Results for 'Shoenfield'S. Conjecture'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  6
    The Embedding Problem for the Recursively Enumerable Degrees.Shoenfield'S. Conjecture - 1985 - In Anil Nerode & Richard A. Shore (eds.), Recursion theory. Providence, R.I.: American Mathematical Society. pp. 42--13.
  2.  8
    Σ2 Induction and infinite injury priority argument, Part I: Maximal sets and the jump operator.C. T. Chong & Yue Yang - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (3):797 - 814.
    Related Works: Part II: C. T. Chong, Yue Yang. $\Sigma_2$ Induction and Infinite Injury Priority Argument, Part II: Tame $\Sigma_2$ Coding and the Jump Operator. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, vol. 87, no. 2, 103--116. Mathematical Reviews : MR1490049 Part III: C. T. Chong, Lei Qian, Theodore A. Slaman, Yue Yang. $\Sigma_2$ Induction and Infinite Injury Priority Argument, Part III: Prompt Sets, Minimal Paries and Shoenfield's Conjecture. Mathematical Reviews : MR1818378.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  4
    Vaught’s conjecture for almost chainable theories.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):991-1005.
    A structure ${\mathbb Y}$ of a relational language L is called almost chainable iff there are a finite set $F \subset Y$ and a linear order $\,<$ on the set $Y\setminus F$ such that for each partial automorphism $\varphi $ of the linear order $\langle Y\setminus F, <\rangle $ the mapping $\mathop {\mathrm {id}}\nolimits _F \cup \varphi $ is a partial automorphism of ${\mathbb Y}$. By theorems of Fraïssé and Pouzet, an infinite structure ${\mathbb Y}$ is almost chainable iff the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  8
    Vaught's conjecture for monomorphic theories.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2019 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 170 (8):910-920.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  12
    The mathematical work of S. C. Kleene.J. R. Shoenfield & S. C. Kleene - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):8-43.
    §1. The origins of recursion theory. In dedicating a book to Steve Kleene, I referred to him as the person who made recursion theory into a theory. Recursion theory was begun by Kleene's teacher at Princeton, Alonzo Church, who first defined the class of recursive functions; first maintained that this class was the class of computable functions ; and first used this fact to solve negatively some classical problems on the existence of algorithms. However, it was Kleene who, in his (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  8
    Sharp Vaught's conjecture for some classes of partial orders.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2024 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 175 (4):103411.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    Vaught's conjecture for quite o-minimal theories.B. Sh Kulpeshov & S. V. Sudoplatov - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (1):129-149.
  8.  5
    Martin’s conjecture for regressive functions on the hyperarithmetic degrees.Patrick Lutz - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    We answer a question of Slaman and Steel by showing that a version of Martin’s conjecture holds for all regressive functions on the hyperarithmetic degrees. A key step in our proof, which may have applications to other cases of Martin’s conjecture, consists of showing that we can always reduce to the case of a continuous function.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  7
    Vaught's conjecture for weakly o-minimal theories of convexity rank 1.A. Alibek, B. S. Baizhanov, B. Sh Kulpeshov & T. S. Zambarnaya - 2018 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 169 (11):1190-1209.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  4
    Rado’s Conjecture and its Baire version.Jing Zhang - 2019 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 20 (1):1950015.
    Rado’s Conjecture is a compactness/reflection principle that says any nonspecial tree of height ω1 has a nonspecial subtree of size ℵ1. Though incompatible with Martin’s Axiom, Rado’s Conjecture turns out to have many interesting consequences that are also implied by certain forcing axioms. In this paper, we obtain consistency results concerning Rado’s Conjecture and its Baire version. In particular, we show that a fragment of PFA, which is the forcing axiom for Baire Indestructibly Proper forcings, is compatible (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  4
    Goldbach’s Conjecture as a ‘Transcendental’ Theorem.Francesco Panizzoli - 2019 - Axiomathes 29 (5):463-481.
    Goldbach’s conjecture, if not read in number theory, but in a precise foundation theory of mathematics, that refers to the metaphysical ‘theory of the participation’ of Thomas Aquinas, poses a surprising analogy between the category of the quantity, within which the same arithmetic conjecture is formulated, and the transcendental/formal dimension. It says: every even number is ‘like’ a two, that is: it has the form-of-two. And that means: it is the composition of two units; not two equal arithmetic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  21
    Chang’s Conjecture and weak square.Hiroshi Sakai - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (1-2):29-45.
    We investigate how weak square principles are denied by Chang’s Conjecture and its generalizations. Among other things we prove that Chang’s Conjecture does not imply the failure of \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\square_{\omega_1, 2}}$$\end{document}, i.e. Chang’s Conjecture is consistent with \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\square_{\omega_1, 2}}$$\end{document}.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  6
    Fraïssé’s conjecture in [math]-comprehension.Antonio Montalbán - 2017 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 17 (2):1750006.
    We prove Fraïssé’s conjecture within the system of Π11-comprehension. Furthermore, we prove that Fraïssé’s conjecture follows from the Δ20-bqo-ness of 3 over the system of Arithmetic Transfinite Recursion, and that the Δ20-bqo-ness of 3 is a Π21-statement strictly weaker than Π11-comprehension.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  5
    Menas’s Conjecture Revisited.Pierre Matet - 2023 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 29 (3):354-405.
    In an article published in 1974, Menas conjectured that any stationary subset of can be split in many pairwise disjoint stationary subsets. Even though the conjecture was shown long ago by Baumgartner and Taylor to be consistently false, it is still haunting papers on. In which situations does it hold? How much of it can be proven in ZFC? We start with an abridged history of the conjecture, then we formulate a new version of it, and finally we (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  11
    Tennant’s Conjecture for Self-Referential Paradoxes and its Classical Counterexample.Seungrak Choi - 2021 - Korean Journal of Logic 1 (24):1-30.
    In his paper, “On paradox without self-reference”, Neil Tennant proposed the conjecture for self-referential paradoxes that any derivation formalizing self-referential paradoxes only generates a looping reduction sequence. According to him, the derivation of the Liar paradox in natural deduction initiates a looping reduction sequence and the derivation of the Yablo's paradox generates a spiral reduction. The present paper proposes the counterexample to Tennant's conjecture for self-referential paradoxes. We shall show that there is a derivation of the Liar paradox (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  3
    Tennant’s Conjecture for Self-Referential Paradoxes and its Classical Counterexample.Seungrak Choi - 2021 - Korean Journal of Logic 1 (24):1-30.
    In his paper, “On paradox without self-reference”, Neil Tennant proposed the conjecture for self-referential paradoxes that any derivation formalizing self-referential paradoxes only generates a looping reduction sequence. According to him, the derivation of the Liar paradox in natural deduction initiates a looping reduction sequence and the derivation of the Yablo's paradox generates a spiral reduction. The present paper proposes the counterexample to Tennant's conjecture for self-referential paradoxes. We shall show that there is a derivation of the Liar paradox (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  5
    Chang’s Conjecture with $$square {omega _1, 2}$$ □ ω 1, 2 from an $$omega 1$$ ω 1 -Erdős cardinal.Itay Neeman & John Susice - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (7-8):893-904.
    Answering a question of Sakai :29–45, 2013), we show that the existence of an \-Erdős cardinal suffices to obtain the consistency of Chang’s Conjecture with \. By a result of Donder, volume 872 of lecture notes in mathematics. Springer, Berlin, pp 55–97, 1981) this is best possible. We also give an answer to another question of Sakai relating to the incompatibility of \ and \ \twoheadrightarrow \) for uncountable \.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  4
    Chang’s Conjecture with $$square {omega _1, 2}$$ □ ω 1, 2 from an $$omega 1$$ ω 1 -Erdős cardinal.Itay Neeman & John Susice - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (7-8):893-904.
    Answering a question of Sakai :29–45, 2013), we show that the existence of an ω1\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\omega _1$$\end{document}-Erdős cardinal suffices to obtain the consistency of Chang’s Conjecture with □ω1,2\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\square _{\omega _1, 2}$$\end{document}. By a result of Donder, volume 872 of lecture notes in mathematics. Springer, Berlin, pp 55–97, 1981) this is best possible. We also give an answer to another question of Sakai relating (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  10
    Kueker's conjecture for stable theories.Ehud Hrushovski - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):207-220.
    Kueker's conjecture is proved for stable theories, for theories that interpret a linear ordering, and for theories with Skolem functions. The proof of the stable case involves certain results on coordinatization that are of independent interest.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20.  4
    Variants of Kreisel’s Conjecture on a New Notion of Provability.Paulo Guilherme Santos & Reinhard Kahle - 2021 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 27 (4):337-350.
    Kreisel’s conjecture is the statement: if, for all$n\in \mathbb {N}$,$\mathop {\text {PA}} \nolimits \vdash _{k \text { steps}} \varphi (\overline {n})$, then$\mathop {\text {PA}} \nolimits \vdash \forall x.\varphi (x)$. For a theory of arithmeticT, given a recursive functionh,$T \vdash _{\leq h} \varphi $holds if there is a proof of$\varphi $inTwhose code is at most$h(\#\varphi )$. This notion depends on the underlying coding.${P}^h_T(x)$is a predicate for$\vdash _{\leq h}$inT. It is shown that there exist a sentence$\varphi $and a total recursive functionhsuch (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  9
    Vaught’s Conjecture Without Equality.Nathanael Leedom Ackerman - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (4):573-582.
    Suppose that $\sigma\in{\mathcal{L}}_{\omega _{1},\omega }$ is such that all equations occurring in $\sigma$ are positive, have the same set of variables on each side of the equality symbol, and have at least one function symbol on each side of the equality symbol. We show that $\sigma$ satisfies Vaught’s conjecture. In particular, this proves Vaught’s conjecture for sentences of $ {\mathcal{L}}_{\omega _{1},\omega }$ without equality.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  10
    Borel's conjecture in topological groups.Fred Galvin & Marion Scheepers - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):168-184.
    We introduce a natural generalization of Borel's Conjecture. For each infinite cardinal number $\kappa$, let ${\sf BC}_{\kappa}$ denote this generalization. Then ${\sf BC}_{\aleph_0}$ is equivalent to the classical Borel conjecture. Assuming the classical Borel conjecture, $\neg{\sf BC}_{\aleph_1}$ is equivalent to the existence of a Kurepa tree of height $\aleph_1$. Using the connection of ${\sf BC}_{\kappa}$ with a generalization of Kurepa's Hypothesis, we obtain the following consistency results: 1. If it is consistent that there is a 1-inaccessible cardinal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  16
    Quine’s conjecture on many-sorted logic.Thomas William Barrett & Hans Halvorson - 2017 - Synthese 194 (9):3563-3582.
    Quine often argued for a simple, untyped system of logic rather than the typed systems that were championed by Russell and Carnap, among others. He claimed that nothing important would be lost by eliminating sorts, and the result would be additional simplicity and elegance. In support of this claim, Quine conjectured that every many-sorted theory is equivalent to a single-sorted theory. We make this conjecture precise, and prove that it is true, at least according to one reasonable notion of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  24.  8
    Rado's Conjecture implies that all stationary set preserving forcings are semiproper.Philipp Doebler - 2013 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 13 (1):1350001.
    Todorčević showed that Rado's Conjecture implies CC*, a strengthening of Chang's Conjecture. We generalize this by showing that also CC**, a global version of CC*, follows from RC. As a corollary we obtain that RC implies Semistationary Reflection and, i.e. the statement that all forcings that preserve the stationarity of subsets of ω1 are semiproper.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  16
    Automorphisms of η-like computable linear orderings and Kierstead's conjecture.Charles M. Harris, Kyung Il Lee & S. Barry Cooper - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (6):481-506.
    We develop an approach to the longstanding conjecture of Kierstead concerning the character of strongly nontrivial automorphisms of computable linear orderings. Our main result is that for any η-like computable linear ordering, such that has no interval of order type η, and such that the order type of is determined by a -limitwise monotonic maximal block function, there exists computable such that has no nontrivial automorphism.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  9
    Kant's Conjectures: The Genesis of the Feminine.Amie Leigh Zimmer - 2022 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 36 (2):183-193.
    ABSTRACT Between the first two Critiques, Kant wrote what he called a “conjectural history” of the development of human freedom through a reading of Genesis. In the essay, reason itself is conceived of in terms of its “genesis,” and Kant primarily reads “Genesis” as an account of reason’s ascension or becoming. Just as humankind becomes itself through the Fall, so too does reason simultaneously come into its own. Adam indeed acts as a template for the conception of moral agency that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. 10. Craven's conjecture.J. S. Kelly - 1991 - Social Choice and Welfare 8 (3).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  19
    Wittgenstein’s Conjecture.Timm Lampert - 2019 - In Gabriele Mras, Paul Weingartner & Bernhard Ritter (eds.), Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics: Proceedings of the 41st International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 515-534.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  8
    Martin’s conjecture and strong ergodicity.Simon Thomas - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (8):749-759.
    In this paper, we explore some of the consequences of Martin’s Conjecture on degree invariant Borel maps. These include the strongest conceivable ergodicity result for the Turing equivalence relation with respect to the filter on the degrees generated by the cones, as well as the statement that the complexity of a weakly universal countable Borel equivalence relation always concentrates on a null set.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  4
    Results on Martin’s Conjecture.Patrick Lutz - 2021 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 27 (2):219-220.
    Martin’s conjecture is an attempt to classify the behavior of all definable functions on the Turing degrees under strong set theoretic hypotheses. Very roughly it says that every such function is either eventually constant, eventually equal to the identity function or eventually equal to a transfinite iterate of the Turing jump. It is typically divided into two parts: the first part states that every function is either eventually constant or eventually above the identity function and the second part states (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  11
    Rado's conjecture and presaturation of the nonstationary ideal on ω1.Qi Feng - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1):38-44.
    We prove that Rado's Conjecture implies that the nonstationary ideal on ω 1 is presaturated.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  7
    Kreisel's Conjecture with minimality principle.Pavel Hrubeš - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (3):976-988.
    We prove that Kreisel's Conjecture is true, if Peano arithmetic is axiomatised using minimality principle and axioms of identity (theory $PA_M $ )-The result is independent on the choice of language of $PA_M $ . We also show that if infinitely many instances of A(x) are provable in a bounded number of steps in $PA_M $ then there existe k ∈ ω s. t. $PA_M $ ┤ ∀x > k̄ A(x). The results imply that $PA_M $ does not prove (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  4
    'Goldbach's Conjecture Can Be Decided in One Minute': On an Alleged Problem for Intuitionism.Alexander George - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:187 - 189.
    Alexander George; Discussions: ‘Goldbach's Conjecture Can Be Decided in One Minute’: On an Alleged Problem for Intuitionism, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Soc.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    Rado's Conjecture and Ascent Paths of Square Sequences.Stevo Todorčević & Víctor Torres Pérez - 2014 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 60 (1-2):84-90.
    This is a continuation of our paper where we show that Rado's Conjecture can trivialize ‐sequences in some cases when ϑ is not necessarily a successor cardinal.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  7
    Non-bounding constructions.J. R. Shoenfield - 1990 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 50 (2):191-205.
    The object of this paper is to explain a certain type of construction which occurs in priority proofs and illustrate it with two examples due to Lachlan and Harrington. The proofs in the examples are essentially the original proofs; our main contribution is to isolate the common part of these proofs. The key ideas in this common part are due to Lachlan; we include several improvements due to Harrington, Soare, Slaman, and the author.Our notation is fairly standard. If X is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  14
    Vaught's conjecture for modules over a serial ring.Vera Puninskaya - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):155-163.
    It is proved that Vaught's conjecture is true for modules over an arbitrary countable serial ring. It follows from the structural result that every module with few models over a (countable) serial ring is ω-stable.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  9
    Vaught’s conjecture for superstable theories of finite rank.Steven Buechler - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 155 (3):135-172.
    In [R. Vaught, Denumerable models of complete theories, in: Infinitistic Methods, Pregamon, London, 1961, pp. 303–321] Vaught conjectured that a countable first order theory has countably many or 20 many countable models. Here, the following special case is proved.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38.  11
    Zilber's conjecture for some o-minimal structures over the reals.Ya'acov Peterzil - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 61 (3):223-239.
    We formulate an analogue of Zilber's conjecture for o-minimal structures in general, and then prove it for a class of o-minimal structures over the reals. We conclude in particular that if is an ordered reduct of ,<,+,·,ex whose theory T does not have the CF property then, given any model of T, a real closed field is definable on a subinterval of.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  5
    Relative Vaught's Conjecture for Some Meager Groups.Ludomir Newelski - 2007 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 48 (1):115-132.
    Assume G is a superstable locally modular group. We describe for any countable model M of Th(G) the quotient group G(M) / Gm(M). Here Gm is the modular part of G. Also, under some additional assumptions we describe G(M) / Gm(M) relative to G⁻(M). We prove Vaught's Conjecture for Th(G) relative to Gm and a finite set provided that ℳ(G) = 1 and the ring of pseudoendomorphisms of G is finite.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  6
    On Vaught’s Conjecture and finitely valued MV algebras.Antonio Di Nola & Giacomo Lenzi - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (3):139-152.
    We show that the complete first order theory of an MV algebra has equation image countable models unless the MV algebra is finitely valued. So, Vaught's Conjecture holds for all MV algebras except, possibly, for finitely valued ones. Additionally, we show that the complete theories of finitely valued MV algebras are equation image and that all ω-categorical complete theories of MV algebras are finitely axiomatizable and decidable. As a final result we prove that the free algebra on countably many (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  6
    A Note on Shoenfield's Unramified Forcing.Kyriakos Keremedis - 1991 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 37 (9-12):183-186.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  2
    Equivalence between Fraïssé’s conjecture and Jullien’s theorem.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 139 (1):1-42.
    We say that a linear ordering is extendible if every partial ordering that does not embed can be extended to a linear ordering which does not embed either. Jullien’s theorem is a complete classification of the countable extendible linear orderings. Fraïssé’s conjecture, which is actually a theorem, is the statement that says that the class of countable linear ordering, quasiordered by the relation of embeddability, contains no infinite descending chain and no infinite antichain. In this paper we study the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43.  3
    Schanuel's conjecture and free exponential rings.Angus Macintyre - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 51 (3):241-246.
  44.  8
    Chang's conjecture and powers of singular cardinals.Menachem Magidor - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):272-276.
  45.  14
    Orey Steven. Relative interpretations. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 7 , pp. 146–153.Feferman S., Kreisel G., and Orey S.. I-consistency and faithful interpretations. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, vol. 6 , pp. 52–63. [REVIEW]J. R. Shoenfield - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):627-627.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  9
    Vaught's conjecture for o-minimal theories.Laura L. Mayer - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):146-159.
  47.  9
    Chang’s conjecture, generic elementary embeddings and inner models for huge cardinals.Matthew Foreman - 2015 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 21 (3):251-269.
    We introduce a natural principleStrong Chang Reflectionstrengthening the classical Chang Conjectures. This principle is between a huge and a two huge cardinal in consistency strength. In this note we prove that it implies the existence of an inner model with a huge cardinal. The technique we explore for building inner models with huge cardinals adapts to show thatdecisiveideals imply the existence of inner models with supercompact cardinals. Proofs for all of these claims can be found in [10].1,2.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  9
    On Fraïssé’s conjecture for linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank.Alberto Marcone & Antonio Montalbán - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 160 (3):355-367.
    We prove that the maximal order type of the wqo of linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank under embeddability is φ2, the first fixed point of the ε-function. We then show that Fraïssé’s conjecture restricted to linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank is provable in +“φ2 is well-ordered” and, over , implies +“φ2 is well-ordered”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49.  2
    Weak Well Orders and Fraïssé’s Conjecture.Anton Freund & Davide Manca - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-16.
    The notion of countable well order admits an alternative definition in terms of embeddings between initial segments. We use the framework of reverse mathematics to investigate the logical strength of this definition and its connection with Fraïssé’s conjecture, which has been proved by Laver. We also fill a small gap in Shore’s proof that Fraïssé’s conjecture implies arithmetic transfinite recursion over $\mathbf {RCA}_0$, by giving a new proof of $\Sigma ^0_2$ -induction.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  6
    Some remarks on Schanuel's conjecture.Ricardo Bianconi - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 108 (1-3):15-18.
    Schanuel's Conjecture is the statement: if x 1 ,…,x n ∈ C are linearly independent over Q , then the transcendence degree of Q ,…, exp ) over Q is at least n . Here we prove that this is true if instead we take infinitesimal elements from any ultrapower of C , and in fact from any nonarchimedean model of the theory of the expansion of the field of real numbers by restricted analytic functions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000