An Argument for Fewer Clinical Trials
Hastings Center Report 46 (6):25-35 (2016)
Abstract
The volume of clinical research is increasing exponentially—far beyond our ability to process and absorb the results. Given this situation, it may be beneficial to consider reducing the flow at its source. In what follows, I will motivate and critically evaluate the following proposal: researchers should conduct fewer clinical trials. More specifically, I c onsider whether researchers should be permitted to conduct only clinical research of very high quality and, in turn, whether research ethics committees should prohibit all other, lower-quality research, even when it might appear to meet some minimal ethical standard. Following a close analysis of the social-value requirement of ethical clinical research, I argue that this proposal is defensible. The problem identified in this paper has two parts, quantity and quality, and some clarification is needed about the latter because “quality” is a highly contested term in the medical literature. When some scholars advocate for high-quality trials, they mean large-scale, simple, explanatory randomized controlled trials. Others, including myself, have defended a different characterization of high-quality research that tends more toward pragmatic trial design and the use of methods other than RCTs. Pragmatic trials aim to provide evidence that directly supports clinical decision-making in “usual” care settings. Unlike explanatory trials, which aim to abstract away from particular settings and patients, in the hopes of creating ideal conditions for the success of an intervention, pragmatic trials deliberately pursue knowledge of high applicability, through the use of representative subjects, clinically important questions, flexible treatment protocols, patient-oriented outcome measures, and so on. I see applicability as a marker of high-quality research. The context in which research is meant to be applied should be the context in which new interventions are evaluated.Author's Profile
My notes
Similar books and articles
Are explanatory trials ethical? Shifting the burden of justification in clinical trial design.Kirstin Borgerson - 2013 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34 (4):293-308.
Methodological quality and reporting of ethical requirements in phase III cancer trials.J. J. Tuech - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (5):251-255.
Clinical Trials Infrastructure as a Quality Improvement Intervention in Low- and Middle-Income Countries.Avram Denburg, Carlos Rodriguez-Galindo & Steven Joffe - 2016 - American Journal of Bioethics 16 (6):3-11.
End of Life Pediatric Research: What About the Ethics? [REVIEW]Danielle Laudy - 2009 - Journal of Academic Ethics 7 (1-2):87-91.
The Research Misconception.Maurie Markman - 2004 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (2):241-252.
A taxonomy of multinational ethical and methodological standards for clinical trials of therapeutic interventions.C. M. Ashton, N. P. Wray, A. F. Jarman, J. M. Kolman, D. M. Wenner & B. A. Brody - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (6):368-373.
Using empirical data to inform the ethical evaluation of placebo controlled trials.Jeremy Sugarman - 2004 - Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (1):29-35.
Clinical Trial Design for HIV Prevention Research: Determining Standards of Prevention.Liza Dawson & Sheryl Zwerski - 2015 - Bioethics 29 (5):316-323.
Selecting Subjects for Participation in Clinical Research: An Empirical Inquiry and Ethical Analysis.Charles Weijer - unknown
Methodological quality and reporting of ethical requirements in clinical trials.M. Ruiz-Canela - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (3):172-176.
Placebos and the UK medical research council — and the consumer perspective.Joan Box - 2004 - Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (1):95-101.
A Clinical Trials Manual From the Duke Clinical Research Institute: Lessons From a Horse Named Jim.Margaret B. Liu - 2010 - Wiley-Blackwell.
A European consistency for functioning of RECs? We just lost our chance.Marcin Waligora - 2013 - Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (6):408-409.
Reporting of informed consent, standard of care and post‐trial obligations in global randomized intervention trials: A systematic survey of registered trials.Jennifer M. O'neill Emma R. Cohen - 2009 - Developing World Bioethics 9 (2):74-80.
Analytics
Added to PP
2016-10-07
Downloads
155 (#82,935)
6 months
79 (#12,989)
2016-10-07
Downloads
155 (#82,935)
6 months
79 (#12,989)
Historical graph of downloads
Author's Profile
Citations of this work
Context is Needed When Assessing Fair Subject Selection.G. Owen Schaefer - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):20-22.
Institutions as an ethical locus of research prioritisation.Luke Gelinas, Holly Fernandez Lynch, Barbara Bierer & I. Glenn Cohen - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (12):816-818.
Redistributing Fair Subject Selection.Kirstin Borgerson - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):25-27.
Fair Inclusion and the Pursuit of Robustly Generalizable Clinically Relevant Knowledge.Ana S. Iltis - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (2):27-30.
References found in this work
A framework for risk-benefit evaluations in biomedical research.Annette Rid & David Wendler - 2011 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21 (2):141-179.
A Non-Paternalistic Model of Research Ethics and Oversight: Assessing the Benefits of Prospective Review.Alex John London - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (4):930-944.
Dealing With the Long-Term Social Implications of Research.Jeremy Sugarman, Dale E. Hammerschmidt, Christine Grady, Lisa Eckenwiler, Carol Levine & Alan Fleischman - 2011 - American Journal of Bioethics 11 (5):5-9.
Are explanatory trials ethical? Shifting the burden of justification in clinical trial design.Kirstin Borgerson - 2013 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 34 (4):293-308.