstrict (positive free) logic is required to handle nonstrict functions and predicates. Previously developed nonstrict logics are not fully satisfactory because they are verbose in describing strict functions (which predominate in many programming languages), and some logicians find their semantics philosophically unpalatable. The newly developed Lazy Logic of Partial Terms LL is as concise as LPT in describing strict functions and predicates, and strict and nonstrict functions and predicates can be introduced in definitional extensions of traditional mathematical theories. LL is "built on top of" LPT, and, like LPT, admits only one domain in the semantics. In the semantics, for the case of a nonstrict unary function h in an LL theory T, we have $\models_T h(\perp) = y \longleftrightarrow \forall x(h(x) = y)$ , where $\perp$ is a canonical undefined term. Correspondingly, in the axiomatization, the "indifference" (to the value of the argument) axiom $h(\perp) = y \longleftrightarrow \forall x(h(x) = y)$ guarantees a proper fit with the semantics. The price paid for LL's naturalness is that it is tailored for describing a specific area of computer science, program specification and verification, possibly limiting its role in explicating classical mathematical and philosophical subjects. (shrink)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  13
    An Algebraic Proof of Completeness for Monadic Fuzzy Predicate Logic.Jun Tao Wang & Hongwei Wu - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-27.
    Monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MTL}$ is the weakest t-norm based residuated fuzzy logic, which is a $[0,1]$ -valued propositional logical system having a t-norm and its residuum as truth function for conjunction and implication. Monadic fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {mMTL\forall }$ that consists of the formulas with unary predicates and just one object variable, is the monadic fragment of fuzzy predicate logic $\mathbf {MTL\forall }$, which is indeed the predicate version of monoidal t-norm based logic $\mathbf {MTL}$. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 997